Skip to main content

Full text of "Modern Painters Vol. 3"

See other formats


SANTINIKETAN 

LIBRARY 

Cla$s 

vol. 3 

5I*e//No • 

* 4- 

Accession No 2t2^0 





M. r., 11 




lEbc “fflew Tllnivcrejfl Xibratg 


MODERN PAINTERS 


VOL. Ill 



THE UNIVERSAL EDITION OF 
JOHN RUSKIN’S WORKS 


Modern Painters, 5 vols. With 315 Illustrations 

and Plates, and i Coloured Plate. 

The Stones of Venice, 3 vols. With 173 Illustra- 
tions and Plates, and 7 Coloured Plates. 

The Seven Lamps of Architecture. With 14 
Plates. 

Lectures on Architecture and Painting. V^iih 23 
Illustrations. 

Elements of Drawing. With 48 Illustrations. 
“Unto this Last.’^ 

The Two Paths : On Decoration and Manufacture. 
With 2 Idates. 

The Political Economy of Art, subsequently called 
A Joy for Ever. 

Selections from His Writings. 

The Illustrations and Plales are throughout 
printed on Art Paper. 

The other Works to follow in course. 





MODER'N PAINTERS 


By 

JOHN RUSKiN 


VOLUME III 

CONTAINING 

PART IV 

®f Bftang irblngs 



LONDON 

GEORGE ROUTLEbGE & SONS Limite 
New York: E. P. DUTTON & CO 



Kiohakd &, Sons, Limitk7>, 

BREAD STREET ITIT.T., K.C'., AND 
BUNGAY, SUFFOLK.’ 



PREFACE 


As this preface is nearly all about myself, no one 
need take the trouble of reading it, unless he hap- 
pens to be desirous of knowing — what I, at least, 
am bound to state — the circumstances which have 
caused the long delay of the work, as well as the 
alterations which will be noticed in its form. 

The first and second volumes were written to 
check, as far as I could, the attacks upon Turne” t 
which prevented the public from honouring his 
genius, at the time when his power was greatest. 
The chccli was partially given, but too late; Turner 
waj^ jeized by painful illness not long after the 
second volume appeared; his works, towards the 
close of the year 1845, showed a conclusive failure 
of power; and I saw that nothing remained for me 
to write, but his epitaph. 

The critics had done their proper and appointed 
work; they had embittered, more than those who 
did not know Turner intimately could have believed 
possible, the closing years of his life; and had 
blinded the world in general (as it appears ordained 
by Fate that the world always shall be blinded) to 
the presence of a great spirit amo»g them, till the 
hour of its departure. With them, and their success- 
ful work, I had nothing more to do; the account of 
gain and los^, of gifts and gratitude, between Turner 
and his countrymen, was for ever closed. He could 
only be left his quiet death at Chelsea — the sun 
upon his face; they to dispose a length of funeral 
through Ludgate, and bury, with threefold honour, 
his body in St Paul’s, his pictures at Charing Cross, 
and his purposes in Chancery. But with respect to 
the illustration and preservation of those of his 
works which remained unburied, I felt that gmuch 



Vi PREFACE 

might yet be done, if I could at all succeed .fc prov- 
ing that these works had some nobleness !n them,, 
and were worth preservation. I pursued my task, 
therefore, as I had at first proposed, with this only 
difference in method — ^that instead of writing in con- 
tinued haste, such as I had been forced into at first 
by the urgency of the occasion, I set myself to do 
the work as well as I could, and to collect materials 
for the complete examination of the canons of art 
received among us. 

I have now given ten years of my life to the 
single purpose of enabling myself to judge rightly of 
art, and spent them in labour as earnest and con- 
tinuous as men usually undertake to gain position, 
accumulate fortune. It is true, that the public 
still call me an ‘ amateur *; nor have I ever been 
able to persuade them that it was possible^ to work 
steadily and hard with any other motive than that 
of gaining bread, or to give up a fixed numljei; of 
hours every day to the furtherance of an object un- 
connected with personal interests. I have, however, 
given up so much of life to this object; earnestly 
desiring to ascertain, and be able to teach, the truth 
respecting art; and also knowing that this truth 
was, by time and labour, definitely ascertainable. 

It is an idea too frequently entertained, by persons 
who are not much interested in art, that there are 
no laws of right or wrong concerning it; and that 
the best art is that which pleases most widely. Hence 
the constant allegation of ‘ dogmatism ’ against any 
one who states unhesitatingfy either preference or 
principle, respecting pictures. There are, however, 
laws of truth and right in painting, jusf as fixed as 
those of harmony in music, or of affinity in chemistry. 
Those laws are perfectly ascertainable by labour, 
and ascertainable no otherwise. It is as ridiculous 
for any one to speak positively about painting who 
has not given a great part of his life to its study, 
as it would be for a person who had never studied 
chemistry to give a lecture on affinities of elements; 
but it is also as ridiculous for a person to speak 



PREFACE 


vii 


hesitatiiigly about laws of painting who has con- 
scientiolely given his time to their ascertainment, 
‘as it would be for Mr Faraday to announce in a 
dubious manner that iron had an affinity for oxygen, 
and to put the question to the vote of his audience 
whether it had or not. Of course there are many 
things, in all stages of knowledge, which cannot be 
dogmatically stated; and it will be found, by any 
candid reader, either of what I have before written, 
or of this book, that, in many cases, I am not dog- 
matic. The phrase, ‘ I think so ’, or, ‘it seems so 
to me ’, will be met with continually; and I pray 
the reader to believe that I use such expression 
always in seriousness, never as matter of form. 

It may perhaps be thought that, considering the 
not very elaborate structure of the following volumes,^ 
they might have been finished sooner. But it will 
be founfl, on reflection, that the ranges of inquiry 
engaged in demanded, even for their slight investi- 
gaficm, time and pains which are quite unrepresented 
in the result. It often required a week or two’s hard 
walking to determine some geological problem, now 
dismissed in an unnoticed sentence; and in con- 
stantly needed examination and thought, prolonged 
during many days in the picture gallery, to form 
opinions which the reader may suppose to be dictated 
by caprice, and will hear only to dispute. 

A more serious disadvantage, resulting from the 
necessary breadth of subject, w^as the chance of 
making mistakes in minor and accessory points. 
For the labour of a critic who sincerely desires to be 
just, extends into more fields than it is possible for 
any single hand to furrow straightly. Ho has to 
take some ]!ote of many physical sciences; of optics, 
geometry, gftology, botany, and anatomy; he must 
acquaint himself with the works of all great artists, 
and with the temper and history of the times in 
which they lived; he must be a fair metaphysician, 
and a careful observer of the phenomena of natural 
scenery. It is not possible to extend the range of 
work thus widely, without running the chance of 



PREFACE 


viii 

occasionally making mistakes; and if I cfirefully 
guarded against that chance, I should be compelled 
both to shorten my powers of usefulness in many 
directions, and to lose much time over what work 
I undertook. All that I can secure, therefore, is 
rightness in main points and main tendencies; for 
it is perfectly possible to protect oneself against 
small errors, and yet to make great and final errprs 
in the sum of work : on the other hand, it is equally 
possible to fall into many small errors, and yet be 
right in tendency all the while, and entirely right 
in the end. In this respect, some men may be 
compared to careful travellers, who neither stumble 
at stones, nor slip in sloughs, but have, from the 
beginning of their journey to its close, chosen the 
'Vrong road; and others to those who, however 
slipping or stumbling at the 'wayside, have yet their 
eyes fixed on the true gate and goal (stilmbling, 
perhaps, even the more because they have), and will 
not fail of reaching them. Such are assuredly 1?iie 
safer guides : he who follows them may avoid their 
slips, and be their companion in attainment. 

Although, therefore, it is not possible but that, in 
the discussion of so many subjects as are necessarily 
introduced in the following pages, here and there a 
chance should arise of minor mistake or misconcep- 
tion, the reader need not be disturbed by the de- 
tection of any such. He will find always that they 
do not afiect the matter mainly in hand. 

I refer especiallv in these remarks to the chapters 
on Classical and Mediseval Landscape. It is certain, 
that in many respects, the views there stated must 
be inaccurate or incomplete; for how should it be 
otherwise when the subject is one whose 'proper dis- 
cussion would require knowledge of the qntire history 
of two great ages of the world? But I am well 
assured that the suggestions in those chapters are 
useful; and that even if, after farther study of the 
subject, the reader should find cause to differ with 
me in this or the other speciality, he 'will yet thank 
me for ^helping him to a certain length in the in- 



PREFACE 


IX 


vestigatioto, and confess, perhaps, that he could not 
at last hve been right, if I had not first ventured 
to be wrong. 

And of one thing he may be certified, that any 
error I fall into will not be in an illogical deduction : 
I may mistake the meaning of a symbol, or the angle 
of a rock-cleavage, but not draw an inconsequent 
conchision. I state this, because it has often been 
said that I am not logical, by persons who do not 
so much as know what logic means. Next to imagin- 
ation, the power of perceiving logical relation is one 
of the rarest among men : certainly, of those with 
whom I have conversed, I have found always ten 
who had deep feeling, quick wit, or extended know- 
ledge, for one who could set down a syllogism with- 
out a flaw; and for ten who could set down a syllo- 
gism, only one who could entirely understand that a 
square ha^ four sides. Even as I am sending these 
sheets to press, a work is put into my hand, written 
to pfbfe (I would, from the depth of my heart, it 
could prove) that there was no ground for what I 
said in The Stones of Venice respecting the logical 
probability of the continuity of evil. It seems 
learned, temperate, thoughtful, everything in feel- 
ing and aim that a book should be, and yet it begins 
with this sentence : 

‘ The question cited in our preface : “ Why not infinite good 
out of infinite evil ? ” must be taken to imply — for it else can 
have no weight — that in order to the production of infinite 
good, the existence of infiiiit^evil is indispegsable.' 

So, if I had said that there was no reason why 
honey should not be sucked out of a rock, and oil 
out of a flint;f rock, the writer would have told me 
this sentence jpust be taken to imply — for it else 
could have no weight — ^that in order to the produc- 
tion of honey, the existence of rocks is indispensable. 
No less intense and marvellous are the logical errors 
into which our best writers are continually falling, 
owing to the notion that laws of logic will help 
them better than common sense. Whereas^ any 



X 


PREFACE? 


man who can reason at all, does it instjftictively, 
and takes leaps over intermediate syllogisms by the 
score, yet never misses his footing at the end of the 
leap; but he who cannot instinctively argue, might 
as well, with the gout in both feet, try to follow a 
chamois hunter by the help of crutches, as to follow, 
by the help of syllogism, a person who has the right 
use of his reason. I should not, however, have 
thought it necessary to allude to this common charge 
against my writings, but that it happens to confirm 
some views I have long entertained, and which the 
reader will find glanced at in their proper place, 
respecting the necessity of a more practically logical 
education for our youth. Of other various charges I 
, need take no note, because they are always answered 
the one by the other. The complaint made against 
me to-day for being narrow and exclusive, is met 
to-morrow by indi'mation that I shoufd admire 
schools whose characters cannot be reconciled;^ and 
the assertion of one critic, that I am always con- 
tradicting myself, is balanced by the vexation of 
another, at my ten years’ obstinacies in error. 

I once intended the illustrations to these volumes 
to be more numerous and elaborate, but the art of 
photography now enables any reader to obtain as 
many memoranda of the facts of nature as he needs; 
and, in the course of my ten years’ pause, I have 
formed plans for the representation of some of the 
works of Turner on their own scale ; so that it 
would have heefi quite useless to spend time in re- 
ducing drawings to the size 6f this page, which were 
afterwards to be engraved of their own size I 
have therefore here only given illustrg,tions enough 
to enable the reader, who has not access to the works 
of Turner, to understand the princi^es laid down 
in the text, and apply them to such art as may be 
within his reach. And I owe sincere thanks to the 

1 I should be very grateful to proprietors of x)ictures or 
drawings by Turner, if they would send me lists of the works 
in their possession ; as I am desirous of forming a systematic 
catalogue of all his works. 



1>REFACE 


XI 


various Agra vers who have worked with me, for the 
zeal and care with which they have carried oiit the 
requirements in each case, and overcome difficulties 
of a nature often widely differing from those involved 
by their habitual practice. I would not make in- 
vidious distinction, wljere all have done well; but 
may perhaps be permitted to point, as examples of 
what I mean, to the 3rd and 6th Plates in this 
volume (the 6th being left unlettered in order not 
to injure the effect of its ground), in which Mr. Le 
Keux and Mr. Armytage have exactly facsimiled, in 
line engraving, drawings of mine made on a grey 
ground touched with white, and have given even the 
loaded look of the body colour. The power of thus 
imitating actual touches of colour with pure lines 
will be, I believe, of great future importance in 
rendering. Turner’s work on a large scale. As for 
the merit or demerit of these or other drawings of 
my which I am obliged now for the sake of 

illustration often to engrave, I believe I could speak 
of it impartially, and should unreluctantly do so; 
but I leave, as most readers will think I ought, such 
judgment to them, merely begging them to remem- 
ber that there are two general principles to be kept 
in mind in examining the drawings of any writer on 
art : the first, that they ought at least to show such 
ordinary skill in draughtsmanship, as to prove that 
the writer knows what the good qualities of drawing 
are; the second, that they are never to be expected 
to equal, in either exec^jtion or conctsption, the work 
of accomidished artists — for the simple reason, that 
in order to do anything thoroughly well, the whole 
mind, and the whole available time, must be given 
to that single art. It is probable, for reasons which 
will be noted fti the following pages, that the critical 
and executive faculties are in great part independent 
of each other; so that it is nearly as great an ab- 
surdity to require of any critic that he should equal 
in execution even the work Tvhich he condemns, as 
to require of the audience which hisses a piece of 
vocal music that they should instantly chant^it in 



4i PREFACE? 

truer harmony themselves. But whethejr this be 
true or not (it is at least untrue to this e^Sent, that 
a certain power of drawing is indispensable to the 
critic of art), and supposing that the executive and 
critical powers always exist in some correspondent 
degree in the same person, still they cannot be 
cultivated to the same extent. The attention re- 
quired for the development of a theory is necessarily 
withdrawn from the design of a drawing, and the 
time devoted to the realization of a form is lost to 
the solution of a problem. Choice must at last be 
made between one and the other power, as the princi- 
pal aim of life ; and if the painter should find it neces- 
sary sometimes to explain one of his pictures in 
words, or the writer to illustrate his meaning with a 
drawing, the skill of the one need not be doubted 
because his logic is feeble, nor the sense of^the other 
because his pencil is listless. 

As, however, it is sometimes alleged by tfeew op- 
ponents of my principles, that I have never done 
anything^ it is proper that the reader should know 
exactly the amount of work for which I am answer- 
able in these illustrations. When an example is 
given from any of the works of Turner, it is either 
etched by myself from the original drawing, or en- 
graved from a drawing of mine, translating Turner’s 
work out of colour into black and white, as, for 
instance, the frontispiece to the fourth volume. 
When a plate is inscribed as ‘ after ’ such and such 
a master, I have always my|jelf made the drawing, 
in black and white, from the original picture; as, 
for instance, Plate XI in this volume. If it has 
been made from a previously existing engraving, it 
is inscribed with the name of the first engraver at 
the left-hand lowest corner; as, for instance, Plate 
XVIIl in Vol. IV. Outline etchings are either by 
my own hand on the steel, as Plate XII here, and 
XX, XXI in Vol. IV.; or copies from my pen draw- 
ings, etched by Mr Boys, with a fidelity for which I 
sincerely thank him; one, Plate XXII, Vol. IV, is 
both drawn and etched by Mr Boys from an old 



yREFACE xiii 

engraving. Most of the other illustrations are en- 
graved ilpm my own studies from nature. The 
coloured Rate (VII in this volume) is from a drawing 
executed with great skill by my assistant, Mr J. J. 
Laing, from MSS. in the British Museum; and the 
lithography of it has been kindly superintended by 
Mr Henry Shaw, whose renderings of mediseval orna- 
ments stand, as far as I know, quite unrivalled in 
modern art. The two woodcuts of mediseval design. 
Figs. 1 and 3, are also from drawings by Mr liaing, 
admirably cut by Miss Byfieid. I use this word 
‘ admirably \ not with reference to mere delicacy of 
execution, which can usually be had for money, but 
to the perfect fidelity of facsimile, which is in general 
not to be had for money, and by which Miss Byfield 
has saved me all trouble wHh respect to the numer- 
ous woodcuts in the fourth volume; first, by her 
excellent ^renderings of various portions of Albert 
Durer’s woodcuts; and, secondly, by reproducing, 
to tlj^y; last dot or scratch, my owm pen diagrams, 
drawn in general so roughly that few wood-engravers 
would have condescended to cut them with care, and 
yet always involving some points in which care v^as 
indispensable. One or two changes have been per- 
mitted in the arrangement of the book, which make 
the text in these volumes not altogether a symmetri- 
cal continuation of that in former ones. Thus, I 
thought it hotter to put the numbers of paragraphs 
always at the left-hand side of the page; and as 
the summaries, in small type, appeared to me for 
the most part cumbrous ^ind useless, i have banished 
them. 1 am not sorry thus to carry out my 
own principle of the sacrifice of architectural or 
constructive symmetry to practical service. The 
plates are, in a somewhat unusual way, numbered 
consecutively through the two volumes, as I intend 
them to be also through the fifth. This plan saves 
much trouble in references. 

I have only to express, in conclusion, my regret 
that it has been impossible to finish the work within 
the limits first proposed. Having, of late, found my 



xiv PREFAC;p 

designs always requiring enlargement in nrocess of 
execution, I will take care, in future, to sy no limits 
whatsoever to any good intentions. In tne present 
instance I trust the reader will pardon me, as the 
later efforts of our schools of art have necessarily 
introduced many new topics of discussion. 

And so I wish him heartily a happy New Year. 

Denmark Hill, Jan. 1856. 



Vable of contents 

PART IV 


OF MANY THINGS 

CHAPTEK PAUE 

’ I : Of the received Opinions touching the 

‘ Grand Style ’ 1 

II : Of Realization 17 

III : Of the Real Nature of Greatness of Style 25 

IV : Of the False Ideal : First, Religious 48 

V : Of the False Ideal : Secondly, Profane... 67 

VI : Of the True Ideal : First, Purist 77 

VII : Of the True Ideal : Secondly, Naturalist. 85 
VIII: Of the True Ideal : Thirdly, Grotesque.. 101 

IX : Of Finish 119 

Of the Use of Pictures 136 

XI : Of the Novelty of Landscape 158 

XTI : Of the Pathetic Fallacy 166 

XIII : Of Classical Landscape 184 

XIV : Of Mediteval Landscape : First, the 

Fields 209 

XV : Of Mediaeval Landscape : Secondly, the 

Rocks 251 

XVI : Of Modern Landscape 271 

XVII : The Moral of Landscape 306 

XVIII : Of the Teachers of Turner 337 

APPENDIX 

I : Claude’s Tree-drawing 365 

II : German Philosophy 367 

III : Plagiarism 369 




LIST OF ILLUSTRATIONS 


Plato 

Lake, Land, and Cloud . 

I True and False Griffins . 

II Drawing of Tree-bark 

III Strength of old Pino 

IV Pamihpation according to ) 

Claude . . . . \ 

V ^•od and bad Tree-drawing 

VI Foreground Leafage 
VII Botany of the Thirteenth Cen- ) 
tury {Coloured) . . . j 

VIII The Growth of Leaves . 

IX Botany of the Fourteenth ) 
Century . . . j' 

X Geology of the Middle Ages . 
XI Latest Purism 
XII The Shoi es of Wharfe . 

XIII First Mountain-Naturalism 

XIV The liOmbard Ai)ennine . 

XV St. George of the Seawited 

XVI Early Naturalism . 

XVII Advanced Naturalism 


. 5LL| B. 


Drawn by 

Facing 

page 

The Author. Front. 

The Author 

. 110 

FariouA 

. 120 

The Author 

. 128 

Claude. 

. 130 

Turner and Con 

_ 

stable 

. 132 

The Author . 

. 133 

M issal- Painters 

. 226 

The Author . 

. 227 

Missa l-Paihi firs 

. 228 

J^eonardo, d^c. 
Raphael 

262 

. 344 

J. IV. M. Turner 

. 346 

Jlasaccio 

. 347 

The Author . 

. 348 

The A^ thor . 

. 350 

Titian 

. 352 

Tiutoret 

. 354 


. 345 


xvii 




MODERN PAINTERS 


PAKT IV 
OF MANY THINGS 
CHAPTER I 

OF THE RECEIVED OPINIONS TOUCHING THE 
‘ GRAND STYLE ' 

§ 1. In taking up the clue of an inquiry, now 
intWiriitted for nearly ten years, it may be well to 
do as a traveller would, who had to recommence an 
interrupted journey in a guideless country; and, as- 
cending, as it were, some little hill beside our road, 
note how far we have already advanced, and what 
pleasantest ways we may choose for farther progress, 
I endeavoured, in the beginning of the first volume, 
to divide the sources of pleasure open to us in Art 
into certain groups, which might conveniently be 
studied in succession. After some preliminary dis- 
cussion, it was concluded (Part I, Chap. Ill, § 86) 
that those groups wc^, in the mUin, three*,, con- 
sisting, first, of the pleasures taken in perceiving 
simple resemblance to Nature (Ideas of Truth); 
secondly, of •the pleasures taken in the beauty of the 
things chosen to be painted (Ideas of Beauty) ; and, 
lastly, of pleasures taken in the meanings and rela- 
tions of these things (Ideas of Relation), 

The first volume, treating of the ideas of Truth, 
was chiefly occupied with an inquiry into the .various 
success with which different artists had represented 
the facts of Nature — an inquiry necessarily con- 

M. P., III. B* 



RECEIVED OPINIONS TOUCHING [part iv 

ducted very imperfectly, owing to the jvant of 
pictorial illustration. 

The second volume merely opened the inquiry into 
the nature of ideas of Beauty and Relation, by analys- 
ing (as far as I was able to do so) the two faculties 
of the human mind which mainly seized such ideas; 
namely, the contemplative and imaginative faculties. 

It remains for us to examine the various suc.cess 
of artists, especially of the great landscape-painter 
whose works have been throughout our principal sub- 
ject, in addressing these faculties of the human mind, 
and to consider who among them has conveyed the 
noblest ideas of beauty, and touched the deepest 
sources of thought. 

§ 2. I do not intend, however, now to pursue the 
inquiry in a method so laboriously systematic; for 
the subject may, it seems to me, be more usefully 
treated by^ pursuing the different questions which rise 
out of it just as they occur to us, without too great 
scrupulousness in marking connections, or in^gling 
on sequences. Much time is wasted by human 
beings, in general, on establishment of systems; and 
it often takes more labour to master the intricacies 
of an artificial connection, than to remember the 
separate facts which are so carefully connected. I 
suspect that system-makers, in general, are not of 
much more use, each in his owm domain, than, in 
that of Pomona, the old women who tie cherries upon 
sticks, for the more convenient portableness of the 
same. To cultivate well, and choose well, your 
cherries, is of some importsmee; but if they can 
be had in their ovm -wild way of clustering about 
their crabbed stalk, it is a better connection for 
them than any other; and, if they canfiot, then, so 
that they be not bruised, it makes to a boy of a 
practical disposition, not much difference whether 
tie gets them by handfuls, or in beaded symmetry on 
the exalting stick. I purpose, therefore, hencefor- 
ward to trouble myself little with sticks or twine, but 
to arrange my chapters with a view to convenient 
referej^ce, rather than to any careful division of sub- 



CHAP. I] THE ' GRAND STYDE " . S 

jeots, aiM to follow out, in any by-ways that may 
open, onr right hand or left, whatever question it 
seems useful at any moment to settle. 

§ 3. And, in the outset, I find myself met by one 
which I ought to have touched upon before — one of 
especial interest in the present state of the Arts. 
I have said that the art is greatest which includes the 
greatest ideas ; but I have not endeavoured to define 
the nature of this greatness in the ideas themselves. 
We speak of great truths, of great beauties, great 
thoughts. What is it which makes one truth greater 
than another, one thought greater than another? 
This question is, I repeat, of peculiar importance at 
the present time; for, during a period now of some 
hundred and fifty years, all writers on Art who have 
pretended to eminence, have insisted much on a 
supposed distinction between what they call the 
Great and the Low Schools; using the terms ‘ High 
Art ‘ Great or Ideal Style and other such, as 
descriptive of a certain noble manner of painting, 
which it was desirable that all students of Art should 
be early led to reverence and adopt; and character- 
izing as ‘ vulgar or ‘ low ’, or ‘ realist another 
manner of painting and conceiving, which it was 
equally necessary that ail students should be taught 
to avoid. 

But lately this established teaching, never very in- 
telligible, has been gravely called in question. The 
advocates and self-supposed practisers of ‘ High Art * 
are beginning to be lookq^ upon with doubt, and their 
peculiar phraseology to be treated with even a certain 
degree of ridicule. And other forms of Art are partly 
developed arri^ng us, which do not pretend to be 
high, but rather to be strong, healthy, and humble. 
This matter of ‘ highness ’ in Art, therefore deserves 
our most careful consideration. Has it been, or is 
it, a true highness, a true princeliness, or only a show 
of it, consisting in courtly manners and robes of 
state? Is it rocky height or cloudy height, adamant 
or vapour, on which the sun of praise so long has 
risen and set? It will be well at once to consider ibis. 



4 BEOEIVfiD OPINIONS TOUCHING [partiv 

§ 4. And first, let us get, as quickly as n^y be, at 
tlie exact meaning with which the advocates of 
‘ High Art ’ use that somewhat obscure and figurative 
term. 

I do not know that the principles in question are 
anywhere more distinctly expressed than in two 
papers in The Idler^ written by Sir Joshua Reynolds, 
of course under the immediate sanction of Johneon; 
and which may thus be considered as the utterance 
of the views then held upon the subject by the artists 
of chief skill, and critics of most sense, arranged in 
a form so brief and clear, as to admit of their being 
brought before the public for a morning’s entertain- 
ment. I cannot, therefore, it seems to me, do better 
than quote these two letters, or at least the import- 
ant parts of them, examining the exact meaning of 
each passage as it occurs. There are, in all, in The 
Idler three letters on painting. Nos. 76, 79, and 82; 
of these, the first is directed only against the ^jpper- 
tinences of pretended connoisseurs, and is as notable 
for its faithfulness, as for its wit, in the description 
of the several modes of criticism in an artificial and 
ignorant state of society : it is only, therefore, in 
the two last papers that we find the expression of 
the doctrines which it is our business to examine. 

No. 79 (Saturday, Oct. 20th, 1759) begins, after a 
short preamble, with the following passage : 

Amongst the painters, and the writers on painting, there is 
one maxim universally admitted and continually inculcated. 
Imitate nature is^ the invariablefrnle : but I know none who 
have explained in what manner th’s rule is to be understood ; 
the sequence of which is, that every one takes it in the most 
obvious sense, that objects are represented naturally when they 
have such relief that they seem real. It majr appear strange, 
perhaps, to hear this sense of the rule disputed ; but it must 
be considered, that, if the excellency of a painter consisted 
only in this kind of imitation, Painting nmst lose its rank, and 
be no longer considered as a liberal art, and sister to Poetry, 
this imitation being merely mechanical, in which the slowest 
intellect is always sure to succeed best; for the painter of 
genius cannot stoop to drudgery, in which the understanding 
has no part ; and what pretence has the art to claim kindred 
with^poetry but by its power over the imagination? To this 



cHAt»*i] THE ‘GRAND STYLE .V $ 

power th« painter of genius directs biiu ; in this ^ sense , he 
studies nwure, and often arrives at his end, even by being 
unnatural in the confined sense of the word. 

The grand style of painting requires this minute attention 
to be carefully avoided, and must be kept as separate from it 
as the style of poetry from that of history. (Poetical orna- 
ments destroy that air of truth and plainness which ought to 
characterize history ; but the very being of poetry consists in 
departing from this plain narrative, and adopting every orna- 
ment that will warm the imagination i.) To desire to see the 
excellencies of each style united — to mingle the Dutch with 
the Italian school, is to join contrarieties, which cannot subsist 
together, and which destroy the efiBcacy of each other. 

§ 5. We find, first, from this interesting passage, 
that the writer considers the Dutch and Italian 
masters as severally representative of the low and 
high schools; next, that he considers the Dutch 
painters as excelling in a mechanical imitation, ‘ in 
which the slowest intellect is always sure to succeed 
best^ and, thirdly, that he considers the Italian 
painJers as excelling in a style which corresponds to 
that of imaginative poetry in literature, and which 
has an exclusive right to be called the grand style. 

I wish that it were in my power entirely to concur 
with the writer, and to enforce this opinion thus 
distinctly stated. I have never been a zealous parti- 
san of the Dutch School, and should rejoice in claim- 
ing Reynolds’s authority for the assertion, that their 
manner was one ‘ in which the slowest intellect is 
always sure to succeed best But before his 
authority can be so claii^ed, we must^observe exactly 
the meaning of the assertion itself, and separate it 
from the company of some others not perhaps so 
admissible, Eirst, I say we must observe Reynolds’s 
exact meaning, for (though the assertion may at first 
appear singular) a man who uses accurate language 
is always more liable to misinterpretation than one 

1 I have put this sentence in a parenthesis, because it is incon- 
sistent with the rest of the statement, and with the general 
teaching of the paper ; since that which ‘ attends only to the 
invariable ’ cannot certainly adopt ‘ every ornament that will 
warm the imagination.’ ^ • 



*6 BECEIVIII) OPINIOITS TOUCHING [part iv 

who is careless in his expressions. We ma# assume 
that the latter means very nearly what wk at first 
suppose him to mean, for words which have been 
uttered without thought may be received without 
examination. But when a writer or speaker may be 
fairly supposed to have considered his expressions 
carefully, and, after having revolved a number of 
terms in his mind, to have chosen the one which 
exactly means the thing he intends to say, we may be 
assured that what costs him time to select, will 
require from us time to understand, and that we shall 
do him wrong, unless we pause to reflect how the 
word which he has actually employed differs from 
other words which it seems he might have em- 
ployed. It thus constantly happens that persons 
themselves unaccustomed to think clearly, or speak 
correctly, misunderstand a logical and careful writer, 
and are actually in more danger of being misled by 
language which is measured and precise, tl^ by 
that which is loose and inaccurate. 

§ 6. Now, in the instance before us, a person not 
accustomed to good writing might very rashly con- 
clude, that when Reynolds spoke of the Dutch School 
as one ‘ in which the slowest intellect was sure to 
succeed best he meant to say that every success- 
ful Dutch painter was a fool. We have no right to 
take his assertion in that sense. He says, the 
slowest intellect. We have no right to assume that 
he meant the wcahest. For it is true, that in order 
to succeed in the Dutch stjjile, a man has need of 
qualities of mind eminently deliberate and sustained. 
He must be possessed of patience rather than of 
power; and must feel no weariness in rfjontemplating 
the expression of a single thought for several months 
together. As opposed to the changeful energies of 
the imagination, these mental characters may be 
properly spoken of as under the general term — slow- 
ness of intellect. But it by no means follows that 
they are necessarily those of weak or foolish men. 

We observe however, farther, that the imitation 
whith Reynolds supposes to be characteristic of the 



7 


cHAP.i] THE ‘GRAND STYLE » 

Dutch l^hool is that which gives to objects such 
relief thSfc they seem real, and that he then speaks of 
this art of realistic imitation as corresponding to 
history in literature. 

§ 7. Reynolds, therefore, seems to class these dull 
works of the Dutch School under a general head, to 
which they are not commonly referred — that of 
Historical painting; while he speaks of the works of 
the Italian school not as historical, but as poetical 
painting. His next sentence will farther manifest his 
meaning. 

The Italian attends only to the inTariable, the great and 
general ideas which are fixed and inherent in universal nature ; 
the Dutch, on the contrary, to literal truth and minute exact- 
ness in the detail, as I may say, of nature modified by acci- 
dent. The attention to these petty peculiarities is the very 
cause of this naturalness so much admired in the Dutch 
pictures, which, if we suppose it to be a beauty, is certainly of 
a lower order, which ought to give place to a beauty of a 
superior kind, since one cannot be obtained but by departing 
fromwie other. 

If my opinion was asked concerning the works of Michael 
Angelo, whether they would receive any advantage from 
possessing this mechanical merit, 1 should not scruple to say, 
they would not only receive no advantage, but would lose, in a 
great measure, the effect which they now have on every mind 
susceptible of great and noble ideas. His works may be said 
to be all genius and soul ; and why should they be loaded with 
heavy matter, which can only counteract his purpose by 
retarding the progress of the imagination? 

Examining carefully this and the preceding pas- 
sage, we find the author’s unmistal^blo meaning to 
be, that Dutch painting is history ; attending to literal 
truth and ‘ minute exactness in the details of nature 
modified by, accident.’ That Italian painting is 
poetry, attending only to the invariable; and that 
works which attend only to the invariable are full 
of genius and soul; but that literal truth and exact 
detail are * heavy matter which retards the progress 
of the imagination.’ 

§ 8, This being then indisputably what Reynolds 
means to tell us, let us think a little whether he is 
in all respects right. And first, as he compai^s his 



B KECEIVED OPINIONS TOUCHING [part iv 

two kinds of painting to history and poety, let us 
see how poetry and history themselves differ, in their 
use of variable and invariable details. I am writing 
at a window which commands a view of the head of 
the Lake of Geneva; and as I look up from my paper, 
to consider this point, I see, beyond it, a blue breadth 
of softly moving water, and the outline of the moun- 
tains above Chillon, bathed in morning mist. The 
first verses which naturally come into my mind 
are 

A thousand feet in depth below 
The massy waters meet and flow ; 

So far the fathom line was sent 
From Ohillon’s snow-white battlement. 

Let ug see in what manner this poetical statement 
is distinguished from a historical one. 

It is distinguished from a truly historical state- 
ment, first, in being dimply false. The water under 
the castle of Chillon is not a thousand feet dee^ nor 
anything like it Herein, certainly, these lines fulfil 
Iteynolds’s first requirement in poetry, ‘ that it should 
be inattentive to literal truth and minute exactness 
in detail.’ In order, however, to make ovir compari- 
son more closely in other points, let us assume that 
what is stated is indeed a fact, and that it was to 
be recorded, first historically, and then poetically. 

Historically stating it, then, we should say : ‘ The 
lake was sounded from the walls of the castle of 
Chillon, and found to be a thousand feet deep.’ 

Now, if Reyn6lds be right fa his idea of the differ- 
ence between history and poetry, we shall find that 
Byron leaves out of this statement certain unneces- 
sary details, and retains only the invarfeble — that is 
to say, the points which the Lake of Geneva and 
castle of Chillon have in common with all other lakes 
and castles. 

^ * MM. Mallet et Pictet, se trouvant snr le lac aupres du 
chateau de ChillQn, le 6 Aoflt, 1774, plong^rent k la profoudeur 
de 312 pieds un thermometre’, &c. Saussure, Voyages davit 
Us Jlpes, ch&p. ii, § 33. It appears from the next paragraph, 
that thermonieter was ‘ au fond du lac.’ 



9 


CHAP. I] THE ‘GRAND STYLE’ 

Let us^ear, therefore : 

A thousand feet in depth below 

‘ Below ’? Here is, at all events, a word added 
(instead of anything being taken away); invariable, 
certainly in the case of lakes, but not absolutely 
necessary. 

The massy waters meet and flow 

‘Massy’! why massy? Because deep water is 
heavy. The word is a good word, but it is assuredly 
an added detail, and expresses a character, not which 
the Lake of Geneva has in common with all other 
lakes, but which it has in distinction from those 
which are narrow, or shallow. 

§ 9. ‘ Meet and flow.’ Why meet and flow? Partly 
to make up a rhyme ; partly to tell us that the waters 
are forceful as well as massy, and changeful as well 
as deep. Observe, a farther addition of details, and 
of details more or less peculiar to the spot, or, accord- 
ing to Reynolds’s definition, of ‘ heavy matter, retard- 
ing the progress of the imagination.’ 

So far the fathom line was sent 

Why ‘ fathom line ’? All lines for sounding are 
not fathom lines. If the lake was ever sounded from 
Chillon, it was probably sounded in metres, not 
fathoms. This is an addition of another particular 
detail, in which the only compliance with Reynolds’s 
requirement is, that there is some chance of its being 
an inaccurate one. • • 

From Chillon’s snow-white battlement 

Why ‘ snow»white ’? Because castle battlements 
are not usually snow-white. This is another added 
detail, and a detail quite peculiar to Chillon, and 
therefore exactly the most striking word in the whole 
passage. 

‘ Battlement ’ ! why battlement? Because all walls 
have not battlements, and the addition of the term 
marks the castle to be not merely a prison, but a 
fortress. • ^ 



10 RECEIVED OPINIONS TOUCHING [paetiv 

This is a curious result. Instead of fin^g, as we 
expected, the poetry distinguished from i!ae history 
by the omission of details, we find it consist entirely 
in the addition of details ; and instead of being charac- 
terized by regard only of the invariable, we find its 
whole power to consist in the clear expression of 
what is singular and particular! 

§ 10. The reader may pursue the investigation for 
himself in other instances. He will find in every 
case that a poetical is distinguished from a merely 
historical statement, not by being more vague, but 
more specific, and it might, therefore, at first appear 
that our author’s comparison should be simply re- 
versed, and that the Dutch school should be called 
poetical, and the Italian historical. But the term 
poetical does not appear very applicable to the 
generality of Dutch painting; and a little reflection 
will show us, that if the Italians represent only the 
invariable, they cannot be properly compared even 
to historians. For that which is incapable ofchange 
has no history, and records which state only the in- 
variable need not be written, and could not be read. 

§ 11. It is evident, therefore, that our author has 
entangled himself in some grave fallacy, by intro- 
ducing this idea of invariableness as forming a dis- 
tinction between poetical and historical art. What 
the fallacy is, we shall discover as we proceed; but 
as an invading army should not leave an untaken 
fortress in its rear, we must not go on w'ith our 
inquiry into the views of ileynolds until we have 
settled satisfactorily the qu^^stion already suggested 
to us, in what the essence of poetical treatment 
really consists. For though, as we, have seen, it 
certainly involves the addition of specific details, it 
cannot be simply that addition which turns the his- 
tory into poetry. For it is perfectly possible to add 
any number of details to a historical statement, and 
to make it more prosaic with every added word. As, 
for instance, ‘ The lake was sounded out of a flat- 
bottomed boat, near the crab tree at the corner of 
the^kitchen-garden , and was found to be a thousand 



11 


CHAP. I] THE ‘GRAND STYLE ‘ 

feet nineiinches deep, with a muddy bottom.’ It 
thus appears that it is not the multiplication of 
details which constitutes poetry; nor their subtrac* 
tion which constitutes history,, but that there must 
be something either in the nature of the details them- 
selves, or the method of using them, which invests 
them with poetical power or historical propriety. 

§ 12. It seems to me, and may seem to the reader, 
strange that we should need to ask the question, 

‘ ^^at is poetry?’ Here is a word we have been 
using all " our lives, and, I suppose, with a very 
distinct idea attached to it; and when I am now 
called upon to give a definition of this idea, I find 
myself at a pause. What is more singular, I do 
not at present recollect hearing the question often 
asked, though surely it is a very natural one; and 
I never recollect hearing it answered, or even 
attempted to be answered. In general, people shelter 
them^lves under metaphors, and while we hear 
poetry described as an utterance of the soul, an effu- 
sion of Divinity, or voice of nature, or in other terms 
equally elevated and obscure, we never attain any- 
thing like a definite explanation of the character 
which actually distinguishes it from prose. 

§ 13- I come, after some embarrassment, to the 
conclusion, that poetry is ‘ the suggestion, by tho 
imagination, of noble grounds for the noble emotions.’ 
I mean, by the noble emotions, those four principal 
sacred passions : Love, Veneration, Admiration, and 
Joy (this latter especiailily, if unselfish); and their 
opposites : Hatred, Indignation (or Scorn), Horror, 
and Grief — this last, when unselfish, becoming Com- 
passion. These passions in their various combina- 
tions constitute what is called ‘ poetical feeling ’, 
when they are felt on noble grounds, that is, on 
great and true grounds. Indignation, for instance, 
is a poetical feeling, if excited by serious injury; but 
it is not a poetical feeling if entertained on being 
cheated out of a small sum of money. It is very 
possible the manner of the cheat may have been 
such as to justify considerable indignation; buVthe 



12 RECEIVED OPINIOKS TOUCHING [partiv 

feeling is nevertheless not poetical unless t]^ grounds 
of it be large as well as just* In like manner, ener- 
getic admiration may be excited in certain minds by 
a display of fireworks, or a street of handsome shops; 
but the feeling is not poetical, because the grounds of 
it are false, and therefore ignoble. There is in reality 
nothing to deserve admiration either in the firing of 
packets of gunpowder, or in the display of the stocks 
of warehouses. But admiration excited by the bud- 
ding of a flower is a poetical feeling, because it is 
impossible that this manifestation of spiritual power 
and vital beauty can ever be enough admired. 

§ 14. Farther, it is necessary to the existence of 
/poetry that the grounds of these feelings should be 
furnished by the imagination. Poetical feeling, that 
is to say, mere noble emotion, .is not poetry. It is 
happily inherent in all human nature deserving the 
name, and is found often to be purest in the least 
sophisticated. But the power of assembling, by. tie 
help of the imagination, such images as willexcite 
these feelings, is the power of the poet or literally of 
the ' Maker ’ K 

^ Take, for instance, the beautiful stanza in The Affliction of 
Margaret : 

I look for ghosts, but none will force 
Their way to me. ’Tis falsely said 
That ever there was intercourse 
Between the living and the dead ; 

For, surely then, I should have sight 
Of him I wait for, day^and night. 

With love and longing infinite. 

This we call Poetry, because it is invented or made by the 
writer, entering into the mind of a supposed person. IN^ext, 
take an instance of the actual feeling truly*experienced and 
simply expressed by a real person. 

Nothing surprised me more than a woman of Argenti^re, 
whose cottage I went into to ask for milk, as I came down 
from the glacier of Argentiere, in the month of March, 1764. 
An epidemic dysentery had prevailed in the village, and, a few 
months before, had taken away from her, her father, her hus- 
band, and her brothers, so that she was left alone, with three 
children in the cradle. Her face had something noble in it, 
and fts expression bore the seal of a calm and profound sorrow. 



13 


CHAP. I] THE ‘ GRAIJD STYLE ’ 

Now th^s power of exciting the emotions depends 
of course on the richness of the imagination, and on 
its choice of those images which, in combination, 
will be most effective, or, for the particular work to 
be done, most fit. And it is altogether impossible 
for a writer not endowed with invention to conceive 
what tools a true poet will make use of, or in what 
way he will apply them, or what unexpected results 
he will bring out by them; so that it is vain to say 
that the details of poetry ought to possess, or ever 
do possess, any definite character. Generally speak- 
ing, poetry runs into finer and more delicate details 
than prose; but the details are not poetical because 
they are more delicate, but because they are em- 
ployed so as to bring out an affecting result. For 
instance, no one but a true poet would have thought 
of exciting our pity for a bereaved father by describ- 
ing his way of locking the door of his house : 

B»rhaps to himself, at that moment he said, 

The key I must take, for my Ellen is dead ; 

But of this in my ears not a word did he speak, 

And he went to the chase with a tear on his cheek. 


After having given me milk, she asked mo whence I came, and 
what I came there to do, so early in the year. When she 
knew that I was of Geneva, she said to me, ‘ she could not be- 
lieve that all Protestants were lost souls; that there were 
many honest people among ns, and that God was too good and 
too great to condemn all without distinction.’ Then, after a 
moment of reflection, she addfd, in shaking h^ head, ‘ But, that 
which is very strange, is that of so many who have gone away, 
none have ever returned. I’, she added, with an expression of 
grief, ‘ who have so mourned my husband and my brothers, 
who have never ceased to think of them, who every night con- 
jure tliem with beseechings to tell me where they are, and in 
what state they are! Ah, surely, if they lived anywhere, 
they would not leave me thus ! But, perhaps \ she added, ‘ I 
am not worthy of this kindness, perhaps the pure and innocent 
spirits of these children ’, and she looked at the cradle, ‘ may 
have their presence, and the joy which is denied to me ." — 
Saussxjbe, Voyacjes dans les Alpes, chap. xxiv. 

This we do not call Poetry, merely because it is not invented, 
hut the true utterance of a real person. • 



14 KECEIVED OPINIONS TOUCHING [partiv 

In like manner, in painting, it is altogetj^er impos- 
sible to say beforehand what details a great painter 
may make poetical by his use of them to excite noble 
emotions : and we shall, therefore, find presently 
that a painting is to be classed in the great or in- 
ferior schools, not according to the kind of details 
Vjhich it represents, but according to the uses for 
which it employs them. 

§ 15. It is only farther to be noticed, that infinite 
confusion has been introduced into this subject by 
the careless and illogical custom of opposing painting 
to poetry, instead of regarding poetry as consisting 
in a noble use, whether of colours or words. Paint- 
ing is properly to be opposed to speaking or writing^ 
but not to poetry. Both painting and speaking are 
[methods of expression. Poetry is the employment 
of either for the noblest purposes. 

§ 16. This question being thus far determined, w^e 
may proceed with our paper in The Idler, 

It is very difficult to determino the exact degree of enthu- 
siasm that the arts of painting and poetry may admit. There 
may, perhaps, be too great indulgence as well as too great a 
restraint of imagination ; if the one produces incoherent mon- 
sters, the other produces what is full as bad, lifeless insipidity. 
An intimate knowledge of the passions, and good sense, but 
not common sense, must at last determine its limits. It has 
been thought, and I believe with reason, that Michael Angelo 
sometimes transgressed those limits ; and, I think, I have seen 
figures of him of which it was very difficult to determine 
whether they were in the highest degree sublime or extremely 
ridiculous. Sucl# faults may be%aid to be the ebullitions of 
genius; but at least he had this merit, that he never was 
insipid, and whatever passion his works may excite, they will 
always escape contempt. 

What I have had under consideration is the sublimest style, 
particularly that of Michael Angelo, the Homer of painting. 
Other kinds may admit of this naturalness, which of the 
lowest kind is the chief merit ; but in painting, as in poetry, the 
highest style has the least of common nature. 

From this passage we gather three important indi- 
cations of the supposed nature of the Great Style. 
Th£^ it is the work of men in a state of enthusiasm. 



CHAP. I] THE ‘ GRAND STYLE ’ 15 

That it is like the writing of Homer; and that it 
has as littfe as possible of ‘ common nature ’ in it. 

§ 17. First, it is produced by men in a state of 
enthusiasm. That is, by men who feel strongly and 
nobly; for we do not call a strong feeling of envy^ 
jealousy, or ambition, enthusiasm. That is, there- 
fore, by men who feel poetically. This much we 
may admit, I think, with perfect safety. Great art 
is produced by men who feel acutely and nobly; 
and it is in some sort an expression of this personal 
feeling. We can easily conceive that there may be 
a sufficiently marked distinction between such art,, 
and that which is produced by men who do not 
feel at all, but who reproduce, though ever so 
accurately, yet coldly, like human mirrors, the scenes 
which pass before their eyes. 

§ 18. Secondly, Great Art is like the writing of 
Homer, and this chiefly because it has little of 
‘ common nature ’ in it. We are not clearly informed 
what meant by common nature in this passage. 
Homer seems to describe a great deal of what is com- 
mon; — cookery, for instance, very carefully in all its 
processes. I suppose the passage in the Iliad which,, 
on the whole, has excited most admiration, is that 
which describes a wife’s sorrow at parting from her 
husband, and a child’s fright at its father’s helmet; 
and I hope, at least, the former feeling may be con- 
sidered ‘ common nature *, But the true greatness 
of Homer’s style is, doubtless, held by our author to 
consist in his imaginatio:|S of things ^ot only un- 
common but impossible (such as spirits in brazen 
armour, or monsters with heads of men and bodies 
of beasts), and in his occasional delineations of the* 
human character and form in their utmost, or heroic, 
strength and beauty. We gather then on the whole,, 
that a painter in the Great Style must be enthus- 
iastic, or full of emotion, and must paint the human 
form in its utmost strength and beauty, and perhaps- 
certain impossible forms besides, liable by persons- 
not in an equally enthusiastic state of mind to be 
looked upon as in some degree absurd. This I pr^ft- 



16 THE ‘ GRAND STYLE ^ [part iv 

4siiime to be Reynolds’s meaning, and to be all that 
he intends us to gather from his comparison of the 
Great Style with the writings of Homer. But if that 
comparison be a just one in all respects, surely two 
other corollaries ought to be drawn from it, namely, 
— ^first, that these Heroic or Impossible images are 
to* be mingled with others very unheroic and very 
possible; and, secondly, that in the representation 
of the Heroic or Impossible forms, the greatest care 
must be taken in finishing the details^ so that a 
painter must not be satisfied with painting well the 
countenance and the body of his hero, but ought 
to spend the greatest part of his time (as Homer 
the greatest number of verses) in elaborating the 
sculptured pattern on his shield, 

§ 19. Let us, however, proceed with our paper : 

One may very safely recommend a little more enthusiasm 
to the modem painters ; iv/o much is certainly not the vice of 
the present age. The Italians seem to have been continually 
declining in this respect, from the time of Michael ?^ngelo to 
that of Carlo Maratti, and from thence to the very bathos of 
insipidity to which they are now sunk, so that there is no need 
of remarking, that where I mentioned the Italian painters in 
opposition to the Dutch, I mean not the moderns, but the 
heads of the old Roman and Bologniau schools ; nor did I 
mean to include, in my idea of an Italian painter, the Yene- 
tian school, which may he said to be the Dutch part of the 
Italian genius, I have only to add a word of advice to the 
painters, that, however excellent they may be in painting 
naturally, they would not flatter themselves very much upon 
it ; and to the connoisseurs, that when they see a cat or a fiddle 
painted so finely, that, as the pflrase is, it looks as if you could 
take it up, they would not fo' that reason immediately 
compare the painter to Raffaelle and Michael Angelo. 

, In this passage there are four points chiefly to be 
remarked. The first, that in the year 1759, the 
Italian painters were, in our author’s opinion, sunk 
in ihe very bathos of insipidity. The second, that 
the Venetian painters, i.e. Titian, Tintoret, and 
Veronese, are, in our author’s opinion, to be classed 
with the Dutch; that is to say, are painters in a 
sijrle ‘ in which the slowest intellect is always sure 



OF REALIZATION 


CHAP, n] 


^7 


to succeed best *. Thirdly, that painting naturally it 
not a difficult thing, nor one on which a painter 
should pride himself. And, finally, that connois- 
seurs, seeing a cat or a fiddle successfully painted, 
ought not therefore immediately to compare the 
painter to Raphael or Michael Angelo. 

Yet Raphael painted fiddles very carefully in the 
foreground of ‘his St Cecilia — ^so carefully, that they 
quite look as if they might be taken up. So care- 
fully, that 1 never yet looked at the picture with- 
out wishing that somebody would take them up, 
and out of the way. And I am under a very strong 
persuasion that Raphael did not think painting 
‘ naturally ’ an easy thing. It will be well to 
examine into this point a little; and for the present, 
with the reader’s permission, we will pass over the 
first two statements in this passage (touching the 
character of Italian art in 1759, and of Venetian art 
in general), and immediately examine some of the 
evideuise existing as to the real dignity of ‘ natural ’ 
painting— that is to say, of painting carried to the 
point at which it reaches a deceptive appearance of 
reality. 


CHAPTER II 

OF REALIZATION 

§ 1. In the outset of this inquiry, the reader must 
thoroughly understand tnat we are nof now consider- 
ing what is to be painted, but how far it is to be 
painted. Not whether Raphael does right in repre- 
senting angels playing upon violins, or whether 
Veronese does right in allowing cats and monkeys, to 
join the company of kings : but whether, supposing 
the subjects rightly chosen, they ought on the .qanvass 
to look like real angels with real violin^, anif sub- 
stantial cats looMng at veritable kings; or only like 
imaginary angels with soundless violins, ideal cats, 
and unsubstantial kings. 

M. P., III. 


c 



18 


OF REALIZATION [part iv 

Now, from the first moment when painting began 
to be a subject of literary inquiry and general criti- 
cism, I cannot remember any writer, not professedly 
artistical, who has not, more or less, in one part of 
his book or another, countenanced the idea that the 
great end of art is to produce a deceptive resemblance 
of reality. It may be, indeed, that we shall find 
the writers, through many pages, explaining prin- 
ciples of ideal beauty, and professing great delight 
in the evidences of imagination. But whenever a 
picture is to be definitely described — whenever the 
writer desires to convey to others some impression 
of an extraordinary excellence, all praise is wound 
up with some such statements as these : ‘ It was so 
exquisitely painted that you expected the figures 
to move and speak; you approached the flowers to 
enjoy their smell, and stretched your hand towards 
the fruit which had fallen from the branches. You 
shrunk back lest the s^vord of the warrior should in- 
deed descend, and turned away your head tbat you 
might not witness the agonies of the expiring 
martyr ! ’ 

§ 2. In a large number of instances, language such 
as this will be found to be merely a clumsy effort 
to convey to others a sense of the admiration, of 
which the writer does not understand the real cause 
in himself. A person is attracted to a picture by the 
beauty of its colour, interested by the liveliness of 
its story, and touched by certain countenances or 
details which remind him ol friends whom he loved, 
or scenes in which he delighted. He naturally sup- 
poses that what gives him so much pleasure must 
be a notable example of the painter’s skill; but he 
is ashamed to confess, or perhaps does not know, 
that he is so much a child as to be fond of bright 
colours and amusing incidents; and he is quite un- 
conscious of the associations which have so secret 
and inewtable a power over his heart. He casts 
about for the cause of his delight, and can discover 
no other than that he thought tne picture like reality. 

^ 3. In another, perhaps a still larger number of 



OF BEALIZATION 


19 


CHAP. Il] 

oases, such language will be found to be that of 
simple ignorance — ^the ignorance of persons whose 
position in life compels them to speak of art with- 
out having any real enjoyment of it. It is inex- 
cusably required from people of the world, that they 
should see merit in Claudes and Titians; and the 
only merit which many persons can either see or 
conceive in them is, that they must be ‘ like nature 
§ 4. In other cases, the deceptive power of the 
art is really felt to be a source of interest and amuse- 
ment. This is the case with a large number of the 
collectors of Dutch pictures. They enjoy seeing what 
is flat made to look round, exactly as a child enjoys 
a trick of legerdemain; they rejoice in flies wnich 
the spectator vainly attempts to brush away, and in 
dew which he endeavours to dry by putting the 
picture in the sun. They* take it for the greatest 
compliment to their treasures that they should be 
mistaken for windows; and think the parting of 
Abraham and Hagar adequately represented, if BLagar 
seems to be really crying. 

It is against critics and connoisseurs of this latter 
stamp (of whom, in the year 1759, the juries of art 
were for the post part composed) that the essay of 
Reynolds, which we have been examining, was justly 
directed. But Reynolds had not sufficiently con- 
sidered that neither the men of this class, nor of the 
two other classes above described, constitute the 
entire body of those who praise Art for its realization ; 
and that the holding of J>his apparently shallow and 
vulgar opinion cannot, in all cases, be attributed to 
the want either of penetration, sincerity, or sense. 
The collectors of Gerard Dows and Hobbimas may ' 
be passed by with a smile; and the affectations of 
Walpole and simplicities of Vasari dismissed with 
contempt or with compassion. But very different 
men from these have held precisely the same lan- 
guage; and, one amongst the rest, whose authority 
is absolutely, and in all points, overwhelming. 

§ 5. There was probably never a period in which 
the influence of art over the minds of men seeijed 



20 OF REALIZATION [part iv 

to depend less on its merely imitative power, than 
the close of the thirteenth century. No painting or 
sculpture at that time reached more than a rude 
resemblance of reality. Its despised perspective, im- 
perfect chiaroscuro, and unrestrained flights of fan- 
tastic imagination, separated the artist’s work from 
nature by an interval which there was no attempt 
to" disguise, and little to diminish. And yet, at this 
very period, the greatest poet of that, or perhaps of 
any other age, and the attached friend of its greatest 
painter, who must over and over again have held 
full and free conversation with him respecting the 
objects of his art, speaks in the following terms of 
painting, supposed to be carried to its highest per- 
fection : 

Qual di pennel fu maestro, e di stile 
Che ritraesse F ombre, e i tratti, ch’ ivi 
Mirar farieno uno ingegno sottile. 

Morti li morti, e i vivi parean vivi : 

Non vide me’ di me, chi vide il vero, 

Quant’ io calcai, fin che chinato givi. 

Dante, Fnrgatorio, canto xii, 1. 64. 

What master of the pencil, or the style, 

Had traced the shades and lines that might have made 
The subtlest workman wonder ? Dead^ the dead. 

The living seemed cdive ; with clearer view 
His eye beheld, not, who beheld the truth. 

Than mine what I did tread on, while I went. 

Low bending. Caret. 

Dante has here clearly no, other idea of the highest 
art than that it should bring back, as in a mirror or 
vision, the aspect of things passed or absent. The 
scenes of which he speaks are, on the pavement, for 
over represented by angelic power, so that the souls 
which traverse this circle of the rock may see them, 
as if the years of the world had been rolled back, 
and they again stood beside the actors in the moment 
of action. Nor do I think that Dante’s authority is 
absolutely necessary to compel us to admit that 
such art as this might indeed be the highest possible. 
Whatever delight we may have been in the habit of 



OF REALIZATION 


21 


CHAP, n] 

taking in pictures, if it were but truly offered to us, 
to remove at our will the canvass from the frame, 
and in lieu of it to behold, fixed for ever, the image 
of some of those mighty scenes which it has been our 
way to make mere themes for the artist’s fancy; if, 
for instance, we could again behold the Magdalene 
receiving her pardon at Christ’s feet, or the disciples 
sitting with Him at the table of Emmaus; and this 
not feebly nor fancifully, but as if some silver mirror, 
that had leaned against the wall of the chamber, had 
been miraculously commanded to retain for ever the 
colours that had flashed upon it for an instant— 
would we not part with our picture — Titian’s or 
Veronese’s though it might be? 

§ 6. Yes, the reader answers, in the instance of 
such scenes as these, but not if the scene repre- 
sented were uninteresting. Not, indeed, if it were 
utterly vulgar or painful; but we are not yet certain 
that t^ art which represents what is vulgar or painful 
is itseli of much value; and with respect to the art 
whose aim is beauty, even of an inferior order, it seems 
that Dante’s idea of its perfection has still much 
evidence in its favour. For among persons of native 
good sense, and courage enough to speak their minds, 
we shall often find a considerable degree of doubt 
as to the use of art, in consequence of their habitual 
comparison of it with reality. ‘ What is the use, 
to me, of the painted landscape?’ they will ask : 
‘ I see more beautiful and perfect landscapes every 
day of my life in my forenoon walk. ’ ‘ What is 

the use, to me, of the painted effigy of hero or 
beauty? I can see a stamp of higher heroism, and 
light of purer beauty, on the faces round me, utterly 
inexpressible by the highest human skill.’ Now, it 
is evident that to persons of this temper the only 
valuable pictures would indeed be mirrors, reflecting 
permanently the images of the things in which they 
took delight, and of the faces that they loved. 
‘ Nay but the reader interrupts (if he is of the 
Idealist school), ‘ I deny that more beautiful things 
are to be seen in nature than in art ; on the contriifry, 



22 


OF REALIZATION [part iv 

everything in nature is faulty, and art represents 
nature as perfected.* Be it so. Must, therefore, 
this perfected nature be imperfectly represented? 
Is it absolutely required of the painter, who has con- 
ceived perfection, that he should so paint it as to 
look only like a picture? Or is not Dante’s view of 
Tche matter right even here, and would it not be 
well that the perfect conception of Pallas should 
be so given as to look like Pallas herself, rather than 
merely like the picture of Pallas? 

§ 7, It is not easy for us to answer this question 
rightly, owing to the difficulty of imagining any art 
which should reach the perfection supposed. Our 
actual powers of imitation are so feeble that wherever 
deception is attempted, a subject of a comparatively 
low or confined order must be chosen. I do not 
enter at present into the inquiry how far the powers 
of imitation extend; but assuredly up to the present 
period they have been so limited that it is^ hardly 
possible for us to conceive a deceptive art embrac- 
ing a high range of subject. But let the reader 
make the effort, and consider seriously what he 
would give at any moment to have the power of 
arresting the fairest scenes, those which so often 
rise before him only to vanish; to stay the cloud 
in its fading, the leaf in its trembling, and the 
shadows in their changing; to bid the fitful foam 
be fixed upon the river, and the ripples be ever- 
lasting upon the lake; and then to bear away with 
him no darkefaed or feeblef sun-stain (though even 
that is beautiful), but a counterfeit which should 
seem no counterfeit — the true and perfect image of 
life indeed. Or rather (for the full majesty of such 
a power is not thus sufficiently expressed) let him 
consider that it would be in efiect nothing else than 
a capacity of transporting himself at any moment 
into any scene — a gift as great as can be possessed 
by a disembodied spirit : and suppose, also, this 
necromancy embracing not only the present but the 
past, and enabling us seemingly to enter into the 
vefy bodily presence of men long since gathered to 



OF REALIZATION 


23 


CHAP. Il] 

the dust; to behold them in act as they lived, but — 
with greater privilege than ever was granted to the 
companions of those transient acts of life — to see 
them fastened at our will in the gesture and expres- 
sion of an instant, and stayed, on the eve of some 
great deed, in immortality of burning purpose. Con- 
ceive, so far as it is possible, such power as this, 
and then say whether the art which conferred it is 
to be spoken lightly of, or whether we should not 
rather reverence, as half divine, a gift which would 
go so far as to raise us into the rank, and invest 
us with the felicities, of angels? 

Yet such would imitative art be in its perfection. 
Not by any means an easy thing, as Reynolds sup- 
poses it. Far from being easy, it is so utterly be- 
yond all human power that we have difficulty even 
in conceiving its nature or results — the best art we 
as yet possess comes so far short of it. 

§ 8. But we must not rashly come to the con- 
clusidh that such art would, indeed, be the highest 
possible. There is much to be considered hereafter 
on the other side : the only conclusion we are as 
yet warranted in forming is, that Reynolds had no 
right to speak lightly or contemptuously of imitative 
art; that in fact, when he did so, he had not con- 
ceived its entire nature, but was thinking of some 
vulgar conditions of it, which were the only ones 
known to him, and that, therefore, his whole endeav- 
our to explain the difference between great and mean 
art has been disappointed; that has involved 
himself in a crowd of theories, whose issue he had 
not foreseen, and committed himself to conclusions 
which he never intended. There is an instinctive 
consciousness in his own mind of the difference be- 
tween high and low art; but he is utterly incapable 
of explaining it, and every effort which he makes to 
do so involves him in unexpected fallacy and ab- 
surdity. It is not true that Poetry does not concern 
herself with minute details. It is not true that high 
art seeks only the Invariable. It is not true that 
imitative art is an easy thing. It is not true jbhat 



24 


OF REAIilZATION [part iv 

the faithful rendering of nature is an employment 
in which ‘ the slowest intellect is likely to succeed 
best All these successive assertions are utterly 
false and untenable, while the plain truth, a truth 
lying at the very door, has all the while escaped 
him — ^that which was incidentally stated in the pre- 
ceding chapter — ^namely, that the difierence between 
great and mean art lies, not in definable methods of 
handling, or styles of representation, or choices of 
subjects, but wholly in the nobleness of the end to 
which the effort of the painter is addressed. We 
cannot say that a painter is great because he paints 
boldly, or paints delicately; because he generalizes 
or particularizes; because he loves detail, or because 
he disdains it. He is great if, by any of these means, 
he has laid open noble truths, or aroused noble 
emotions. It does not matter whether he paint the 
petal of a rose, or the chasms of a precipice, so that 
Love and Admiration attend him as he labours, and 
wait for ever upon his work. It does not iliatter 
whether he toil for months upon a few inches of his 
canvass, or cover a palace front with colour in a 
day, so only that it be with a solemn purpose that 
he has filled his heart with patience, or urged his 
hand to haste. And it does not matter whether he 
seek for his subjects among peasants or nobles, 
among the heroic or the simple, in courts or in fields, 
so cipy that he behold all things with a thirst for 
beauty, and a hatred of meanness and vice. There 
are, indeed, certain methods ^of representation which 
are usually adopted by the most active minds, and 
certain characters of subjeco usually delighted in 
by the noblest hearts; but it is quite possible, quite 
easy, to adopt the manner of painting without sharing 
the activity of mind, and to imitate the choice of 
subject without possessing the nobility of spirit; 
while, on the other hand, it is altogether impossible 
to foretell on what strange objects the strength of a 
great man will sometimes be concentrated, or by 
what strange means he will sometimes express him- 
selfy So that true criticism of art never can consist 



25 


CHAP, m] GREATNESS OF STYLE 

in the mere application of rules; it can be just only 
when it is founded on quick sympathy with the in- 
numerable instinets and changeful efforts of human 
nature, chastened and guided by unchanging love of 
all things that God has created to be beautiful, and 
pronounced to be good. 


CHAPTER III 

OP THE REAL NATURE OP GREATNESS OF STYLE 

§ 1. I DOUBT not that the reader was ill-satisfied 
with the conclusion arrived at in the last chapter. 
That ‘ great art ’ is art which represents what is 
beautiful and good, may not seem a very profound 
discovery; and the main question may be thought 
to have been all the time lost sight of, namely, 
‘ What is beautiful, and what is good?’ No; those 
are no? the main, at least not the first questions; 
on the contrary, our subject becomes at once opened 
and simplified as soon as we have left those the 
only questions. For observe, our present task, ac- 
cording to our old plan, is merely to investigate the 
relative degrees of the beautiful in the art of different 
masters; and it is an encouragement to be con- 
vinced, first of all, that what is lovely will also be 
great, and what is pleasing, noble. Nor is the lidn- 
clusion so much a matter of course as it at first 
appears, for, surprising a6 the statem^t may seem, 
all the confusion into which Reynolds has plunged 
both himself and his readers, in the essay we have 
been examining, results primarily from a doubt in 
his own mind as to the existence of beauty at all. 
In the next paper I alluded to, No. 82 (which needs 
not, however, to be examined at so great length), he 
calmly attributes the whole influence of beauty to 
custom, saying, that ‘ he has no doubt, if we were 
more used to deformity than to beauty, deformity 
would then lose the idea now annexed to it, and take 
that of beauty; as if the whole world shall agupe 



26 THE REAL NATURE OF [part ivi 

that Yes and No should change their meanings. Yes 
would then deny, and No would affirm I’ 

§ 2. The world does, indeed, succeed — oftener than 
is, perhaps, altogether well for the world — in making 
Yes mean No, and No mean Yes But the world 
has never succeeded, nor ever will, in making itself 
delight in black clouds more than in blue sky, or 
love the dark earth better than the rose that grows 
from it. Happily for mankind, beauty and ugliness 
are as positive in their nature as physical pain and 
pleasure, as light and darkness, or as life and death; 
and, though they may be denied or misunderstood in 
many fantastic ways, the most subtle reasoner will 
at last find that colour and sweetness are still attrac- 
tive to him, and that no logic will enable him to 
think the rainbow sombre, or the violet scentless. 
But the theory that beauty was merely a result of 
custom was very common in Johnson’s time. Gold- 
smith has, I think, expressed it with more force and 
wit than any other Tvriter, in various pas^ges of 
The Citizen of the World. And it was, indeed, a 
curious retribution of the folly of the world of art, 
which for some three centuries had given itself reck- 
lessly to the pursuit of beauty, that at last it should 
be led to deny the very existence of what it had 
so morbidly and passionately sought. It was as if 
a child should leave its home to pursue the rainbow, 
and then, breathless and hopeless, declare that it 
did not exist. Nor is the lesson less useful which 
may be gain^ in observing the adoption of such a 
theory by Reynolds himself. It shows how com- 
pletely an artist may be unconscious of the principles 
of his own work, and how he may be led by instinct 
to do all that is right, while he is misled by false 
logic to say all that is wrong. For nearly every 
word that Reynolds wrote was contrary to his own 
practice; he seems to have been born to teach all 
error by his precept, and all excellence by his ex- 
ample; he enforced with his lips generalization and 
idealism, while with his pencil he was tracing the 
€’♦ ’ Del * no per li danar, vi ‘ si ’ far ita. 



27 


cHAP.m] GREATl^ESS OF STYLE 

patterns of the dresses of the belles of his day ; he 
exhorted his pupils to attend only to the invariable, 
while he himself was occupied in distinguishing every 
variation of womanly temper; and ne denied the 
existence of the beautiful, at the same instant that 
he arrested it as it passed, and perpetuated it for 
ever, 

§ 8. But we must not quit the subject here. How- 
ever inconsistently or dimly expressed, there is, in- 
deed, some truth in that commonly accepted dis- 
tinction between high and low art. That a thing 
should be beautiful is not enough; there is, as we 
said in the outset, a higher and lower range of 
beauty, and some ground for separating into various 
and unequal ranks painters who have, nevertheless, 
each in his several way, represented something that 
was beautiful or good. 

Nor, if we would, can we get rid of this conviction. 
We hf,ve at all times some instinctive sense that 
the function of one painter is greater than that of 
another, even supposing each equally successful in 
his own way; and we feel that, if it were possible 
to conquer prejudice, and do away with the iniquities 
of personal feeling, and the insufficiencies of limited 
knowledge, we should all agree in this estimate, and 
be able to place each painter in his right rank, 
measuring them by a true scale of nobleness. We 
feel that the men in the higher classes of the scale 
would be, in the full sense of the word. Great — men 
whom one would give ftiuch to see the faces of but 
for an instant; and that those in the lower classes 
of the scale (though none were admitted but who 
had true merit of some kind) would be very small 
men, not greatly exciting either reverence or curi- 
osity. And with this fixed instinct in our minds, 
we permit our teachers daily to exhort their pupils 
to the cultivation of ‘ great art ’ — ^neither they nor 
we having any very clear notion as to what the 
greatness consists in ; but sometimes inclining to 
think it must depend on the space of the canvass, 
and that art on a scale of 6 feet by 10 is something 



,0 THE REAL NATURE OP [part iM 

spiritually separated from that on a scale of 3 feet 
by 6; — sometimes holding it to consist in painting 
the nude body, rather than the body decently clothed; 
— sometimes being convinced that it is connected 
with the study of past history, and that the art is 
only great which represents what the painter never 
SAW, and about which he knows nothing; — and some- 
times being firmly persuaded that it consists in 
generally finding fault with, and endeavouring to 
mend, whatsoever the Divine Wisdom has made. 
All which various errors, having yet some motes 
and atoms of truth in the make of each of them, 
deserve some attentive analysis, for they come under 
that general law — that ‘ the corruption of the best 
is the worst \ There are not worse errors going than 
these four; and yet the truth they contain, and the 
instinct which urges many to preach them, are at 
the root of all healthy growth in art. We ruin one 
young painter after another by telling him to^follow 
great art without knowing, ourselves, what greatness 
is; and yet the feeling that it verily is something, 
and that there are depths and breadths, shallows 
and narrows, in the matter, is all that we have to 
look to, if we would ever make our art serviceable 
to ourselves or others. To follow art for the sake 
of being a great man, and therefore to cast about 
continually for some means of achieving position or 
attracting admiration, is the surest way of ending 
in total extinction. And yet it is only by honest 
reverence for art itself, and* by great self-respect in 
the practice of it, that it can be rescued from 
dilettantism, raised to approved honourableness, and 
brought to the proper work it has to accomplish in 
the service of man. 

§ 4. Let us therefore look into the facts of the 
thing, not with any metaphysical, or otherwise vain 
and troublesome effort at acuteness, but in a plain 
way; for the facts themselves are plain enough, 
and may be plainly stated, only the difficulty is that 
out of these facts, right and left, the different forms 
of »iisapprehension branch into grievous complexity. 



cHAP.m] GREATNESS OF STYLE 29 

and branch so far and wide, that if once we try to 
follow them, they will lead ns quite from our mark 
into other separate, though not less interesting dis- 
cussions. The best way will be therefore, I think, 
to sketch out at once in this chapter, the different 
characters which really constitute * greatness ’ of 
style, and to indicate the principal directions of the 
out branching misapprehensions of them; then, in 
the succeeding chapters, to take up in succession 
those which need more talk about them, and follow 
out at leisure whatever inquiries they may suggest. 

§ 6. I. Choice of Noble Subject. Greatness of 
style consists, then : first, in the habitual choice of 
subiects of thought which involve wide interests and 
profound passions, as opposed to those which involve 
narrow interests and slight passions. The style is 
greater or less in exact proportion to the nobleness 
of the interests and passions involved in the subject. 
The habitual choice of sacred subjects, such as the 
Nativity, Transfiguration, Crucifixion (if the choice be 
sincere) , implies that the painter has a natural disposi- 
tion to dwell on the highest thoughts of which human- 
ity is capable ; it constitutes him so far forth a painter 
of the highest order, as, for instance, Leonardo, in 
his painting of the Last Supper : he who delights in 
representing the acts or meditations of great men, 
as, for instance, Raphael painting the School of 
Athens, is, so far forth, a painter of the second 
order : he who represents the passions and events 
of ordinary life, of the third. And in this ordinary 
life, he who represents deep thoughts and sorrows, 
as, for instance. Hunt, in his Claudio and Isabella, 
and such other works, is of the highest rank in his 
sphere; and he who represents the slight malignities 
and passions of the drawing-room, as, for instance, 
LesUe, of the second rank; he who represents the 
sports of boys or simplicities of clowns, as Webster 
or Teniers, of the third rank; and he who represents 
brutalities and vices (for delight in them, and not 
for rebuke of them), of no rank at ail, or rather of 
a negative rank, holding a certain order in the abjss. 



; m the real nature of [part iv, 

§ 6. The reader will, I hope, understand how 
much importance is to be attached to the sentence 
in the first parenthesis, ‘ if the choice be sincere 
for choice of subject is, of course, only available as 
a criterion of the rank of the painter, when it is 
made from the heart. Indeed, in the lower orders 
of painting, the choice is always made from such 
heart as the painter has; for his selection of the 
brawls of peasants or sports of children can, of 
course, proceed only from the fact that he has more 
sympathy with such brawls or pastimes than with 
nobler subjects. But the choice of the higher kind 
of subjects is often insincere; and may, therefore, 
afford no real criterion of the painter’s rank. The 
greater number of men who have lately painted 
religious or heroic subjects have done so in mere 
ambition, because they had been taught that it was 
a good thing to be a ‘ high art ’ painter; and the 
fact is that, in nine cases out of ten, the so-called 
historical or ‘ high art ’ painter is a person infinitely 
inferior to the painter of flowers or still life. He is, 
in modern times, nearly always a man who has 
peat vanity without pictorial capacity, and differs 
from the landscape or fruit painter merely in mis- 
understanding and overestimating his own powers. 
He mistakes his vanity for inspiration, his ambition 
for greatness of soul, and takes pleasure in what he 
calls ‘ the ideal \ merely because he has neither 
humility nor capacity enough to comprehend the 
real. ^ 

§ 7. But alfo observe, it is not enough even that 
the choice be sincere. It must also be wiee. It 
happens very often that a man of weak intellect, 
sincerely desiring to do what is good and useful, will 
devote himself to high art subjects because he thinks 
them the only ones on which time and toil can be 
usefully spent, or, sometimes, because they are 
really the only ones he has pleasure in contemplating. 
But not having intellect enough to enter into the 
minds of truly peat men, or to imagine great events 
as they really happened, he cannot become a great 



oHAP.m] GBEATNESS OF STILE U 

painter; he degrades the subjects he intended to 
honour, and his work is more utterly thrown away, 
and his rank as an artist in reality lower, than if he 
had devoted himself to the imitation of the simplest 
objects of natural history. The works of Overbeok 
are a most notable instance of this form of error. 

§ 8, It must also be remembered, that in nearly 
all the great periods of art the choice of subject has 
not been left to the painter. His employer— abbot, 
baron, , or monarch — determined for him whether 
he should earn his bread by making cloisters bright 
with choirs of saints, painting coats of arms on 
leaves of romances, or decorating presence-chambers 
with complimentary mythology ; and his own 
personal feelings are ascertainable only by watching, 
in the themes assigned to him, what are the points 
in which he seems to take most pleasure. Thus, in 
the prolonged ranges of varied subjects with which 
Benozzo Gozzoli decorated the cloisters of Pisa, it 
is easy •to see that love of simple domestic incident, 
sweet landscape, and glittering ornament, prevails 
slightly over the solemn elements of religious feel- 
ing, which, nevertheless, the spirit of the age in- 
stilled into him in such measure as to form a very 
lovely and noble mind, though still one of the second 
order. In the work of Orcagna, an intense solemnity 
and energy in Ihe sublimest groups of his figures, 
fading away as he touches inferior subjects, indicates 
that his home was among the archangels, and his 
rank among the first oj the sons of men; while 
Correggio, in the sidelong grace, artificial smiles, and 
purple languors of his saints, indicates the inferior 
instinct which would have guided his choice in quite 
other directions, had it not been for the fashion of 
the age, and the need of the day. 

§ 9. It will follow, of course, from the above con- 
siderations, that the choice which characterises the 
school of high art is seen as much in the treatment 
of a subject as in its selection, and that the expression 
of the thoughts of the persons represented will always 
be the first thing considered by the painter wno 



THE EEAIi IJATUBE OP [paet rwl 

IvortMly enters that highest school. For the artist 
who sincerely chooses the noblest subject will also 
chcfcsp cMeny to represent what makes that sub- 
ject noble, namely, the various heroic or other 
.noble emotions of the persons represented. If, in- 
iStfead.of this, the artist seeks only to make his picture 
agreeable by the Composition of its masses and 
colours, or by any other merely pictorial merit, as 
fine, drawing of limbs, it is evident, not only that 
any other subject would have answered his purpose 
as well, but that he is unfit to approach the subject 
he hae chosen, '"because he cannot enter into its 
deepest meaning, and therefore cannot in reality have 
chosen ii for that meaning. Nevertheless, while the 
expression is always to be the first thing considered, 
all Other merits must be added to the utmost of the 
painter's power; for until he can both colour and 
draw beautifully he has no business to consider him- 
self a painter at all, far less to attempt the noblest 
subjects of painting; and, w'hen he has once pos- 
sessed himself of these powers, he will naturally 
and fitly employ them to deepen and perfect the 
inmression madje by the sentiment of his subject. 

The perfect unison of expression, as the painter’s 
main purpose, with the full and natural exertion of 
his pictorial power in the details of the work, is 
found only in the old Pre-Eaphaelite periods, and 
in the modern Pre-llaphaelite school. In the works 
of Giotto, Angelico, Orcagna, John Bellini, and one 
or two more, these two cgnditipns of high art are 
..entirely fulfilled, so far as tjie knowledge of those 
days enabled them to be fulfilled ; and in the modern 
Pre-Raphaelite school they are fulfilled nearly to 
the uttermost. Hunt’s Light of the World, is, I 
believe, the most perfect instance of expressional 
purpose with technical power, which the world has 
yet produced. 

§ 10. Now in the Post-Raphaelite period of ancient 
art, and in the spurious high art of modem times, 
two broad forms of ert-or divide the schools ; the one 
consisting in (A) the superseding of expression by 



cJHAP.in] i&REATNEgS'OF STILE U 

technical excellence, and the other in (B) the super- 
seding of technical exceiUence by expression/ 

(A). Superseding expression by technical excel- 
lence. — This takes place most franMy, and therefore 
most innocently, in the work of the Venetians. They 
very nearly ignore expression altogether? directing 
their aim exclusively to the rendering of external 
truths of colour and form, Paul Veronese will make 
the Magdalene wash the feet of Christ with a coun- 
tenance as absolutely unmoved as that of any ordinary 
servant bringing a ewer to her master, and will 
introduce 4he supper at Emmaus as a background 
to the ^rtraits of two children playing with a dog. 
Of the wrongness or rightness of such a proceeding 
we shall reason in another place; at present we 
have to note it merely as displacing the Venetian 
work from the highest or expressional rank of art- 
But the error is generally made in a more subtle 
and dangerous way. The artist deceives himself into 
the idtja that he is doing all he can to elevate his 
subject by treating it under rules of art, introducing 
into it accurate science, and collecting for it the 
beauties of (so called) ideal form; whereas he may, 
in reality, be all the while sacrificing his subject to, 
his own vanity or pleasure, and losing truth, noble- 
ness, and impressiveness for the sake of delightful 
lines or creditable pedantries. v 

§ 11. (B). Superseding technical excellence by 
expression. — This is usually done under the influence 
of another kind of vanity. The artist desires that 
men should think he has an elevated soul, affects 
to despise the ordinary excellence of art, contem- 
plates with separated egotism the course of his own 
imaginations or sensations, and refuses to look at 
the real facts round about him, in order that he 
may adore at leisure the shadow of himself. He 
lives in an element of what he calls tender emotions 
and lofty aspirations; which are, in fact, nothing 
more than very ordinary weaknesses or instincts/ 
contemplated through a mist of pride, A larger 
range of modern German art comes under this head.* 
M. p., ni. B * 



THE BEAL NATURE OF [paet iv 

A more interesting and respectable form of this 
error is fallen into by some truly earnest men, who, 
finding their powers not adequate to the attainment 
of great artistical excellence, but adequate to render- 
ing, up to a certain point, the expression of the 
human countenance, devote themselves to that object 
alo;ie, abandoning effort in other directions, and 
executing the accessaries of their pictures feebly or 
carelessly. With these are associated another group 
of philosophical painters, who suppose the artistical 
merits of other parts adverse to the expression, as 
drawing the spectator’s attention away from it, and 
who paint in grey colour, and imperfect light and 
shade, by way of enforcing the purity of their con- 
ceptions. Both these classes of conscientious but 
narrow-minded artists labour under the same grievous 
mistake of imagining that wilful fallacy can ever be 
either pardonable or helpful. They forget that 
Colour, if used at all, must be either true or false, 
and that what they call chastity, dignity, and re- 
serve is, to the eye of any person accustomed to 
nature, pure, bold, and impertinent falsehood. It 
does not in the eyes of any soundly minded man, 
exalt the expression of a female face that the cheeks 
should be painted of the colour of clay, nor does it 
in the least enhance his reverence for a saint to 
find the scenery around him deprived, by his pre- 
sence, of sunshine. It is an important consolation, 
however, to reflect that no artist ever fell into any 
of these last jthree errors (wnder head B) who had 
really the capacity of becoming a great painter. No 
man ever despised colour who could produce it; and 
the error of these sentimentalists and philosophers is 
not so much in the choice of their manner of paint- 
ing, as in supposing themselves capable of painting 
at all. Some of them might have made efficient 
sculptors, but the greater number had their mission 
in some other sphere than that of art, and would 
have found, in works of practical charity, better em- 
ployment for their gentleness and sentimentalism, 
th^ in denying to human beauty its colour, and 



m 


CHAP.m] GREATNESS OF STYLE 

to natural scenery its light; in depriving heaven of 
its blue, and earth of its bloom, valour of its glow, 
and modesty of its blush. 

§ 12. II. Love op Beauty. The second charac- 
teristic of the great school of art is, that it introduces 
in the conception of its subject as much beauty as 
is possible, consistently with truth 

1 As here, for the first time, I am obliged to use the terms 
Truth and Beauty in a kind of opposition. I must therefore 
stop for a moment to state clearly the relation ot these two 
qualities of art ; and to protest against the vulgar and foolish 
habit of confusing truth and beauty with each other. People 
with shallow powers of thought, desiring to flatter themselves 
with the sensation of having attained profundity, are continu- 
ally doing the most serious mischief by introducing confusion 
into plain matters, and then valuing themselves on being con- 
founded. Nothing is more common than to hear people who 
desire to be thought philosophical, declare that ‘beauty is 
truth’, and ‘truth is beauty’. I would most earnestly beg 
every sensible person who hears such an assertion made, to nip 
the germinating philosopher in his ambiguous bud ; and beg 
him, if he really believes his own assertion, never thence- 
forward to use two words for the same thing. The fact is, 
truth and beauty are entirely distinct, though often related, 
things. One is a property of statements, the other of objects. 
The statement that * two and two make four ’ is true, but it is 
neither beautiful nor ngly, for it is invisible ; a rose is lovely, 
but it is neither true nor false, for it is silent. That which 
shows nothing cannot be fair, and that which asserts nothing 
cannot be false. Even the ordinary use of the words false and 
true, as applied to artificial and real things, is inaccurate. An 
artificial rose is not a * false ’ ro.se, it is not a rose at all. The 
falseness is in the person wh% states, or induces the belief, that 
it IS a rose. 

Now, therefore, in things concerning art, the words true and 
false are only to be rightly used while the picture is considered 
as a statement of facts. The painter asserts that this which 
he has painted is the form of a dog, a man, or a tree. If it be 
not the form of a dog, a man, or a tree, the painter’s statement 
is false ; and, therefore, we justly speak of a false line, or 
false colour ; not that any line or colour can in themselves be 
false, but they become so when they convey a statement that 
they resemble something which they do not resemble. But 
the beauty of the lines or colours is wholly independent of any 
such statement. They may be beautiful lines, though quite 
inaccurate, and ugly lines though quite faithful. A pictj^re 



is THE REAL NATURE OF [part iV. 

For instance, in any subject consisting of a num- 
ber of figures, it will make as many of those figures 
beautiful as the faithful representation of humanity 
will admit. It will not deny the facts of ugliness or 
decrepitude, or relative inferiority and superiority of 
feature as necessarily manifested in a crowd, but 
it will, so far as it is in its power, seek for and 
dwell upon the fairest forms, and in all things insist 
on the beauty that is in them, not on the ugliness. 
In this respect, schools of art become higher in 
exact proportion to the degree in which they appre- 
hend and love the beautiful. Thus, Angelico, 
intensely loving all spiritual beauty, will be of the 
highest rank; and Paul Veronese and Correggio, 
intensely loving physical and corporeal beauty, of 
the second rank; and Albert Diirer, Rubens, and in 
general the Northern artists, apparently insensible 
to beauty, and caring only for truth, whether shapely 
or not, of the third rank; and Teniers and Salvator, 
Caravaggio, and other such worshippers af the 
depraved, of no rank, or, as we said before, of a 
certain order in the abyss. 

§ 13. The corruption of the schools of high art, 
BO far as this particular quality is concerned, con- 

may be frightfully ugly, which represents with fidelity some 
base circumstance of daily life ; and a painted window may be 
exquisitely beautiful, which represents men with eagles’ faces, 
and dogs with blue heads and crimson tails (though, by the 
way, this is not in the strict sense arr, as we shall see 
hereafter, inasmuch as it means ^j,o assertion that men ever had 
eagles’ faces). If this were not so, it would be impossible to 
sacrifice truth to beauty ; for to at^jain the one would always 
be to attain the other. But, unfortunately, this sacrifice is 
exceedingly possible, and it is chiefly this which characterizes 
the false schools of high art, so far as high art consists in the 
pursuit of beauty. For although truth and beauty are inde- 
pendent of each other, it does not follow that we are at liberty 
to pursue whichever we please. They are indeed separable, 
but it is wrong to separate them ; they are to be sought 
together in the order of their worthiness ; that is to say, truth 
first, and beauty afterwards. High art differs from low art in 
possessing an excess of beauty in addition to its truth, not in 
possessing excess of beauty inconsistent with truth. 



CHAP.m] GREATNESS OF STYLE 87 

sists in the sacrifice 6f truth to beauty. Great ^ 
dwells on all that is beautiful; but false art omits 
or changes all that is Ugly. Great art accepts Nature 
as she is, but directs the eyes and thoughts to what 
is most perfect in her; false art saves itself the 
trouble of direction by removing' or altering what- 
ever it thinks objectionable. The evil results of 
which proceeding are twofold. 

§ 14. First : That beauty deprived of its proper 
foils and adjuncts ceases to be enjoyed as beauty, 
just as light deprived of all shadow ceases to be 
enjoyed as light. A white canvass cannot produce 
an effect of sunshine; the painter must darken it in 
some places before he can make it look luminous 
in others; nor can an uninterrupted succession of 
beauty produce the true effect of beauty; it must be 
foiled by inferiority before its own power can be 
developed. Nature has for the most part mingled 
her inferior and nobler elements as she mingles 
sunshfne with shade, giving due use and influence 
to both, and the painter who chooses to remove the 
shadow, perishes in the burning desert he has created. 
The truly high and beautiful art of Angelico is 
continually refreshed and strengthened by his frank 
portraiture of the most ordinary features of his 
brother monks, and of the recorded peculiarities of 
ungainly sanctity; but the modern German and 
Raphaelesque schools lose all honour and nobleness 
in barber-like admiration of handsome faces, and 
have, in fact, no real Mth except in ^straight noses, 
and curled hair. Paul Veronese opposes the dwarf 
to the soldier, and the negress to the queen; Shaks- 
peare places Caliban beside Miranda, and Autolycus 
beside Perdita; but the vulgar idealist withdraws 
his beauty to the safety of the saloon, and his inno- 
cence to the seclusion of the cloister; he pretends 
that he does this in delicacy of choice and purity of 
sentiment, while in truth he has neither courage to 
front the monster, not wit enough to furnish the 
knave. 

§ 15. It is only by the habit of representing fa.^h- 



fis THE BEAL NATURE OF [part I'Vl 

fully all things, that we can truly learn what is 
beautiful, and what is not. The ugliest objects con- 
tain some element of beauty; and in all, it is an 
element peculiar to themselves, which cannot be 
separated from their ugliness, but must either be 
enjoyed together with it, or not at all. The more a 
painter accepts nature as he finds it, the more un- 
expected beauty he discovers in what he at first 
despised; but once let him arrogate the right of 
rejection, and he will gradually contract his circle 
of enjoyment, until what he supposed to be noble- 
ness of selection ends in narrowness of perception. 
Dwelling perpetually upon one class of ideas, his art 
becomes at once monstrous and morbid; until at 
last he cannot faithfully represent even what he 
chooses to retain; his discrimination contracts into 
darkness, and his fastidiousness fades into fatuity. 

High art, therefore, consists neither in altering, 
nor in improving nature; but in seeking throughout 
nature for ‘ whatsoever tnings are lovely, and" what- 
soever things are pure ’; in loving these, in display- 
ing to the utmost of the painter’s power such love- 
liness as is in them, and directing the thoughts of 
others to them by winning art, or gentle emphasis. 
Of the degree in which this can be done, and in which 
. it may be permitted to gather together, without 
falsifying, the finest forms or thoughts, so as to 
create a sort of perfect vision, we shall have to 
speak hereafter : at present, it is enough to remem- 
ber that art (^ceteris paribvXi) is great in exact pro- 
portion to the love of beauty -^hown by the painter, 
provided that love of beauty forfeit no atom of truth. 

§ 16 . HI. Sincerity. The next ^ characteristic of 
great art is that it includes the largest possible 
quantity of Truth in the most perfect possible har- 
mony. If it were possible for art to give all the 
truths of nature, it ought to do it. But this is not 
possible. Choice must always be rnade of some 
facts which can be represented, from among others 

1 I name them in order of increasing, not decreasing import- 
anfe. 



CHAP.m] GREATNESS OF STYLE 89 

which must be passed by in silence, or even, in some 
respects, misrepresented. The inferior artist chooses 
unimportant and scattered truths; the great artist 
chooses the most necessary first, and afterwards the 
most consistent with these, so as to obtain the 
greatest possible and most harmonious sum. For 
instance, Rembrandt always chooses to represent the 
exact force with which the light on the most illumined 
part of an object is opposed to its obscurer por- 
tions. In order to obtain this, in most oases, not 
very important truth, he sacrifices the light and 
colour of five-sixths of his picture; and the expres- 
sion of every character of objects which depends on 
tenderness of shape or tint. But he obtains his 
single truth, and what picturesque and forcible 
expression is dependent upon it, with magnificent 
skill and subtlety. Veronese, on the contrary, 
chooses to represent the great relations of visible 
things to each other, to the heaven above, and to 
the earth beneath them. He holds it more import- 
ant to show how a figure stands relieved from delicate 
air, or marble wall; how as a red, or purple, or 
white figure, it separates itself, in clear discernibility, 
from things not red, nor purple, nor white; how 
infinite daylight shines round it; how innumerable 
veils of faint shadow invest it; how its blackness 
and darkness are, in the excess of their nature, 
just as limited and local as its intensity of light : 
all this, I say, he feels to be more important than 
showing merely the e^jact measwre of the spark of 
sunshine that gleams on a dagger-hMt, or glows on 
a jewel. All this, moreover, he feels to be harmoni- 
ous — capable of being joined in one great system of 
spacious truth. And with inevitable watcnfulness, 
inestimable subtlety, he unites all this in tenderest 
balance, noting in each hair’s-breadth of colour, not 
merely what its rightness or wrongness is in itself, 
but wnat its relation is to every other on his canvass ; 
restraining, for truth’s sake, his exhaustless energy, 
reining back, for truth’s sake, his fiery strength; 
veiling, before truth, the vanity of brightness; pene- 



40 THE BEAL NATURE OF [part iv. 

tratiug, for truth, the discouragement of gloom; 
ruling his restless invention with a rod of iron; 
pardoning no error, no thoughtlessness, no forgetful- 
ness; and subduing all his powers, impulses, and 
imagin&tions, to the arbitrement of a merciless 
justice, and the obedience of an incorruptible verity. 

J give this instance with respect to colour and 
shade; but, in the whole field of art, the difference 
between the great and inferior artists is of the same 
kind, and may be determined at once by the question, 
which of them conveys the largest sum of truth? 

§ 17. It follows from this principle, that in general 
all great drawing is distinct drawing; for truths 
which are rendered indistinctly might, for the most 
part, as well not be rendered at all. There are, in- 
deed, certain facts of mystery, and facts of indis- 
tinctness, in all objects, which must have their 
proper place in the general harmony, and the reader 
will presently find me, when we come to that part 
of our investigation, telling him that all good tdr aw- 
ing must in some sort be wdistinct. We may, 
however, understand this apparent contradiction, by 
reflecting that the highest knowledge always involves 
a more advanced perception of the fields of the 
unknown; and, therefore, it may most truly be said, 
that to know anything well involves a profound sen- 
sation of ignorance, while yet it is equally true that 
good and noble knowledge is distinguished from vain 
and useless knowledge chiefly by its clearness and 
distinctness, and by the vigorous consciousness of 
what is known and what is not. 

So in art. The best drawing involves a wonderful 
perception and expression of indistinctness; and yet 
all noble drawing is separated from the ignoble by 
its distinctness, by its fine expression and firm 
assertion of Something; whereas the bad drawing, 
without either firmness or fineness, expresses and 
asserts Nothing. The first thing, therefore, to be 
looked for as a sign of noble art, is a clear con- 
sciousness of what is drawn and what is not; the 
bold statement, and frank confession — ‘ This I 



41 


CHAP. Ill] GREATNESS .OF STILE 

know *, ‘ that I know not and, generally speaking, 
all haste, slurring, obscurity, indecision, are signs 
of low art, and afl calmness, distinctness, luminous- 
ness, and positiveness, of high art. 

§ 18. It follows, secondly, from this principle, that 
as the great painter is always attending to tke sum 
and harmony of his truths rather than to one or the 
other of any group, a quality of Grasp is visible in 
his work, like the power of a great reasoner over 
his subject, or a great poet over his conception, 
manifesting itself very often in missing out certain 
details or less truths (which, though good in them- 
selves, he finds are in the way of others), and in 
a sweeping manner of getting the beginnings and 
ends of things shown at once, and the squares and 
depths rather than the surfaces : hence, on the 
whole, a habit of looking at large masses rather than 
small ones; and even a physical largeness of hand- 
ling, and love of working, if possible, on a large 
scale; %nd various other qualities, more or less 
imperfectly expressed by such technical terms as 
breadth, massing, unity, boldness, &c., all of which 
are, indeed, great qualities when they mean breadth 
of truth, weight of truth, unity of truth, and courage- 
ous assertion of truth; but which have all their 
correlative errors and mockeries, almost universally 
mistaken for them — ^the breadth which has no con- 
tents, the weight which has no value, the unity 
which plots deception, and the boldness which faces 
out fallacy. § 

§ 10. And it is to be noted especially respecting 
largeness of scale, that though for the most part it 
is characteristic of the more powerful masters, they 
having both more invention wherewith to fill space 
(as Ghirlandajo wished that he might paint all the 
walls of Florence), and, often, an impetuosity of 
mind which makes them like free play for hand 
and arm (besides that they usually desire to paint 
everything in the foreground of their picture of the 
natural size), yet, as this largeness of scale involves 
the placing of the picture at a considerable distance 



42 THE REAL NATURE OF [part iv: 

from the eye, and this distance involves the loss of 
many delicate details, and especially of the subtle 
lines of expression in features, it follows that the 
masters of refined detail and human expression are 
apt to prefer a small scale to work upon; so that 
the chief masterpieces of expression which the world 
possesses are small pictures by Angelico, in which 
the figures are rarely more than six or seven inches 
high; in the best works of Raphael and Leonardo the 
figures are almost always less than life, and the best 
works of Turner do not exceed the size of 18 inches 
by 12. 

§ 20. As its greatness depends on the sum of truth, 
and this sum of truth can always be increased by 
delicacy of handling, it follpws that all great art 
must have this delicacy to the utmost possible degree. 
This rule is infallible and inflexible. All coarse work 
is the sign of low art. Only, it is to be remembered, 
that coarseness must be estimated by the distance 
from the eye; it being necessary to consult this 
distance, when great, by laying on touches which 
appear coarse when seen near; but which, so far 
from being coarse, are, in reality, more delicate in a 
master’s work than the finest close handling, for 
they involve a calculation of result, and are laid 
on with a subtlety of sense precisely correspondent 
to that with which a good archer draws his bow; the 
spectator seeing in the action nothing but the strain 
of the strong arm, while there is, in reality, in the 
finger and eye, an ineffably delicate estimate of 
distance, and touch on the arrow plume. And, in- 
deed, this delicacy is generally quite perceptible to 
those who know what the truth is, for strokes by 
Tintoret or Paul Veronese, which were done in an 
instant, and look to an ignorant spectator merely 
like a violent dash of loaded colour, (and are, as 
such, imitated by blundering artists), are, in fact, 
modulated by the brush and finger to that degree of 
delicacy that no single grain of the colour could be 
taken from the touch without injury; and little 
golden particles of it, not the size of a gnat’s head. 



43 


CHAP. Ill] GREATNESS OF STILE 

have important share and function in the balances 
of light in a picture perhaps fifty feet long. Nearly 
every other rule applicable to art has soAie exception 
but this. This has absolutely none. All great art 
is delicate art, and all coarse art is bad art. Nay, 
even to a certain extent, all hold art is bad art; 
for boldness is not the proper word to apply to the 
courage and swiftness of a great master, based on 
knowledge, and coupled with fear and love. There 
is as much difference between the boldness of the 
true and the false masters, as there is between the 
courage of a pure woman and the shamelessness of 
a lost one. 

§ 21. IV. Invention. The last characteristic of 
great art is that it must be inventive, that is, be 
produced by the imagination. In this respect, it 
must precisely fulfil the definition already given of 
poetry; and not only present grounds for noble 
emotion, but furnish these grounds by imaginative 
power, • Hence there is at once a great bar fixed 
between the two schools of Lower and Higher Art. 
The lower merely copies what is set before it, 
whether in portrait, landscape, or still-life; the 
higher either entirely imagines its subject, or arranges 
the materials presented to it, so as to manifest the 
imaginative power in all the three phases which have 
been already explained in the second volume. 

And this was the truth which was confusedly 
present in Reynolds's mind when he spoke, as above 
quoted, of the difference between Historical and 
Poetical Painting. Every relation of tfie plain facts 
tvhich the painter saw is proper historical painting i. 
If those facts are unimportant (as that he saw a 
gambler quarrel with another gambler, or a sot 
enjoying himself with another sot), then the history 
is trivial; if the facts are important (as that he 
saw such and such a great man look thus, or act 
thus, at such a time), then the history is noble : 
in each case perfect truth of narrative being sup- 
posed, otherwise the whole thing is worthless, being 
^ Compare my Edinburgh Lectures, lecture ir. 



44 THE KEAL NATURE OF [part iv. 

Hither kistory nor poetry, but plain falsehood. And 
farther, as greater or less elegance and precision are 
manifested in the relation or painting of the incidents, 
the merit of the work varies; so that, what with 
difference of subject, and what with difference of 
treatment, historical painting falls or rises in change- 
ful eminence, from Dutch trivialities to a Velasquez 
|)ortrait, just as historical talking or writing varies 
in eminence, from an old woman’s story-telling up 
to Herodotus. Besides which, certain operations of 
the imagination come into play inevitably, here and 
there, so as to touch the history with some light 
of poetry, that is, with some light shot forth of the 
narrator’s mind, or brought out by the way he has 
put the accidents together : and wherever the 
imagination has thus had anything to do with the 
matter at all (and it must be somewhat cold work 
where it has not), then, the confines of the lower 
and higher schools touching each other, the work is 
oolourM by both; but there is no reason wh^, there- 
fore, we should in the least confuse the historical 
and poetical characters, any more than that we 
should confuse blue with crimson, because they may 
overlap each other, and produce purple. 

§ 22. Now, historical or simply narrative art is 
very precious in its proper place and way, but it is 
never great art until the poetical or imaginative 
power touches it; and in proportion to the stronger 
manifestation of this power, it becomes greater and 
greater, while the highest %irt is purely imaginative, 
all its materials being wrought into their form by 
invention; and it differs, the^refore, from the simple 
historical painting, exactly as Wordsworth’s stanza, 
above quoted, differs from Saussure’s plain narrative 
of the parallel fact; and the imaginative painter 
differs from the historical painter in the manner 
that Wordsworth differs from Saussure. 

§ 23. Farther, imaginative art always includes 
historical art; so that, strictly speaking, according 
to the analogy above used, we meet with the pure 
blue, and with the crimson ruling the blue and 



CHAP.ni] G-REAINjESS OF 8TY.LE. 4| 

changing it into kingly purple, but not with the pure 
crimson : for all imagination must deal with the 
knowledge it has before accumulated; it never pro- 
duces anything but by combination or contempla- 
tion. Creation, in the full sense, is impossible to 
it. And the mode in which the historical faculties 
are included by it is often quite simple, and easily, 
seen. Thus, in Hunt’s great poetical picture of the 
Light of the World, the whole thought and arrange- 
ment of the picture being imaginative, the several 
details of it are wrought out with simple portraiture ; 
the ivy, the jewels, the creeping plants, and the 
moonlight being calmly studied or remembered from 
the things themselves. But of all these special ways- 
in which the invention works with plain facts, we 
shall have to treat farther afterwards. 

§ 24. And now, finally, since this poetical power 
includes the historical, if we glance back to the 
other qualities required in great art, and put all 
together, we find that the sum of them is simply 
the sum of ^11 the powers of man. For as (1) the 
choice of the high subject involves all conditions of 
right moral choice, and as (2) the love of beauty 
involves all conditions of right admiration, and as 
(3) the grasp of truth involves all strength of sense, 
evenness of judgment, and honesty of purpose, and 
as (4) the poetical power involves all swiftness ol 
invention, and accuracy of historical memory, the 
sum of all thesie powers is the sum of the human 
soul. Hence we see why^ the word ‘ Great ’ is used 
of this art. It is literally great. It compasses and. 
calls forth the entire human spirit, whereas any 
other kind of art, being more or less small or 
harrow, compasses and calls forth only part of the* 
human spirit. Hence the idea of its magnitude is a 
literal and just one, the art being simply less or 
greater in proportion to the number of faculties it, 
exercises and addresses i. And this is the ultimate 
meaning of the definition I gave of it long ago, as con- 
taining the ‘ greatest number of the greatest ideas. ^ 

1 Compare Stones of Venice^ vol. iii, chap, iv, § 7 and § 21. 



, 46 THE KEAE NATURE OF [pabt iv. 

§ 25. Such, then, being the characters required 
in order to constitute high art, if the reader will 
think over them a little, and over the various ways 
in which they may be falsely assumed, he will easily 
perceive how spacious and dangerous a field of dis- 
cussion they open to the ambitious critic, and of 
eyror to the ambitious artist ; he will see how difficult 
it must be, either to distinguish what is truly great 
art from the mockeries of it, or to rank the real 
artists in any thing like a progressive system of 
greater and less. For it will have been observed that 
the various qualities which form greatness are partly 
inconsistent with each other (as some virtues are, 
docility and firmness for instance), and partly inde- 
pendent of each other; and the fact is, that artists 
differ not more by mere capacity, than by the com- 
ponent elements of their capacity, each possessing in 
very different proportions the several attributes of 
greatness; so that, classed by one kind of merit, as, 
for instance, purity of expression, Angelico will stand 
highest; classed by another, sincerity of manner, 
Veronese will stand highest; classed by another, love 
of beauty, Leonardo will stand highest; and so on : 
hence arise continual disputes and misunderstandings 
among those who think that high art must always 
be one and the same, and that great artists ought 
to unite all great attributes in an equal degree. 

§ 26. In one of the exquisitely finished tales of 
Marmontel, a company of critics are received at 
dinner by the hero of the<,story, an old gentleman, 
somewhat vE^in of his acquired taste, and his niece, 
by whose incorrigible natural taste, he is seriously 
disturbed and tormented. During the entertainment, 
‘ On parcourut tous les genres de litt^rature, et pour 
donner plus d’essor k I’irudition et k la critique, on 
mit Bur le tapis cette question toute neuve, SQavoir, 
lequel m^ritoit la pr^f^rence de Corneille ou de Racine. 
L’on disoit meme Ik-dessus les plus belles choses du 
monde, lorsque la petite nikce, qui n’avoit pas dit un 
mot, s’avisa de demander naivement lequel des deux 
fruits, de I’orange ou de la peche, avoit le gofit le plus 



CHAP, in] GKEATNESS OF STYLE 47 

cxquis et m^ritoit le plus d’^loges. Son oncle rougit 
de sa simplicity, et les convives baisserent tous les 
yeux sans daigner rypondre k cette b^tise. Ma ni^ce, 
dit Fintac, k votre age, il faut SQavoir ycouter, et se 
taire.’ 

I cannot close this chapter with shorter or better 
advice to the reader, than merely, whenever he hears 
discussions about the relative merits of great masters, 
to remember the young lady’s question. It is, in- 
deed, true that there is a relative merit, that a peach 
is nobler than a hawthorn berry, and still more a 
hawthorn berry than a bead of the nightshade; but 
in each rank of fruits, as in each rank of masters, 
one is endowed with one virtue, and another with 
another; their glory is their dissimilarity, and they 
who propose to themselves in the training of an artist 
that he should unite the colouring of Tintoret, the 
finish of Albert Diirer, and the tenderness of Cor- 
reggio, are no wiser than a horticulturist would be, 
who made it the object of his labour to produce a 
fruit which should unite in itself the lusciousness of 
the grape, the crispness of the nut, and the fragrance 
of the pine., 

§ 27. And from these considerations one most 
important practical corollary is to be deduced, with 
the good help of Mademoiselle Agathe’s simile, 
namely, that the greatness or smallness of a man 
is, in the most conclusive sense, determined for him 
at his birth, as strictly as it is determined for a 
fruit whether it is to be* a currant or an apricot. 
Education, favourable circumstances, reiffolution, and 
industry can do much; in a certain sense they do 
every thing; that is to say, they determine whether 
the poor apricot shall fall in the form of a green 
bead, blighted by the east wind, and be trodden 
under foot, or whether it shall expand into tender 
pride, and sweet brightness of golden velvet. But 
apricot out of currant — great man oilt of small— 
did never yet art or effort make; and, in a general 
way, men have their excellence nearly fixed tor 
them when they are born; a little cramped and 



OF THE FAliSE IDEAL [part iv> 

'■fi^ost-bitten on one side, a little sun-bumt and for-' 
tune-spotted on the other, they reach, between good 
and evil chances, such size and taste as generally 
belong to the men of their calibre, and, the small 
in their serviceable bunches, the great in their 
golden isolation, have, these no cause for regret, nor 
those for disdain. 

§ 28. Therefore it is, that every system of teach- 
ing is false which holds forth ‘ great art ’ as in any 
wise to be taught to students, or even to be aimed 
at by them. Great art is precisely that which never 
was, nor will be taught, it is pre-eminently and finally 
the expression of the spirits of great men; so that 
the only wholesome teaching is that which simply 
endeavours to fix those characters of nobleness in 
the pupil’s mind, of which it seems easily suscept- 
ible; • and without holding out to him, as a possible 
or even probable result, that he should ever paint 
like Titian, or carve like Michael Angelo, enforces 
upon him the manifest possibility, and assured duty, 
of endeavouring to draw in a manner at least honest 
and intelligible; and cultivates in him those general 
charities of heart, sincerities of thought, and graces 
of habit which are likely to lead him, throughout 
life, to prefer openness to affectation, realities to 
shadows, and beauty to corruption. 


CHAPTER IV 

OF Trik FALSE IDEAL *, FIRST, RELIGIOUS 

§ 1. Having now gained some general notion of 
the meaning of ‘ great art ’, we may, without risk 
of confusing ourselves, take up thei questions sug-J 
gested, incidentally in the preceding chapter, and 
pursue them at leisure. Of these, two principal 
ones are closely connected with each other, to wit, 
that put in the 12th paragraph — How may beauty 
be sought in defiance of truth? and that in the 
28rd paragraph — How does the imagination show; 



I. REUGIOUS 


CHAP. IV] 

itself in dealing with truth? These two, 
which are, besides, the most important of allTanu? 
if well answered, will answer many others inclusively, 
we shall find it most convenient to deal with at 
once. 

§ 2. The pursuit, by the imagination, of beautiful 
and strange thoughts or subjects, to the exclusiqii; of 
painful or common ones, is called among us, in tftlie 
modern days, the pursuit of ‘ the ideal not d^es 
any subject deserve more attentive examination than 
the manner in which this pursuit is entered upon by 
the modem mind. The reader must pardon me for 
making in the outset one or two statements which 
may appear to him somewhat wide of the matter, 
but which, (if he admits their truth), he ■will, I 
think, presently perceive to reach to the root of it. 
Namely, 

That men’s proper business in this world falls 
mainly into three divisions : 

First, to know themselves, and the existing state 
of the things they have to do with. 

Secondly, to be happy in themselves, and in the 
existing state of things. 

Thirdly, to mend themselves, and the existing state 
of things, as far as either are marred and mendable. 

These, I say, are the three plain divisions of 
proper human business on this earth. For these 
three, the following are usually substituted and 
adopted by human creatures : 

First, to be totally igncj^ant of themselves, and the 
existing state of things. • 

Secondly, to be miserable in themselves, and in 
the existing state of things. 

Thirdly, to let themselves, and the existing state 
of things, alone (at least, in the way of correction). 

§ 3. The dispositions which induce us to manage, 
thus wisely, the affairs of this life seem to be : 

First, a fear of disagreeable facts, and conscious 
shrinking from clearness of light, which keep us 
from examining ourselves, and increase gradually 
into a species of instinctive terror at all truth, and 

M. P.,111. E • 



OF THE FALSE IDEAL [part iv 

love of glosses, veils, and decorative lies of every 
sort, 

Secondly, a general readiness to take delight in 
anything past, future, far off, or somewhere else, 
rather than in things now, near, and here; leading 
us gradually to place our pleasure principally in 
the exercise of the imagination, and to build all our 
Satisfaction on things as they are not. Which power 
being one not accorded to the lower animals, and 
having indeed, when disciplined, a very noble use, 
we pride ourselves upon it, whether disciplined or 
not, and pass our lives complacently, in substantial 
discontent, and visionary satisfaction. 

§ 4. Now nearly all artistical and poetical seeking 
after the ideal is only one branch of this base habit 
^the abuse of the imagination, in allowing it to 
find its whole delight in the impossible and untrue; 
while the faithful pursuit of the ideal is an honest 
use of the imagination, giving full power and 
presence to the possible and true. 

It is the difference between these two uses of it 
which we have to examine. 

§ 6. And, first, consider what are the legitimate 
uses of the imagination, that is to say, of the power 
of perceiving, or conceiving with the mind, things 
which cannot be perceived by the senses. 

Its first and noblest use is, to enable us to bring 
sensibly to our sight the things which are recorded 
as belonging to our future state, or as invisibly 
surrounding us in this. It is given us, that we may 
imagine the <cloud of witnesses in heaven and earth, 
and see, as if they were n^w present, the souls of 
the righteous waiting for us; that we may conceive 
the great army of the inhabitants of heaven, and 
discover among them those whom we most desire 
to be with for ever; that we may be able to vision 
forth the ministry of angels beside us, and see the 
chariots of fire on the mountains that gird us round; 
but, above all, to call up the scenes and facts in 
which we are commanded to believe, and be present, 
as if in the body, at every recorded event of the 



I. BELIGIOUS 


CHAP. IV] 


51 


history of the Redeemed. Its second and ordinary 
use is to empower us to traverse the scenes of all 
other history, and force the facts to become again 
visible, so as to make upon us the same impression 
which they would have made if we had witnessed 
them : and in the minor necessities of life, to enable 
us, out of any present good, to gather the utmost 
measure of enjoyment by investing it with happy 
associations, and, in any present evil, to lighten it, 
by summoning back the images of other hours; and, 
also, to give to all mental truths some visible type 
in allegory, simile, or personification, which shall 
more deeply enforce them; and, finally, when the 
mind is utterly outwearied, to refresh it with such 
innocent play as shall be most in harmony with 
the suggestive voices of natural things, permitting it 
to possess living companionship instead of silent 
beauty, and create for itself fairies in the grass, and 
naiads in the wave, 

§ 6., These being the uses of imagination, its 
abuses are either in creating, for mere pleasure, false 
images, where it is its duty to create true ones; 
or in turning what was intended for the mere refresh- 
ment of the heart into its daily food, and changing 
the innocent pastime of an hour into the guilty 
occupation of a life. 

Let us examine the principal forms of this misuse, 
one by one. 

§ 7. First, then, the imagination is chiefly warped 
and dishonoured by bei:i|g allowed to create false 
images, where it is its duty to create trufe ones. And 
this most dangerously in matters of religion. For 
a long time, when art was in its infancy, it remained 
unexposed to this danger, because it could not, with 
any power, realize or create any thing. It consisted 
merely in simple outlines and pleasant colours ; 
which were understood to be nothing more than 
signs of the thing thought of, a sort of pictorial 
letter for it, no more pretending to represent it than 
the written characters of its name. Such art excited 
the imagination, while it pleased the eye. But it 



OF THE FALSE IDEAL [part iv 

aasertBd nothing, for it could realize nothing. The 
reader glanced at it as a glittering symbol, and went 
on to form truer images for himself. This act of 
the mind may be still seen in daily operation in 
children, as they look at brightly coloured pictures 
in their story-books. Such pictures neither deceive 
them nor satisfy them; they only set their own 
inventive powers to work in the directions required. 

§ 8. But as soon as art obtained the power of 
realization, it obtained also that of assertion. As 
fast as the painter advanced in skill he gained also 
in credibility, and that which he perfectly repre- 
sented was perfectly believed, or could be disbelieved 
qnly l^y an actual effort of the beholder to escape 
from the fascinating deception. What had been 
faintly declared, might be painlessly denied; but it 
was difficult to discredit things forcibly alleged; and 
representations, which had been innocent in dis- 
crepancy, became guilty in consistency. 

§ 9. For instance, when in the thirteenth Qentury, 
the Nativity was habitually represented by such a 
symbol as in fig. 1, Plate A, there was not the 
smallest possibility that such a picture could dis- 
turb, in the mind of the reader of the New Testa- 
ment, the simple meaning of the w’ords ‘ wrapped 
Him in swaddling clothes, and laid Him in a manger.’ 
That this manger was typified by a trefoiled arch ^ 
would no more prevent his distinct understanding 
of the narrative, than the grotesque heads intro- 
duced above it would interfere with his firm com- 
prehension di the words ‘ ox ’ or ‘ ass ’ ; while if 
there were anything in the action of the principal 
figures suggestive of real feeling, that suggestion 
he would accept, together with the general pleasant- 
ness of the lines and colours in the decorative letter; 

J The curious inequality of the little trefoil is not a mistake ; 
it is faithfully copied by the draughtsman from the MS. Per- 
hap • the actual date of the illumination may be a year or two 
past the thirteenth century, i.e. 1300— -1310 ; but it is quite 
characteristic of the thirteenth century treatment in the 
figures. 




//Al 


I’i-Ali. A 


iyh( c />. 





CHAP. IV] I. BELIGIOUS 58 

but T^thout having his faith in the unrepresented 
and actual scene obscured for a moment. But it 
was far otherwise, when Francia or Perugino, with 
exquisite power of representing the human form, 
and high knowledge of the mysteries of art, devoted 
all their skill to the delineation of an impossible 
scene; and painted, for their subjects of the 
Nativity, a beautiful and queenly lady, her dress 
embroidered with gold, and with a crown of jewels 
upon her hair, kneeling, on a floor of inlaid and 
precious marble, before a crowned child, laid under 
a portico of Lombardic i architecture; with a sweet, 
verdurous, and vivid landscape in the distance, full 
of winding rivers, village spires, and baronial 
towers 2. It is quite true that the frank absurdity 
of the thought prevented its being received as a 
deliberate contradiction of the truths of Scripture; 
but it is no less certain, that the continual present- 
ment to the mind of this beautiful and fully realized 
imager^ more and more chilled its power of appre- 
hending the real truth; and that when pictures of 
this description met the eye in every corner of every 
chapel, it was physically impossible to dwell dis- 
tinctly upon facts the direct reverse of those repre- 
sented. The word ‘ Virgin ’ or ‘ Madonna instead 
of calling up the vision of a simple Jewish girl, bear- 
ing the calamities of poverty, and the dishonours of 
inferior station, summoned instantly the idea of a 
graceful princess, crowned with gems, and sur- 
rounded by obsequious lilinistry of kings and saints. 
The fallacy which was presented to the imagination 
was indeed discredited, but also the fact which was 
not presented to the imagination was forgotten; all 
true grounds of faith were gradually undermined, 
and the beholder was either enticed into mere luxury 
of fanciful enjoyment, believing nothing; or left, in 

1 Lombardic, i.e. in the style of Pietro and Tullio Lombardo, 
in the fifteenth century (not Lombard), 

All this, it will be observed, is that seeking for beauty at 
the cost of truth which we have generally noted in the last 
chapter, f 



64 OF THE FALSE IDEAL [part iv 

his confusion of mind, the prey of vain tales and 
traditions; while in his best feelings he was uncon- 
Bciously subject to the power of the fallacious pic- 
ture, and, with no sense of the real cause of his 
error, bowed himself, in prayer or adoration, to the 
lovely lady on her golden throne, when he would 
never have dreamed of doing so to the Jewish girl 
in her outcast poverty, or, in her simple household, 
to the carpenter’s wife. 

§ 10. But a shadow of increasing darkness fell upon 
the human mind as art proceeded to still more per- 
fect realization. These fantasies of the earlier 
painters, though they darkened faith, never hardened 
feeling; on the contrary, the frankness of their un- 
likelihood proceeded mainly from the endeavour on 
the part of the painter to express, not the actual 
fact, but the enthusiastic state of his own feelings 
about the fact; he covers the Virgin’s dress with 
gold, not with any idea of representing the Virgin 
as she ever was, or ever will be seen, but* with a 
burning desire to show what his love and reverence 
would think fittest for her. He erects for the stable 
a Lombardic portico, not because he supposes the 
Lombardi to have built stables in Palestine in the 
days of Tiberius, but to show that the manger in 
which Christ was laid is, in his eyes, nobler than 
the greatest architecture in the world. He fills his 
landscape with church spires and silver streams, 
not because he supposes that either were in sight 
at Bethieher^, but to renfind the beholder of the 
peaceful course and succeeding power of Christianity. 
And, regarded with due sympathy and clear under- 
standing of these thoughts of the artist, such pictures 
remain most impressive and touching, even to this 
day* I shall refer to them in future, in general 
terms, as' the pictures of the ‘ Angelican Ideal 
Angelico being the central master of the school. 

§ 11. It was far otherwise in the next step of the 
Realistic progress. The greater his powers became, 
the^ more the mind of the painter was absorbed in 
their attainment, and complacent in their display* 



I. RELIGIOUS 


55 


CHAP. IV] 

The early arts of laying on bright colours smoothly, 
of burnishing golden ornaments, or tracing, leaf by 
leaf, the outlines of flowers, were not so difficult 
as that they should materially occupy the thoughts 
of the artist, or furnish foundation for nis conceit; he 
learned these rudiments of his work without pain, 
and employed them without pride, his spirit being 
left free to express, so far as it was capable of them, 
the reaches of higher thought. But when accurate 
shade, and subtle colour, and perfect anatomy, and 
complicated perspective, became necessary to the 
work, the artist’s whole energy was employed in 
learning the laws of these, and his whole pleasure 
consisted in exhibiting them. His life was devoted, 
not to the objects of art, but to the cunning of it; 
and the sciences of composition and light and shade 
were pursued as if there were abstract good in them ; 
as if, like astronomy or mathematics, they were ends 
in themselves, irrespective of anything to be effected 
by the!n. And without perception, on the part of 
any one, of the abyss to which all were hastening, 
a fatal change of aim took place throughout the 
whole world of art. In early times art was employed 
for the display of religious facts; now, religious facts 
ivere employed for the display of art. The transi- 
tion, though imperceptible, was consummate; it 
involved the entire destiny of painting. It was 
passing from the paths of life to the paths of 

§ 12. And this change* was all the rgore fatal, be- 
cause at first veiled by an appearance of greater 
dignity and sincerity than were possessed by the 
older art. One of the earliest results of the new 
knowledge was the putting away the greater part 
of the unlikelihoods and fineries of the ancient 
pictures, and an apparently closer following of nature 
and probability. All the fantasy which I have just 
been blaming as disturbant of the simplicity of faith, 
was first subdued — ^then despised and cast aside. 
The appearances of nature were more closely followed 
in everything; and the crowned Queen-Virgin j>i 



66 OF THE FALSE IDEAL [paet iv 

Perugino sank into a simple Italian mother in 
Raphaers Madonna of the Chair. 

§ 13. Was not this, then, a healthy change? No. 
It would have been healthy if it had been effected 
with a pure motive, and the new truths would have 
been precious if they had been sought for truth’s 
sake. But they were not sought for truth’s sake, 
but for pride ’s ; and truth which is sought for display 
may be just as harmful as truth which is spoken in 
malice. The glittering childishness of the old art 
was rejected, not because it was false, but because 
it was easy; and, still more, because the painter 
had no longer any religious passion to express. He 
could think of the Madonna now very calmly, with 
no desire to pour out the treasures of earth at her 
feet, or crown her brows with the golden shafts of 
heaven. He could think of her as an available sub- 
ject for the display of transparent shadows, skilful 
tints, and scientific foreshortenings — as a fair 
woman, forming, if well painted, a pleasant piece 
of furniture for the corner of a boudoir, and best 
imagined by combination of the beauties of the 
prettiest contadinas. He could think of her, in her 
last maternal agony, with academical discrimination; 
sketch in first her skeleton, invest her, in serene 
science, with the muscles of misery and the fibres 
of sorrow; then cast the grace of antique drapery 
over the nakedness of her desolation, and fulfil, with 
studious lustre of tears and delicately painted pallor, 
the perfect type of the ‘ Mater Dolorosa ’. 

§ 14. It was thus that Raphael thought of the 
Madonna i. 

Now observe, when the subject was thus scientific- 
ally completed, it became necessary, as we have just 
said, to the full display of all the power of the artist, 
that it should in many respects be more faithfully 
imagined^ than it had been hitherto. ‘ Keeping ’, 

‘ Expression * Historical Unity ’, and such other 

1 This is one form of the sacrifice of expression to technical 
noted at the end of the 10th paragraph of the 



I. RELIGIOUS 


57 


CHAP. IV] 


requirements, were enforoed on the painter, in the 
same tone, and with the same purpose, as the purity 
of his oil and the accuracy of his perspective. He 
was told that the figure of Christ should be ‘ digni- 
fied those of the Apostles ‘ expressive \ that of the 
Virgin * modest ’, and those of children ‘ innocent 
All this was perfectly true ; and in obedience to such 
directions, the painter proceeded to manufacture 
certain arrangements of apostolic sublimity, virginal 
mildness, and infantine innocence, which, being free 
from the quaint imperfection and contradictoriness 
of the early art, were looked upon by the European 
public as true things, and trustworthy represent- 
ations of the events of religious history. The pictures 
of Francia and Bellini had been received as pleasant 
visions. But the cartoons of Raphael were received 
as representations of historical fact. 

§ 15. Now, neither they, nor any other work of 
the pejiod, were representations either of historical 
or of possible fact. They were, in the strictest sense 
of the word, ‘ compositions ’ — cold arrangements of 
propriety and agreeableness, according to academical 
formulas; the -painter never in any case making the 
slightest effort to conceive the thing as it really 
must have happened, but only to gather together 
graceful lines and beautiful faces, in such compliance 
with commonplace ideas of the subject as might ob- 
tain for the whole an * epic unity or some such 
other form of scholastic j)erfectness. 

§ 16, Take a very important instancy. 

I suppose there is no event in the whole life of 
Christ to which, in hours of doubt or fear, men turn 
with more anxious thirst to know the close facts of 
it, or with more earnest and passionate dwelling 
upon every syllable of its recorded narrative, than 
Christ’s showing Himself -to His disciples at the lake 
of Galilee. There is something pre-eminently open, 
natural, full fronting our disbelief in this manifest- 
ation. The others, recorded after the resurrection, 
were sudden, phantom-like, occurring to men in pro- 
found sorrow and wearied agitation of heart ; ; n^t. 



58 OF THE FALSE IDEAL [part iv 

it might seem, safe judges of what they saw. But 
the agitation was now over. They had gone back 
to their daily work, thinking still their business lay 
net-wards, unmeshed from the literal rope and drag. 
‘ Simon Peter saith unto them, “I go a fishing 
Th,ey say unto him, “We also go with thee’’.’ 
True words enough, and having far echo beyond those 
Galilean hills. That night they caught nothing; but 
when the morning came, in the clear light of it, be- 
hold, a figure stood on the shore. They were not 
thinking of anything but their fruitless hauls. They 
had no guess who it was. It asked them simply if 
they had caught anything. They said no. And 
it tells them to cast yet again. And John shades 
his eyes from the morning sun with his hand, to look 
who it is; and though the glinting of the sea, too, 
dazzles him, he makes out who it is, at last; and 
poor Simon, not to be outrun this time, tightens 
his fisher’s coat about him, and dashes in, over the 
nets. One would have liked to see him swim those 
hundred yards, and stagger to his knees on the 
beach. 

Well, the others get to the beach, too, in time, 
in such slow way as men in general do get, in this 
World, to its true shore, much impeded by that 
wonderful ‘ dragging the net with fishes ’; but they 
get there — seven of them in all; — first the Denier, 
and then the slowest believer, and then the quickeslj 
believer, and then the twcj. throne-seekers, and two 
more, we knpw not who. 

They sit down on the shoriJ face to face with Him, 
and eat their broiled fish as He bids. And then, to 
Peter, all dripping still, shivering, and amazed, 
staring at Christ in the sun, on the other side of the 
coal fire — thinking a little perhaps, of what hap- 
pened by another coal fire, when it was colder, and 
having had no word once changed with him by his 
Master since that look of His — to him, so amazed, 
comes the question, ‘ Simon, lovest thou me?’ Try 
to feel that a little, and think of it till it is true to 
you; and then, take up that infinite monstrosity and 



I. RELIGIOUS 


59 


CHAP, IV] 

hypocrisy — Raphael’s cartoon of the Charge to Peter* 
Note, first, the bold fallacy — ^the putting all the 
Apostles there, a mere lie to serve the Papal heresy 
of the Petrie supremacy, by putting them all in the 
background while Peter receives the charge, and 
making them all witnesses to it. Note the hand- 
somely curled hair and neatly tied sandals of the 
men who had been out all night in the sea-mists 
and on the slimy decks. Note their convenient 
dresses for going a-fishing, with trains that lie a 
yard along the ground, and goodly fringes — all made 
to match, an apostolic fishing costume Note how 
Peter especially (whose chief glory was in his wet 
coat girt about him and naked limbs) is enveloped 
in folds and fringes, so as to kneel and hold his keys 
with grace. No fire of coals at all, nor lonely moun- 
tain shore, but a pleasant Italian landscape, full of 
villas and churches, and a flock of sheep to be 
pointed at; and the whole group of Apostles, not 
round Christ, as they would have been naturally, but 
straggling away in a line, that they may all be 
shown. 

The simple truth is, that the moment we look at 
the picture we feel our belief of the whole thing taken 
away. There is, visibly, no possibility of that group 
ever having existed, in any place, or on any occasion* 
It is all a mere mythic absurdity, and faded con- 
coction of fringes, muscular arms, and curly heads 
of Greek philosophers. ^ 

§ 17* Now, the evil consequences of Jhe acceptance 
of this kind of religious idealism for true, were in- 
stant and manifold. So far as it was received and 
trusted in by thoughtful persons, it only served to 
chill all the conceptions of sacred history which they 
might otherwise have obtained. Whatever they could 
have fancied for themselves about the wild, strange, 
infinitely stern, infinitely tender, infinitely varied 
veracities of the life of Christ, was blotted out by 

1 I suppose Raphael intended a reference to Numbers xv, 
38 ; but if he did, the blue riband, or ‘ vitta \ as it is in the 
V iilgate, should have been on the larders too. 



60 


OF THE FALSE IDEAL [paex jv 

the vapid fineries of Raphael : the rough Galilean 
pilot, the orderly custom receiver, and all the ques- 
tioning wonder and fire of uneducated apostleship, 
were obscured under an antique mask of philoBophical 
faces and long robes. The feeble, subtle, suffering, 
ceaseless energy and humiliation of St Paul were 
ounfused with an idea of a meditative Hercules 
leaning on a sweeping sword ^ ; and the mighty pre- 
sences of Moses and Elias were softened by intro-- 
ductions of delicate grace, adopted from dancing 
nymphs and rising Auroras 3. 

Now, no vigorously minded religious person could 
possibly receive pleasure or help from such art as 
this; and the necessary result was the instant re- 
jection of it by the healthy religion of the world. 
Raphael ministered, with- applause, to the impious 
luxury of the Vatican, but was trampled under foot 
at once by every believing and advancing Christian 
of his own and subsequent times; and thencefor- 
ward pure Christianity and ‘ high art ’ took ^parate 
roads, and fared on, as ,b©st they might, independ- 
ently of each other. 

§ 18. But although Calvin, and Knox, and Luther, 
and their flocks, with all the hardest-headed and 
truest-hearted faithful left in Christendom, thus 
Spurned away the spurious art, and all art with it, 
(not without harm to themselves, such as a man 
must needs sustain in cutting off a decayed limb ®,) 

1 In the St Cecilia of Bologna. 

2 In the Transfiguration. Do ^ut try to believe that Moses 
and Elias are really there talking v^ith Christ. Moses in the 
loveliest heart and midst of the land which once it had been 
denied him to behold — Elijah treading the earth again, from 
which he had been swept to heaven in fire ; both now with a 
mightier message than ever they had given in life — mightier, 
in closing their own mission — mightier, in speaking to Christ 
* of His decease, which He should accomplish at Jerusalem.’ 
They, men of like passions once with us, appointed to speak to 
the Ked^eemer of His death. 

And, then, look at Raphael’s kicking gracefulnesses. 

3 Luther had no dislike of religious art on principle. Even 
the stove in his chamber was wrought with sacred subjects. 
Se^ Mrs Stowe’s Mutiny Memories, 



I. RELIGIOUS 


61 


CHAP, iv] 

certain conditions of weaker Christianity suffered 
the false system to retain influence over them; and 
to this day, the clear and tasteless poison of the art 
of Raphael infects with sleep of infidelity the hearts 
■of millions of Christians. It is the first cause of 
all that pre-eminent dulness which characterizes what 
Protestants call sacred art; a dulness not merely 
baneful in making religion distasteful to the young, 
but in sickening, as we have seen, all vital belief 
of religion in the old. A dim sense of impossibility 
attaches itself always to the graceful emptiness of 
the representation; we feel instinctively that the 
painted Christ and painted apostle are not beings 
that ever did or could exist; and this fatal sense 
of fair fabulousness, and well-composed impossibility, 
steals gradually from the picture into the history, 
until we find ourselves reading St Mark or St Luke 
with the same admiring, but uninterested, incredulity, 
with which we contemplate Raphael. 

§ 19. On a certain class of minds, however, these 
Raphadesque and other sacred paintings of high 
order, have had, of late years, another kind of in- 
fluence, much resembling that which they had at 
first on the most pious Romanists. They are used 
to excite certain conditions of religious dream or 
reverie; being again, as in earliest times, regarded 
not as representations of fact, but as expressions of 
sentiment respecting the fact. In this way the best 
of them have unquestionably much purifying and 
enchanting power; and^they are helpful opponents 
to sinful passion and weakness of every kind. A fit 
of unjust anger, petty malice, unreasonable vexation, 
or dark passion, cannot certainly, in a mind of 
ordinary sensibility, hold its own in the presence of 
a good engraving from any work of Angelico, Mem- 
ling, or Perugino. But I nevertheless believe, that 
he who trusts much to such helps will find them fail 
.him at his need; and that the dependence, in any 
^eat degree, on the presence or power of a picture, 
indicates a wonderfully feeble sense of the presence 
and power of God. I do not think that any man,* 



OF THE FALSE IDEAL [paet iv 

who is thoroughly certain that Christ is in the room, 
will care what sort of pictures of Christ he has on 
its walls; and, in the plurality of cases, the delight 
taken in art of this kind is, in reality, nothing more 
than a form of graceful indulgence of those sensi- 
bilities which the habits of a disciplined life restrain 
in pther directions. Such art is, in a word, the opera 
and drama of the monk. Sometimes it is worse than 
this, and the love of it is the mask under which a 
general thirst for morbid excitement will pass itself 
for religion. The young lady who rises in the middle 
of the day, jaded by her last night’s ball, and utterly 
incapable of any simple or wholesome religious exer- 
cise, can still gaze into the dark eyes of the Madonna 
di San Sisto, or dream over the whiteness of an 
ivory crucifix, and returns to the course of her daily 
life in full persuasion that her morning’s feverishness 
has atoned for her evening’s folly. And all the 
while, the art which possesses these very doubtful 
advantages is acting for undoubtful detriment, in 
the various ways above examined, on the ‘’inmost 
fastnesses of faith; it is throwing subtle endearments 
roimd foolish traditions, confusing sweet fancies with 
sound doctrines, obscuring real events with unlikely 
semblances, and enforcing false assertions with 
pleasant circumstantiality, until, to the usual, and 
assuredly^ sufficient, difficulties standing in the way 
of belief, its votaries have added a habit of sentiment- 
ally changing what they know to be true, and of 
dearly loving what they confess to be false. 

§ 20. Has .tihere, then (the reader asks emphatic- 
ally), been no true religious’ ideal? Has religious 
art never been of any service to mankind? I fear, 
on the whole, not. Of true religious ideal, repre- 
senting events historically recorded, with solemn 
effort at a sincere and unartificial conception, there 
exist, as yet, hardly any examples. Nearly all good 
religious pictures fall into one or other branch of 
the false ideal already examined, either into the 
Angelican ^ (passionate ideal) or the Raphaelesque 
(philosophical ideal). But there is one true form of 



L RELIGIOUS 


63 


CHAP. IV] 


religious art, nevertheless, in the pictures of the 
passionate ideal which represent imaginarv beings of 
another world. Since it is evidently right that we 
should try to imagine the glories of the next world, 
and as tnis imagination must be, in each separate 
mind, more or less different, and unconfined by any 
laws of material fact, the passionate ideal has not 
only full scope here, but it becomes our duty to 
urge its powers to its utmost, so that every condition 
of beautiful form and colour may be employed to 
invest these scenes with greater delightfulness (the 
whole being, of course, received as an assertion of 
possibility, not of absolute fact). All the paradises 
imagined by the religious painters — ^the choirs of 
glorified saints, angels, and spiritual powers, when 
painted with full belief in this possibility of their 
existence, are true ideals; and so far from our 
having dwelt on these too much, I believe, rather, 
we have not trusted them enough, nor accepted them 
enough, as possible statements of most precious 
truth, * Nothing but unmiXed good can accrue to any 
mind from the contemplation of Orcagna’s Last 
Judgment or his Triumph of Death, of Angelico’s 
Last Judgment and Paradise, or any of the scenes 
laid in heaven by the other faithful religious masters ; 
and the more they are considered, not as works of 
art, but as real visions of real things, more or less 
imperfectly set down, the more good will be got by 
dwelling upon them. The same is true of all repre- 
pentations of Christ as g living presence among us 
now, as in Hunt’s Light of the World.^ 

§ 21. For the rest, there is a reality of conception 
in some of the works of Benozzo Gozzoli, Ghirlandajo, 
and Giotto, which approaches to a true ideal, even 
of recorded facts. But the examination of the 
various degrees in which sacred art has reached its 
proper power is not to our present purpose; still 
less, to investigate the infinitely difficult question of 
its past operation on the Christian mind. I hope to 
prosecute my inquiry into this subject in another 
work; it being enough here to mark the fo^rms of 



64 OF TH^l FALSE IDEAL [papt iv 

erroi*, without historically tracing their ejttent, 
and to state generally that my impression is, up to 
the presept moment, that the best religious art has 
been hitherto rather a fruit, and attendant sign, of 
sincere Christianity than a promoter of or help to 
it. More, I think, has always been done for God 
by few words than many pictures, and more by few 
acts than many words. 

§ 22. I must not, however, quit the subject with- 
out insisting on the chief practical consequence of 
what we have observed, namely, that sacred art, so 
far from being exhausted, has yet to attain the de- 
velopement of its highest branches; and the task, 
or privilege, yet remains for mankind, to produce an 
art which shall be at once entirely skilful and entirely 
sincere. All the histories of the Bible are, in my 
judgment, yet waiting to be painted. Moses has 
never been painted; Elijah never; David never (ex- 
cept as a mere ruddy stripling); Deborah never; 
Gideon never; Isaiah never. What single example 
does the reader remember of painting which sug- 
gested so much as the faintest shadow of these people, 
or of their deeds? Strong men in armour, or aged 
men with flowing beards, he viay remember, who, 
when he looked at his Louvre or Uffizi catalogue, he 
found were intended to stand for David or for Moses, 
But does he suppose that, if these pictures had sug- 
gested to him the feeblest image of the presence of 
such men, he would have passed on, as he assuredly 
did, to the next picture- 7 -representing, doubtless, 
Diana and Actaeon, or Cupid and the Graces, or a 
gambling quarrel in a pothouse — ^with no sense of 
pain, or surprise? Let him meditate over the matter, 
and he will find ultimately that what I say is true, 
and that religious art, at once complete and sincere, 
never yet has existed, 

^ § 28. It will exist : nay, I believe the era of its 
bir& has come, and that those bright Turnerian 
imageries, which the European public declared to 
be ‘ dotage and those calm Pre-Raphaelite studies 
which, in like manner, it nronounced * puerility \ 



I. RELIGIOUS 


65 


CHAP. IV] 

form the first foundation that has been ever laid for 
true sacred art. Of this we shall presently reason 
farther. But, be it as it may, if we would cherish 
the hope that sacred art may, indeed, arise for tis, 
two separate cautions are to be addressed to the 
two opposed classes of religionists whose influence 
will chiefly retard that hope’s accomplishment. The 
group calling themselves Evangelical Ought no longer 
to render their religion an offence to men of the 
world by associating it only with the most vulgar 
forms of art. It is not necessary that they should 
admit either music or painting into religious service; 
but, if they admit either the one or the other, let it 
not be bad music nor bad painting : it is certainly 
in nowise more for Christ’s honour that His praise 
should be sung discordantly, or His miracles painted 
discreditably, than that His word should be preached 
ungrammatically. Some Evangelicals, however, 
seem to take a morbid pride in the triple degradation i. 

§ 2^. The opposite class of men, whose natural 
instincts lead them to mingle the refinements of art 
with all the offices and practices of religion, are to be 
warned, on the contrary, how they mistake their 
enjoyments for their duties, or confound poetry with 
faith. I admit that it is impossible for one man to 
judge another in this matter, and that it can never 
be said with certainty how far what seems frivolity 
may be force, and what seems the indulgence of 

1 I do not know anything more humiliating to a man of 
common sense, than to open what is called*an ‘ Illustrated 
Bible ’ of modern days. See, for instance, the plates in Brown’s 
Bible (octavo : Edinburgh, 1840), a standard evangelical edition. 
Our habit of reducing the Psalms to doggrel before we will 
condescend to sing them, is a parallel abuse. It is marvellous 
to think that human creatures with tongues and souls should 
refuse to chant the verse : ‘ Before Ephraim, Benjamin, and 
Mauasseh, stir up thy strength, and come and help us ’ : 
preferring this; — 

Behold, how Benjamin expects, , 

With Ephraim and Manasseh joined, 

In their deliverance, the effects 

Of thy resistless strength to find ! ^ 


M. P., III. 


F 



66 OF THF FALSE IDEAL [part iv 

the heart may be, indeed, its dedication, I am ready 
to believe that Metastasio, expiring in a canzonet, 
may have died better than if his prayer had been 
in unmeasured syllables But, for the most part, 
it is assuredly much to be feared lest we mistake 
a surrender to the charms of art for one to the service 
of God; and, in the art which we permit, lest we 
substitute sentiment for sense, grace for utility. And 
for us all there is in this matter even a deeper 
danger than that of indulgence. There is the danger 
of Artistical Pharisaism. Of all the forms of pride 
and vanity, as there are none more subtle, so I 
believe there are none more sinful, than those which 
are manifested by the Pharisees of art. To be proud 
of birth, of place, of wit, of bodily beauty, is com- 
paratively innocent, just because such pride is more 
natural, and more easily detected. But to be proud 
of our sanctities; to’l^our contempt upon our fellows, 
because, forsooth, we like to look at Madonnas in 
bowers of roses, better than at plain pictures *'of plain 
things; and to make this religious art of ours the 
expression of our own perpetual self-complacency — 
congratulating ourselves, day by dajr, on our purities, 
proprieties, elevations, and inspirations, as above the 
reach of common mortals — ^this I believe to be one 
of the wickedest and foolishest forms of human 
egotism; and, truly, I had rather, with great, 
thoughtless, humble Paul Veronese, make the Supper^ 
at Emmaus a background^. for two children playing 
with a dog ias, God knows, men do usually put it 

1 En 1780, &g6 de quatre-vingtJ-deux ans, au moment de 
recevoir le viatique, il rassembla ses forces, et chanta, k son 
Cr^ateur : 

Eterno Genitor 
lo t’ offro il proprio figlio 
Che in pegno del tuo amor 
Si vuole a me donar. 

A lui rivolgi il ciglio, 

Mira chi t’ offro ; e poi, 

Niega, Signor, se puoi, 

Niega di perdonar. 

^ De Stendhal, Vte de Metastasio, 



!!• PROFAKE 


67 


CHAP. V] 

in the background to everything, if not out of sight 
altogether), than join that school of modern German- 
ism which wears its pieties for decoration as women 
wear their diamonds, and flaunts the dry fleeces of 
its phylacteries between its dust and the dew of 
heaven. 


CHAPTER V 

OF THE FALSE IDEAL : SECONDLY, PROFANE 

§ 1. Such having been the effects of the pursuit 
of ideal beauty on the religious mind of Europe, we 
might be tempted next to consider in what way the 
same movement affected the art which concerned 
itself with profane subject, and, through that art, 
the whole temper of modern civilization, 

I shall, however, merely glance at this question. 
It is a yery painful and a very wide one. Its dis- 
cussion cannot come properly within the limits, or 
even within the aim, of a work like this; it ought 
to be made the subject of a separate essay, and that 
essay should be written by some one who had passed 
less of his life than I have among mountains, and 
more of it among men. But one or two points may 
be suggested for the reader to reflect upon at his 
leisure. 

§ 2, I said just now that wo might be tempted to 
consider how this pursuit® of the ideal affected pro- 
fane art. Strictly speaking, it brought that art into 
existence. As long as men sought for truth first, 
and beauty secondarily, they cared chiefly, of course, 
for the chief truth, and all art was instinctively re- 
ligious. But as soon as they Bought for beauty first, 
and truth secondarily, they were punished by losing 
sight of spiritual truth altogether, and the profane 
(properly so called) schools of art were instantly 
developed. 

The perfect human beauty, which, to a large part 
of the community, was by far the most interesting 
feature in the work of the rising school, might indeed® 



68 OF THE FALSE IDEAL [part iv 

be in some degree consistent with the agony of 
Madonnas, and the repentance of Magdalenes; but 
could not be exhibited in fulness, when the subjects, 
however irreverently treated, nevertheless demanded 
some decen^ in the artist, and some gravity in the 
i^pectator. The newly acquired powers of rounding 
limbs, and tinting lips, had too little scope in the 
sanctities even of the softest womanhood; and the 
newly acquired conceptions of the nobility of naked- 
ness could in no wise be expressed beneath the robes 
of the prelate or the sackcloth of the recluse. But 
the source from which these ideas had been received 
afforded also full field for their expression ; the 
heathen mythology, which had furnished the ex- 
amples of these heights of art, might again become 
the subject of the inspirations it had kindled; — with 
the additional advantage that it could now be de- 
lighted in, without being believed; that its errors 
might be indulged, unrepressed by its awe; and 
those of its deities whose function was temptation 
might be worshipped, in scorn of those whose hands 
were charged with chastisement. 

So, at least, men dreamed in their foolishness — 
to find, as the ages wore on, that the returning 
Apollo bore not only his lyre, but his arrows; and 
that at the instant of Cytherea’s resurrection to the 
sunshine, Persephone had reascended her throne in 
the deep. 

§ 3. Little thinking thig, they gave themselves up 
fearlessly tw the chase of the new delight, and ex- 
hausted themselves in the pursuit of an ideal now 
doubly false. Formerly, though they attempted to 
reach an unnatural beauty, it was yet in representing 
historical facts and real persons; now they sought 
for the same unnatural beauty in representing tales 
which they knew to be fictitious, and personages 
who they knew had never existed. Such a state of 
^ings had never before been found in any nation. 
Every people^ till then had painted the acts of their 
kings, the triumphs of their armies, the beauty of 
their race, or the glory of their gods. They showed 



II. PROFANE 


CHAP. V] 


69 


the things they had seen or done; -the beings they 
truly loved or faithfully adored. But the ideal art 
of modem Europe was the shadow of a shadow; 
and, with mechanism substituted for perception, and 
bodily beauty for spiritual life, it set itself to repre- 
sent men it had never seen, customs it had never 
practised, and gods in whom it had never believed. 

§ 4. Such art could of course have no help from 
the virtues, nor claim on the energies of men. It 
necessarily rooted itself in their vices and their idle- 
ness; and of their vices principally in two, pride 
and sensuality. To the pride, was attached emi- 
nently the art of architecture; to the sensuality, 
those of painting and sculpture. Of the fall of 
architecture, as resultant from the formalist pride 
of its patrons and designers, I have spoken else- 
where. The sensualist ideal, as seen in painting and 
sculpture, remains to be examined here. But one 
interestiig circumstance is to be observed with 
respect to the manner of the separation of these 
arts. Pride, being wholly a vice, and in every 
phase inexcusable, wholly betrayed and destroyed the 
art w’hich was founded on it. But passion, having 
some root and use in healthy nature, and only be- 
coming guilty in excess, did not altogether destroy 
the art founded upon it. The architecture of Pal- 
ladio is wholly virtueless and despicable. Not so 
the Venus of Titian, nor the Antiope of Correggio. 

§ 5. We find, then, ah the close of the sixteenth 
century, the arts of painting and sculpture wholly 
devoted to entertain the indolent and satiate the 
luxurious. To eft'ect these noble ends, they took 
a thousand different forms; painting, however, of 
course being the most complying, aiming sometimes 
at mere amusement by deception in landscapes, or 
minute imitation of natural objects; sometimes 
giving more piquant excitement in battle-pieces full of 
slaughter, or revels deep in drunkenness; sometimes 
entering upon serious subject, for the sake of 
potesque fiends and picturesque infernos, or that 
it might introduce pretty children as cherubs, anjj 



Ill OF THE FALSE IDEAL [part iv 

handsome women as Magdalenes, and Maries of 
Egypt, or portraits of patrons in the character of the 
more decorous saints : but more frequently, for 
direct flatteries of this kind, recurring to Pagan 
mythology, and painting frail ladies as goddesses or 
graces, and foolish kings in radiant apotheosis; while, 
for the earthly delict of the persons whom it 
honoured as divine, it ransacked the records of lusci- 
ous fable, and brought back, in fullest depth of dye 
and flame of fancy, the impurest dreams of the un- 
Christian ages. 

§ 6. Meanwhile, the art of sculpture, less capable 
of ministering to mere amusement, was more or less 
reserved for the affectations of taste; and the study 
of the classical statues introduced various ideas on 
the subjects of ‘ purity * chastity and ‘ dignity 
such as it was possible for people to entertain who 
were themselves impure, luxurious, and ridiculous. 
It is a matter of extreme difficulty to expjain the 
exact character of this modern sculpturesque ideal; 
but its relation to the true ideal may be best under- 
stood by considering it as in exact parallelism with 
the relation of the word ‘ taste ’ to the word * love *. 
Wherever the word ‘ taste ' is used with respect to 
matters of art, it indicates either that the thing 
spoken of belongs to some inferior class of objects, 
or that the person speaking has a false conception 
of its nature. For, consider the exact sense in which 
a work of art is said to bq.‘ in good or bad taste 
It does not jpean that it is true, or false; that it is 
beautiful, or ugly : but that it does or does not 
comply either with the laws of choice, which are 
enforced by certain modes of life; or the habits of 
mind produced by a particular sort of education. It 
does not mean merely fashionable, that is, complying 
with a momentary caprice of the upper classes; but 
it means agreeing with the habitual sense which the 
most refined education, common to those upper 
classes at the period, gives to their whole mind. 
Now, therefore, so far as that education does indeed 
tend to make the senses delicate, and the percep- 



II. PROFANE 


71 


OHAP. V] 

tions accurate, and thus enables people to be pleased 
with quiet instead of gaudy colour, and with graceful 
instead of coarse form; and,. by long acquaintance 
with the best things, to discern quickly what is fine 
from what is common; so far, acquired taste is an 
honourable faculty, and it is true praise of anything 
to say it is ‘ in good taste But so far as this 
higher education has a tendency to narrow the sym- 
pathies and harden the heart, diminishing the interest 
of all beautiful things by familiarity, until e\en what 
is best can hardly please, and what is brightest hardly 
entertain; so far as it fosters pride, and leads men 
to found the pleasure they take in anything, not on 
the worthiness of the thing, but on the degree in 
which it indicates some greatness of their own (as 
people build marble porticoes, and inlay marble floors, 
not so much because they like the colours of marble, 
or find it pleasant to the foot, as because such porches 
and floors are costly, and separated in all human 
eyes from plain entrances of stone and timber); so 
far as it leads people to prefer gracefulness of dress, 
manner, and aspect, to value of substance and heart, 
liking a well mid thing better than a true thing, 
and a well-trained manner better than a sincere one, 
and a delicately formed face better than a good- 
natured one, and in all other ways and things set- 
ting custom and semblance above everlasting truth; 
so far, finally, as it induces a sense of inherent dis- 
tinction between class ^d class, and causes every- 
thing to be more or less despised which Jias no social 
rank, so that the affection, pleasure, or grief of a 
clown are looked upon as of no interest compared 
with the affection and grief of a well-bred man; just 
so far, in all these several ways, the feeling induced 
by what is called a * liberal education ’ is utterly 
adverse to the understanding of noble art; and the 
name which is given to the feeling — Taste, Gofit, 
Gusto — in all languages, indicates the baseness of 
it, for it implies that art gives only a kind of pleasure 
analogous to that derived from eating by the palate. 

§ 7. Modern education, not in art only, but in all 



OF THE FALSE IDEAL [part iv 

otLer things referable to the same standard, has in- 
variably given taste in this bad sense; it has given 
fastidiousness of choice without judgment, super- 
ciliousness of manner without dignity, refinement of 
habit without purity, grace of expression without sin- 
cerity, and desire of loveliness without love; and the 
mbdern ‘ ideal ’ of high art is a curious mingling of 
the gracefulness and reserve of the drawingroom with 
a certain measure of classical sensuality. Of this last 
element, and the singular artifices by which vice 
succeeds in combining it with what appears to be 

? ure and severe, it would take us long to reason fully; 

would rather leave the reader to follow out for 
himself the consideration of the influence, in this 
direction, of statues, bronzes, and paintings, as at 
present employed by the upper circles of London, and 
(especially) Paris ; and this not so much in the works 
which are really fine, as in the multiplied coarse 
copies of them; taking the widest range, fropi Dan- 
naeker’s Ariadne down to the amorous shepherd and 
shepherdess in china on the drawing-room time-piece, 
rigidly questioning, in each case, how far the charm 
of the art does indeed depend on some appeal to the 
inferior passions. Let it be considered, for instance, 
exactly how far the value of a picture of a girl’s 
head by Greuze would be lowered in the market, if 
the dress, which now leaves the bosom bare, were 
raised to the neck; and how far, in the commonest 
lithograph of some utterly popular subject — for in- 
stance, the teaching of Uncle Tom by Eva — the 
sentiment which is supposed- to he excited by the 
exhibition of Christianity in youth is complicated with 
that which depends upon Eva’s having a dainty foot 
and a well-made satin slipper; and then, having com- 
pletely determined for himself how far the element 
exists, consider farther, whether, when art is thus 
frequent (for frequent he will assuredly find it to be) 
in its appeal to the lower passions, it is likely to 
attain the highest order of merit, or be judged by 
the truest standards of judgment. For, of all the 
causes which have combined, in modern times, to 



II. PROFANE 


73 


CHAP. V] 

lower the rank of art, I believe this to be one of 
the most fatal; while, reciprocally, it may be ques- 
tioned how far society suffers, in its turn, from the 
influences possessed over it by the arts it has de- 
graded. It seems to me a subject of the very deepest 
interest to determine what has been the effect upon 
the European nations of the great change by which 
art became again capable of ministering delicately to 
the lower passions, as it had in the worst days of 
Rome; how far, indeed, in all ages, the fall of 
nations may be attributed to art’s arriving at this 
particular stage among them. I do not mean that, 
in any of its stages, it is incapable of being employed 
for evil, but that assuredly an Egyptian, Spartan, or 
Norman was unexposed to the kind of temptation 
which is continually offered by the delicate painting 
and sculpture of modern days; and, although the 
diseased imagination might complete the imperfect 
image ^of beauty from the coloured image on the 
wall 1, or the most revolting thoughts be suggested 
by the mocking barbarism of the Gothic sculpture, 
their hard outline and rude execution were free from 
all the subtle treachery which now fills the flushed 
canvass and the rounded marble. 

§ 8. I cannot, however, pursue this inquiry here. 
For our present purpose it is enough to note that the 
feeling, in itself so debased, branches upwards into 
that of which, while no one has cause to be ashamed, 
no one, on the other hand, has cause to be proud, 
namely, the admiration of physical beauty in the 
human form, as distinguished from expression of 
character. Every one can easily appreciate the merit 
of regular features and well-formed limbs, but it 
requires some attention, sympathy, and sense, to 
detect the charm of passing expression, or life-dis- 
ciplined character. The beauty of the Apollo Belvi- 
dere, or Venus de Medicis, is perfectly palpable to 
any shallow fine lady or fine gentleman, though they 
would have perceived none in the face of an old 
weather-beaten St Peter, or a grey-haired ‘ Grand- 
1 Ezek,, xxiii, 14. • 



OF THE FALSE IDEAL [part iv 

mother Loie The knowledge that long study is 
necessary to produce these regular types of the 
human form renders the facile admiration matter of 
eager self-complacency; the shallow spectator, de- 
lighted that he can really, and without hypocrisy, 
aojnire what required much thought to produce, sup- 
poses himself endowed with the highest critical facul- 
ties, and easily lets himself be carried into rhapsodies 
about the ‘ ideal ’, which, when all is said, if they be 
accurately examined, will be found literally to mean 
nothing more than that the figure has got handsome 
calves to its legs, and a straight nose. 

§ 9. That they do mean, in reality, nothing more 
than this may be easily ascertained by watching the 
taste of the same persons in other things. The 
fashionable lady who will write five or six pages in 
her diary respecting the effect upon her mind of such 
and sucn an ‘ ideal * in marble, will have her draw- 
ingroom table covered with Books of Beauty, iq which 
the engravings represent the human form in every 
possible aspect of distortion and affectation; and 
the connoisseur who, in the morning, pretends to 
the most exquisite taste in the antique, will be seen, 
in the evening, in his opera-stall, applauding the 
least graceful gestures of the least modest figurante. 

§ 10. But even this vulgar pursuit of physical 
beauty (vulgar in the profoundest sense, for there is 
no vulgarity like the vulgarity of education) would be 
less contemptible if it reallju succeeded in its object; 
but, like all pursuits carried to inordinate length, it 
defeats itself. Physical beauty is a noble thing when 
it is seen in perfectness; but the manner in which 
the moderns pursue their ideal prevents their ever 
really seeing what they are always seeking; for, 
requiring that all forms should be regular and fault- 
less, they permit, or even compel, their painters and 
sculptors to work chiefly by rule, altering their 
models to fit their preconceived notions of what 
is right. When such artists look at a face, they do 
not give it the attention necessary to discern what 
b^^auty is already in its peculiar features; but only 



II. PROFAlJE 


78 


CHAP. V] 

to see how best it mey be altered into something for 
which they have themselves laid down the laws. 
Nature never unveils her beauty to such a gaze. She 
keeps whatever she has done best, close sealed^ until 
it is regarded with reverence. To the painter who 
honours her, she will open a revelation in the face of 
a street mendicant; but in the work of the painter 
who alters her, she will make Portia become ignoble, 
and Perdita graceless. 

§ 11. Nor is the effect less for evil on the mind of 
the general observer. The lover of ideal beauty, with 
all his conceptions narrowed by rule, never looks care- 
fully enough upon the features which do not come 
under his law (or any others), to discern the inner 
beauty in them. The strange intricacies about the 
lines of the lips, and marvellous shadows and watch- 
fires of the eye, and wavering traceries of the eye- 
lash, and infinite modulations of the brow, wherein 
high humanity is embodied, are all invisible to him. 
He finds himself driven back at last, with all his 
idealism, to the lionne of the ball-room, whom youth 
and passion can as easily distinguish as his utmost 
critical science ; whereas, the observer who has accus- 
tomed himself to take human faces as God made 
them, will often find as much beauty on a village 
green as in the proudest room of state, and as much 
in the free seats of a church aisle, as in all the sacred 
paintings of the Vatican or the Pitti. 

§ 12. Then, farther, iiie habit of disdaining ordin- 
ary truth, and seeking to alter it so %s to fit the 
fancy of the beholder, gradually infects the mind in 
all its other operation; so that it begins to propose 
to itself an ideal in history, an ideal in general narra- 
tion, an ideal in portraiture and description, and in 
every thing else where truth may be painful or unin- 
teresting; with the necessary result of more or less 
weakness, wickedness, and uselessness in all that is 
done or said, with the desire of concealing this pain- 
ful truth. And, finally, even when truth is not inten- 
tionally concealed, the pursuer of idealism will pass 
his days in false and useless trains of thought, plum- 



#6 OF THE FALSE IDEAL [part iv 

ing himself, all the while, upon his superiority therein 
to the rest of mankind. A modern German, without 
either invention or sense, seeing a rapid in a river, 
will immediately devote the remainder of the day to 
the composition of dialogues between amorous water 
nymphs and unhappy mariners; while the man of 
true invention, power, and sense will, instead, set 
himself to consider whether the rocks in the river 
could have their points knocked off, or the boats 
upon it be made with stronger bottoms. 

§ 13. Of this final baseness of the false ideal, its 
miserable waste of the time, strength, and available 
intellect of man, by turning, as I have said above, 
iimocenoe of pastime into seriousness of occupation, 
it is, of course, hardly possible to sketch out even 
so much as the leading manifestations. The vain and 
haughty projects of youth for future life; the giddy 
reveries of insatiable self-exaltation ; the discontented 
dreams of what might have been or should tbe, in- 
stead of the thankful understanding of what is; the 
casting about for sources of interest in senseless fic- 
tion, instead of the real human histories of the people 
round us ; the prolongation from age to age of 
romantic historical deceptions instead of sifted truth; 
the pleasures taken in fanciful portraits of rural or 
romantic life in poetry and on the stage, without the 
smallest effort to rescue the living rural population 
of the world from its ignorance or misery; the ex- 
citement of the feelings by •laboured imagination of 
spirits, fairie^, monsters, and ^emons, issuing in total 
blindness of heart and sight to the true presences of 
beneficent or destructive spiritual powers around us; 
in fine, the constant abandonment of all the straight- 
forward paths of sense and duty, for fear of losing 
some of the enticement of ghostly joys, or trampling 
somewhat ‘ sopra lor vanit^, che par persona ’; all 
these various forms of false idealism have so en- 
tangled the modern mind, often called, I suppose 
ironically, practical, that truly I believe there never 
yet was idolatry of stock or staff so utterly unholy 
sfe this our idolatry of shadows ; nor can I think that. 



77 


CHAP.vi] OF THE TRUE IDEAL 

of those who burnt incense under oaks, and poplars, 
and elms, because ‘ the shadow thereof was good 
it could in any wise be more justly or sternly 
declared than of us — ‘ The wind hath bound them 
up in her wings, and they shall be ashamed because 
of their sacrifices. i ’ 


CHAPTER VI 

OF THE TRUE IDEAL : FIRST, PURIST 

§ 1. Having thus glanced at the principal modes 
in which the imagination works for evil, we must 
rapidly note also the principal directions in which its 
operation is admissible, oven in changing or strangely 
combining what is brought within its sphere. 

For hitherto we have spoken as if every change 
wilfuUy wrought by the imagination was an error; 
apparently implying that its only proper work was 
to summon up the memories of past events, and the 
anticipations of future ones, under aspects which 
would bear the sternest tests of historical investiga- 
tion, or abstract reasoning. And in general this is, 
indeed, its noblest work. Nevertheless, it has also 
permissible functions peculiarly its own, and certain 
rights of feigning, adorning, and fancifully arrang- 
ing, inalienable from its nature. Everything that is 
natural is, within certsBln limits, right; and we must 
take care not, in over-severity, to deprive ourselves 
of any refreshing or animating power ordained to be 
in us for our help. 

§ 2, (A). It was noted in speaking above of the 
Angelican or passionate ideal, that there was a cer- 
tain virtue in it dependent on the expression of its 
loving enthusiasm (Chap. IV, § 10). 

(B). In speaking of the pursuit of beauty as one 
of the characteristics of the highest art, it was also 
said that there were certain ways of showing this 

1 Hosea, chap, iv, 12, 13 and 19. 



Ift OF THE TRUE IDEAL [past iv 

beauty by gathering together, without altering, the 
finest forms, and marking them by gentle emphasis 
(Chap. Ill, § 15). 

(C). And in speaking of the true uses of imagina- 
tion it was said, that we might be allowed to create 
for ourselves, in innocent play, fairies and naiads, 
and other such fictitious creatures (Chap. IV, § 5). 

Now this loving enthusiasm, which seeks for a 
beauty fit to be the object of eternal love; this in- 
ventive skill, which kindly displays what exists 
around us in the world; and this playful energy of 
thought which delights in various conditions of the 
impossible, are three forms of idealism more or less 
connected with the three tendencies of the artistical 
mind which I had occasion to explain in the chapter 
on the Nature of Gothic, in the Stones of Venice, It 
was there pointed out, that, the things around us 
containing mixed good and evil, certain men chose 
the good and left the evil (thence properly called 
Purists) ; others received both good and evil together 
(thence properly called Naturalists); and others had 
a tendency to choose the evil and leave the good, 
whom, for convenience’ sake, I termed Sensualists. 
I do not mean to say that painters of fairies and 
naiads must belong to this last and lowest class, or 
habitually choose the evil and leave the good; but 
there is, nevertheless, a strange connection between 
the reinless play of the imagination, and* a sense of 
the presence of evil, which usually more or less 
developed in Jihose creations of the imagination to 
which we properly attach the word Grotesque, 

For this reason, we shall find it convenient to 
arrange what we have to note respecting true idealism 
under the three heads 

A. Purist Idealism 

B. Naturalist Idealism 

C. Grotesque Idealism. 

§ 3. (A). Purist Idealism. It results from the un- 
willingness of men whose dispositions are more than 
ordinarily tender and holy, to contemplate the vari- 
ous forms of definite evil which necessarily occur in 



I. PURIST 


70 


CHAP. Vl] 

the daily aspects of the world around them. They 
shrink from them as from pollution, and endeavour 
to create for themselves an imaginary state, in which 
pain and imperfection either do not exist, or exist 
in some edgeless and enfeebled condition. 

As, however, pain and imperfection are, by eternal 
laws, bound up with existence, so far as it is visible 
to us, the endeavour to cast them away invariably 
indicates a comparative childishness of mind, and 
produces a childish form of art. In general, the 
effort is most successful when it is most naive, and 
when the ignorance of the draughtsman is in some 
frank proportion to his innocence. For instance, one 
of the modes of treatment, the most conducive to 
this ideal expression, is simply drawing everything 
without shadows, as if the sun were everywhere at 
once. This, in the present state of our knowledge, 
we could not do with grace, because we could not 
do it without fear or shame. But an artist of the 
thirteeifth century did it with no disturbance of con- 
science — ^knowing no better, or rather, in some sense, 
we might say, knowing no worse. It is, however, 
evident, at the first thought, that all representations 
of nature without evil must either be ideals of a 
future world, or be false ideals, if they are under- 
stood to be representations of facts. They can only 
be classed among the branches of the true ideal, in 
BO far as they are understood to be nothing more 
than expressions of the painter’s personal affections 
or hopes. ^ 

§ 4. Let us take one or two instances in order 
clearly to explain our meaning. 

The life of Angelico was almost entirely spent in 
the endeavour to imagine the beings belonging to 
another world. By purity of life, habitual elevation 
of thought, and natural sweetness of disposition, he 
was enabled to express the sacred affections upon 
the human countenance as no one ever did before 
or since. In order to effect clearer distinction be- 
tween heavenly beings and those of this world, he 
represents the former as clothed in draperies of the 



so OF THE TRUE IDEAL [paet iv 

purest colour, crowned with glories of burnished gold, 
and entirely shadowless. With exquisite choice of 
gesture, and disposition of folds of drapery, this mode 
of treatment gives perhaps the best idea of spiritual 
beings which the human mind is capable of forming. 
It is, therefore, a true ideal but the mode in 
which it is arrived at (being so far mechanical and 
•contradictory of the appearances of nature) neces- 
sarily precludes those who practise it from being com- 
plete masters of their art. It is always childi^, but 
beautiful in its childishness. 

§ 5 , The works of our own Stothard are examples 
of the operation of another mind, singular in gentle- 
ness and purity, upon mere worldly subject. It 
seems as if Stothard could not conceive wickedness, 
coarseness, or baseness; every one of his figures 
looks as if it had been copied from some creature 
who had never harboured an unkind thought, or per- 
mitted itself in an ignoble action. With this intense 
love of mental purity is joined, in Stothard, a love 
of mere physical smoothness and softness, so that he 
lived in a universe of soft grass and stainless foun- 
tains, tender trees, and stones at which no loot could 
stumble. 

All this is very beautiful, and may sometimes urge 
us to an endeavour to make the world itself more 
like the conception of the painter. At least, in the 
midst of its malice, misery, and baseness, it is often 
a relief to glance at the gr^^ceful shadows, and take, 
for momentj^ry companionship, creatures full only of 
love, gladness, and honour. ^ But the perfect truth 
will at last vindicate itself against the partial truth; 
the help which we can gain from the unsubstantial 
vision will be only like that which we may some- 
times receive, in weariness, from the scent of a flower 
or the passing of a breeze. For all firm aid, and 
steady use, we must look to harder realities; and, 
as far as the painter himself is regarded, we can 
'Only receive such work as the sign of an amiable 


^ As noted above in Chap. IV, § 20. 



1. PUBIST 


81 


CHAP. Vl] 

imbecility. It is indeed ideal; but ideal as a fair 
dream is in the dawn of morning, before the faculties 
are astir. The apparent completeness of grace can 
never be attained without much definite falsification 
as well as omission; stones, over which we cannot 
stumble, must be ill-drawn stones; trees, which are 
all gentleness and softness, cannot be trees of wood; 
nor companies without evil in them, companies of 
flesh and blood. The habit of falsification (with 
whatever aim) begins always in dulness and ends 
always in incapacity : nothing can be more pitiable 
than any endeavour by Stothard to express facts 
beyond his own sphere of soft pathos or graceful 
mirth, and nothing more unwise than the aim at 
a similar ideality by any painter who has power to 
render a sincerer truth. 

§ 6, I remember another interesting example of 
ideality on this same root, but belonging to another 
branch of it, in the works of a young German painter, 
which I saw some time ago in a London drawing- 
room. •He had boon travelling in Italy, and had 
brought home a portfolio of sketches remarkable alike 
for their fidelity and purity. Every one was a 
laborious and accurate study of some particular spot. 
Every cottage, every cliff, every tree, at the site 
chosea, had been drawn; and drawm with palpable 
sincerity of portraiture, and yet in such a spirit that it 
was impossible to conceive that any sin or misery had 
ever entered into one of the scenes he had repre- 
sented; and the volcani* horrors of Radicofani, the 
pestilent gloom of the Pon tines, and tlie boundless 
despondency of the Campagna became, under his 
hand, only various appearances of Paradise. 

It was very interesting to observe the minute 
emendations or omissions by which this was effected. 
To set the tiles the slightest degree more in order 
upon a cottage roof; to insist upon the vine-leaves 
at the window, and let the shadow which fell from 
them naturally conceal the rent in the wall; to draw 
all the flowers in the foreground, and miss the 
weeds; to draw all the folds of the white clouds, 

M. P., III. G • 



B2 OF THE TRUE IDEAL [part iv 

and miss those of the black ones; to mark the 
graceful branches of the trees, and, in one way or 
another, beguile the eye from those which were 
ungainly; to give every peasant-girl whose face was 
visible the expression of an angel, and every one 
whose back was turned the bearing of a princess; 
finally, to give a general look of light, clear organiza- 
tion and serene vitality to every feature in the land- 
scape; such were his artifices, and such his delights. 
It was impossible not to sympathize deeply with 
the spirit of such a painter; and it was just cause 
for gratitude to be permitted to travel, as it were, 
through Italy with such a friend. But his work had, 
nevertheless, its stern limitations and marks of ever- 
lasting inferiority. Always soothing and pathetic, 
it could never be sublime, never perfectly nor en- 
trancingly beautiful; for the narrow spirit of correc- 
tion could not cast itself fully into any scene; the 
calm cheerfulness which shrank from the shadow of 
the cypress, and the distortion of the olive, could 
not enter into the brightness of the sky that they 
pierced, nor the softness of the bloom that they bore : 
for every sorrow that his heart turned from, he lost 
a consolation; for every fear which he dared not 
confront, he lost a portion of his hardiness; the 
unsceptred sweep of the storm-clouds, the fair free- 
dom of glancing shower and flickering sunbeam, sank 
into sweet rectitudes and decent formalisms; and, 
before eyes that refused to be dazzled or darkened, 
the hours of sunset wreathed their rays unheeded, 
and the mirts of the Apennines spread their blue 
veils in vain. ^ 

§ 7. To this inherent shortcoming and narrow- 
ness of reach the farther defect was added, that this 
work gave no useful representation of the state of 
facts in the country which it pretended to contem- 
plate. It was not only wanting in all the higher 
elements of beauty, but wholly unavailable for in- 
struction of any kind beyond that which exists in 
pleasurableness of pure emotion. And considering 
what cost of labour was devoted to the series of 



CHAP, vi] I. PURIST 88 

drawings, it could not but be matter for grave blame, 
as well as for partial contempt, that a man of 
amiable feeling and considerable intellectual power 
should thus expend his life in the declaration of his 
own petty pieties and pleasant reveries, leaving the 
burden of human sorrow unwitnessed, and the power 
of God’s judgments unconfessed; and, while poor 
Italy lay wounded and moaning at his feet, pass by, 
in priestly calm, lest the whiteness of his decent 
vesture should be spotted with unhallowed blood. 

§ 8. Of several other forms of Purism I shall have 
to speak hereafter, more especially of that exhibited 
in the landscapes of the early religious painters; but 
these examples are enough, for the present, to show 
the general principle that the purist ideal, though 
in some measure true, in so far as it springs from 
the true longings of an earnest mind, is yet neces- 
sarily in many things deficient or blameable, and 
always an indication of some degree of weakness in 
the mind pursuing it. But, on the other hand, it 
is to be noted that entire scorn of this purist ideal 
is the sign of a far greater weakness. Multitudes 
of petty artists, incapable of any noble sensation 
whatever, but acquainted, in a dim way, with the 
technicalities of the schools ^ mock at the art whose 
depths they cannot fathom, and whose motives they 
cannot comprehend, but of which they can easily 
detect the imperfections, and deride the simplicities. 
Thus poor funiigatory Fuseli, with an art composed 
of the tinsel of the sta^e and the panics of the 
nursery, speaks contemptuously of th% name of 
Angelico as ‘ dearer to sanctity than to art ’. And a 
large portion of the resistance to the noble Pre- 
Raphaelite movement of our own days has been 
offered by men who suppose the entire function of 
the artist in this world to consist in laying on colour 
with a large brush, and surrounding dashes of flake 
white with bituminous brown ; men whose entire 
capacities of brain, soul, and sympathy, applied in- 
dustriously to the end of their lives, would not enable 
them, at last, to paint so much as one of the leaves 



OF THE TRUE IDEAL [part iv 

of the nettles at the bottom of Hunt’s picture of 
the Light of the World 

§ 9. It is finally to be remembered, therefore, that 
Purism is always noble when it is instinctive* It 
is not the greatest thing that can be done, but it 
is probably the greatest thing that the man who does 
it can do, provided it comes from his heart. True, 
it is a sign of weakness, but it is not in our choice 
whether we will be weak or strong; and there is a 
certain strength which can only be made perfect 
in weakness. If he is working in humility, fear of 
evil, desire of beauty, and sincere purity of purpose 
and thought, he will produce good and helpful things; 
but he must be much on his guard against suppos- 
ing himself to be greater than his fellows, because 
he has shut himself into this calm and cloistered 
sphere. His only safety lies in knowing himself to 
be, on the contrary, less than his fellows, and in 
always striving, so far as he can find it in his heart, 
to extend his delicate narrowness towards the great 
naturalist ideal. The whole group of modern Ger- 
man purists have lost themselves, because they 
founded their work not on humility, nor on religion, 
but on small self-conceit. Incapable of understand- 
ing the great Venetians, or any other masters of 
true imaginative power, and having fed what mind 
they had with weak poetry and false philosophy, they 
thought themselves the best and greatest of artistic 
mankind, and expected to found a new school of 
painting in pious plagiarisifi and delicate pride. It 
is difficult aV first to decide which is the more worth- 
less, the spiritual affectation of the petty German, 
or the composition and chiaroscuro of the petty Eng- 
lishman; on the whole, however, the latter have 
lightest weight, for the pseudo-religious painter must, 
at all events, pass much of his time in meditation 

1 Not that the Pre-Raphaelite is a purist movement, it is 
stern naturalist ; but its unfortunate opposers, who neither 
know what nature is, nor what purism is, have mistaken the 
simple nature for morbid purism, and therefore cried out 
against it. 



II. NATURALIST 


85 


CHAP. VII J 

upon solemn subjects, and in examining venerable 
models; and may sometimes even cast a little use- 
ful reflected light, or touch the heart with a pleasant 
echo. 


CHAPTER VII 

OP THE TRUE IDEAL! SECONDLY, NATURALIST 

§ 1. We now enter on the consideration of that 
central and highest branch of ideal art which con- 
cerns itself simply with things as they are, and 
accepts, in all of them, alike the evil and the good. 
The question is, therefore, how the art which repre- 
sents things simply as they are, can be called ideal 
at all. How does it meet that requirement stated 
in Chap. HI, § 4, as imperative on all great art, 
that it shall be inventive, and a product of the 
imagination? It meets it pre-eminently by that 
power ef arrangement which I have endeavoured, at 
great length and with great pains, to define accurately 
in the chapter on Imagination associative in the 
second volume. That is to say, accepting the weak- 
nesses, faults, and wrongnesses in all things that it 
sees, it so places and harmonizes them that they 
form a noble whole, in which the imperfection of 
each several part is not only harmless, but absolutely 
essential, and yet in which whatever is good in each 
several part shall be completely displayed. 

§ 2. This operation oi true idealism holds, from 
the least things to the greatest. For in^ance, in the 
arrangement of the smallest masses of colour, the 
false idealist, or even the purist, depends upon per- 
fecting each separate hue, and raises them all, as 
far as he can, into costly brilliancy; but the natural- 
ist takes the coarsest and feeblest colours of the 
things around him, and so interweaves and opposes 
them that they become more lovely than if they had 
all been bright. So in the treatment of the human 
form. The naturalist will take it as he finds it; but, 
with such examples as his picture may rationally 



86 OF THE TRUE IDEAL [paiit iv 

admit of more or less exalted beauty, he will associate 
inferior forms, so as not only to set off those which 
are most beautiful, but to bring out clearly what 
good there is in the inferior forms themselves ; finally 
using such measure of absolute evil as there is com- 
monly in nature, both for teaching and for contrast. 

In Tintoret’s Adoration of the Magi, the Madonna 
is not an enthroned queen, but a fair girl, full of 
simplicity and almost childish sweetness. To her are 
opposed (as Magi) two of the noblest and most 
thoughtful of the Venetian senators in extreme old 
age — the utmost manly dignity, in its decline, being 
set beside the utmost feminine simplicity, in its 
dawn. The steep foreheads and refined features of 
the nobles are, again, opposed to the head of a negro 
servant, and of an Indian, both, however, noble of 
their kind. On the other side of the picture, the 
delicacy of the Madonna is farther enhanced by con- 
trast with a largely made farm-servant, leaning on 
a basket. All these figures are in repose : "outside, 
the troop of the attendants of the Magi is seen coming 
up at the gallop. 

§ 3. 1 bring forward this picture, observe, not as 
an example of the ideal in conception of religious 
subject, but of the general ideal treatment of the 
human form; in which the peculiarity is, that the 
beauty of each figure is displayed to the utmost, 
while yet, taken separately the Madonna is an un- 
altered portrait of a Venetian girl, the Magi are 
unaltered Venetian senators, and the figure with the 
basket, an unaltered market-wq^an of Mestre. 

And the greater the master of the ideal, the more 
perfectly true in portraiture will his individual figures 
be alwaj^s found, the more subtle and bold his arts 
of harmony and contrast. This is a universal prin- 
ciple, common to all great art. Consider, in Shak- 
speare, how Prince Henry is opposed to Falstaff, 
Falstaff to Shallow, Titania to Bottom, Cordelia to 
Regan, Imogen to Cloten, and so on; while all the 
meaner idealists disdain the naturalism, and are 
shocked at the contrasts. The fact is, a man who 



CHAP, vii] II. NATURALIST 87 

can see truth at all, sees it wholly, and neither 
desires nor dares to mutilate it. 

§ 4. It is evident that within this faithful idealism, 
and as one branch of it only, will arrange itself the 
representation of the human form and mind in per- 
fection, when this perfection is rationally to be sup- 
posed or introduced — that is to say, in the highest 
personages of the story. The careless habit of con- 
fining the term ‘ ideal ’ to such representations, and 
not understanding the imperfect ones to be equally 
ideal in their place, has greatly added to the em- 
barrassment and multiplied the errors of artists 
Thersites is just as ideal as Achilles, and Alecto as 
Helen; and, what is more, all the nobleness of the 
beautiful ideal depends upon its being just as prob- 
able and natural as the ugly one, and having in itself, 
occasionally or partially, both faults and familiarities. 
If the next painter who desires to illustrate the 
character of Homer’s Achilles, would represent him 
cutting pork chops for Ulysses 2 , he would enable 
the public to understand the Homeric ideal better 
than they have done for several centuries. For it 
is to be kept in mind that the naturalist ideal has 
always in it, to the full, the power expressed by those 
two words. It is naturalist, because studied from 
nature, and ideal, because it is mentally arranged 
in a certain manner. Achilles must be represented 
cutting pork chops, because that was one of the 
things which the nat^ire of Achilles involved his 
doing : he could not be shown wholly as Achilles, if 
he were not shown doing that. But he shall do it 
at such time and place as Homer chooses. 

§ 5. Now, therefore, observe the main conclusions 
which follow from these two conditions, attached 
always to art of this kind. First, it is to be taken 
straight from nature; it is to be the plain narration 
of something the painter or writer saw. Herein is 

1 The word ‘ ideal ’ is used in this limited sense in the chapter 
on Generic Beauty in the second volume, but under protest. 
See § 4 in that chapter. 

2 n., ix, 209. 



88 


OF THE TRUE IDEAL [part iv 

the chief practical difference between the higher and 
lower artists; a difference which I feel more and 
more every day that I give to the study of art. All 
the great men see what they paint before they paint 
it — see it in a perfectly passive manner — cannot 
help seeing it if they would; whether in their mind’s 
eye, or in bodily fact, does not matter; very often 
the mental vision is, I believe, in men of imagination, 
clearer than the bodily one; but vision it is, of one 
kind or another — the whole scene, character, or 
incident passing before them as in second sight, 
whether they will or no, and requiring them to paint 
it as they see it; they not daring, under the might 
of its presence, to alter i one jot or tittle of it as 
they write it down or paint it down; it being to 
them in its own kind and degree always a true vision 
or Apocalypse, and invariably accompanied in their 
hearts by a feeling correspondent to the words, 
‘ Write the things which thou hast seen, and the 
things which are.' * 

And the whole power, whether of painter or poet, 
to describe rightly what we call an ideal thing, de- 
pends upon its being thus, to him, not an ideal, but 
a real thing. No man ever did or ever will work 
well, but either from actual sight or sight of faith; 
and all that we call ideal in Greek or any other art, 
because to us it is false and visionary, was, to the 
makers of it, true and existent. The heroes of 
Phidias are simply representations of such noble 
human persons as he every day saw, and the gods 
of Phidias simply representations of such noble divine 
persons as he thoroughly believed to exist, and did 
in mental vision truly behold. Hence I said in the 
second preface to the Seven Lamps of Architecture : 
* All great art represents something that it sees or 
believes in; — nothing unseen or uncredited.* 

§ 6. And just because it is always something that 
it sees or believes in, there is the peculiar character 

1 * And yet yon have just said it shall be at such time and 
place as Homer chooses. Is not this altering ? ’ No ; wait a 
little, and read on. 



II. NATURALIST 


89 


CHAP. Vll] 

above noted, almost unmistakeable, in all high and 
true ideals, of having been as it were studied from 
the life, and involving pieces of sudden familiarity, 
and close specific painting which never would have 
been admitted or even thought of, had not the 
painter drawn either from the bodily life or from the 
life of faith. For instance, Dante’s centaur, Chiron, 
dividing his beard with his arrow before he can 
speak, is a thing that no mortal would ever have 
thought of, if he had not actually seen the centaur 
do it. They might have composed handsome bodies 
of men and horses in all possible ways, through a 
whole life of pseudo -idealism, and yet never dreamed 
of any such thing. But the real living centaur 
actually trotted across Dante’s brain, and he saw 
him do it. 

§ 7. And on account of this reality it is, that the 
great idealists venture into all kinds of what, to the 
pseudo-idealists, are ‘ vulgarities ’. Nay, venturing 
is the ^rong word; the great men have no choice 
in the matter; they do not know or care whether 
the things they describe are vulgarities or not. They 
saw them; they are the facts of the case. If they 
had merely composed what they describe, they would 
have had it at their will to refuse this circumstance 
or add that. But they did not compose it. It came 
to them ready fashioned; they were too much im- 
pressed by it to think what was vulgar or not vulgar 
in it. It might be a vei^ wrong thing in a centaur 
to have so much beard ; but so it was. Ar)^, therefore, 
among the various ready tests of true greatness there 
is not any more certain than this daring reference 
to, or use of, mean and little things — mean and 
little, that is, to mean and little minds; but, when 
used by the great men, evidently part of the noble 
whole which is authoritatively present before them. 
Thus, in the highest poetry, as partly above noted 
in the first chapter, there is no word so familiar but 
a great man will bring good out of it, or rather, it 
will bring good to him, and answer some end for 
which no other word would have done equally well^ 



% OF THE TRUE IDEAL [part iv 

§ 8. A‘ common person, for instance, would be 
mightily puzzled to apply the word ‘ whelp ’ to any 
one with a view of flattering him. There is a certain 
freshness and energy in the term, which gives it 
agreeableness; but it seems difficult, at first hearing, 
to use it complimentarily. If the person spoken of 
be a prince, the difficulty seems increased; and 
when, farther, he is at one and the same moment to 
be called a ‘ whelp ’ and contemplated as a hero, it 
seems that a common idealist might well be brought 
to a pause. But hear Shakspeare do it : 

Invoke his warlike spirit, 

And your great nude’s, Edward the Black Prince, 

Whp on the French ground play’d a tragedy, 

Making defeat on the full power of France, 

While his most mighty father on a hill 
Stood smiling, to behold his lion’s whelp 
Forage in blood of French nobility. 

So a common idealist would have been rather 
alarmed at the thought of introducing the name of a 
street in Paris — Straw Street — Rue de Fouarre — ^into 
the midst of a description of the highest heavens. 
Not so Dante : 

Beyond, thou mayst the flaming lustre scan 
Of Isidore, of Bede, and that Richart 
Who was in contemplation more than man. 

And he, from whom thy looks returning are 
To me, a spirit was, that in austere 
Deep musings often thought death kept too far. 

That is the light eternal of Sigier, 

Wlio while in Rue de Fouarre his days he wore. 

Has argued hateful truths in haughtiest ear. 

Cayley. 

What did it matter to Dante, up in heaven there, 
whether the mob below thought him vulgar or not? 
Sigier had road in Straw Street; that was the fact, 
and he had to say so, and there an end. 

§ 9. There is, indeed, perhaps, no greater sign of 
innate and real vulgarity of mind or defective educa- 
tion than the want of power to understand the 
universality of the ideal truth ; the absence of 



CHAP. VII] IJ. NATURALIST ^ 91 

sympathy with the colossal grasp of those intellects, 
which have in them so much of divine, that nothing 
is small to them- and nothing large; but with equal 
and unoffended vision they take in the sum of the 
world — Straw Street and the seventh heavens — in 
the same instant. A certain portion of this divine 
spirit is visible even in the lower examples of all 
the true men; it is, indeed, perhaps, the clearest 
test of their belonging to the true and great group, 
that they are continually touching what to the multi- 
tude appear vulgarities. The higher a man stands, 
the more the word ‘ vulgar ’ becomes unintelligible 
to him. Vulgar? what, that poor farmer’s girl of 
William Hunt’s, bred in the stable, putting on her 
Sunday gown, and pinning her best cap out of the 
green and red pin-cushion! Not so; she may be 
straight on the road to those high heavens, and may 
shine hereafter as one of the stars in the firmament 
for ever. Nay, even that lady in the satin bodice 
with her arm laid over a balustrade to show it, and 
her eyes turned up to heaven to show them ; and the 
sportsman waving his rifle for the terror of beasts, 
and displaying his perfect dress for the delight of 
men, are kept, by the very misery and vanity of 
them, in the thoughts of a great painter, at a sorrow- 
ful level, somewhat above vulgarity. It is only 
when the minor painter takes them on his easel, that 
they become things for the universe to be ashamed of. 

We may dismiss this matter of vulgarity in plain 
and few words, at least *a8 far as regards art. There 
is never vulgarity in a whole truth, howler common- 
place. It may be unimportant or painful. It can- 
not be vulgar. Vulgarity is only in concealment cf 
truth, or in affectation. 

§ 10. ‘ Well, but ’, (at this point the reader asks 
doubtfully,) ‘ if then your great central idealist is 
to show all truth, low as well as lovely, receiving it 
in this passive way, what becomes of all your prin- 
ciples of selection, and of setting in the right place, 
which you were talking about up to the end of your 
fourth paragraph? How is Homer to enforce upon 



ai OF THE TRUE IIJEAL [part iv 

Achilles the cutting of the pork chops ‘ only at such 
time as Homer chooses if Homer is to have no 
choice, but merely to see the thing done, and sing 
it as he sees it?’ Why, the choice, as well as the 
vision, is manifested to Homer. The vision comes 
to him in its chosen order. Chosen for him, not 
6|/,.him, but yet full of visible and exquisite choice, 
just as a sweet and perfect dream will come to a 
sweet and perfect person, so that, in some sense, 
they may be said to have chosen their dream, or 
composed it; and yet they could not help dreaming 
it so, and in no other wisel Thus, exactly thus, in 
all results of true inventive power, the whole harmony 
of the thing done seems as if it had been wrought 
by the most exquisite rules. But to him who did 
it, it presented itself so, and his will, and knowledge, 
and personality, for the moment went for nothing; 
he became simply a scribe, and wrote what he heard 
and saw. 

And all efforts to do things of a similar kind by 
rule or by thought, and all efforts to mend or re- 
arrange the first order of the vision, are not inven- 
tive; on the contrary, they ignore and deny in- 
vention. If any man, seeing certain forms laid on 
the canvass, does by his reasoning power determine 
that certain changes wrought in them would mend 
or enforce them, that is not only uninventive, but 
contrary to invention, which must be the involun- 
tary occurrence of certain forms or fancies to the 
mind in the order they are* to be portrayed. Thus 
the knowing' of rules and the exertion of judgment 
have a tendency to check andf confuse the fancy in 
its flow; so that it will follow, that, in exact pro- 
portion as a master knows anything about rules of 
right and wrong, he is likely to be uninventive; and, 
in exact proportion as he holds higher rank and has 
nobler inventive power, he will know less of rules; 
not despising them, but simply feeling that between 
mm and them there is nothing in common — that 
dreams cannot be ruled — ^that as they come, so they 
must be caught, and they cannot be caught in any 



II. NATURALIST 


CHAP. VIl] 




other shape than that they come in : and that he 
might as well attempt to rule a rainbow into recti- 
tude, or cut notches in a moth’s wings to hold it by, 
as in any wise attempt to modify, by rule, the forms 
of the involuntary vision. 

§ 11. And this, which by reason we have thus 
anticipated, is in reality universally so. There is no 
exception. The great men never know how or why 
they do things. They have no rules; cannot com- 
prehend the nature of rules; — do not, usually, even 
know, in what they do, what is best or what is 
worst: to them it is all ‘the same: something they 
cannot help saying or doing, — one piece of it as good 
as another, and none of it (it seems to them) worth 
much. The moment any man begins to talk about 
rules, in whatsoever art, you may know him for a 
second-rate man; and, if he talks about them much, 
he is a third-rate, or not an artist at all. To this 
rule there is no exception in any art; but it is per- 
haps better to be illustrated in the art of music than 
in that of painting. I fell by chance the other day 
upon a work of De Stendhal’s, Vies de Haydn, de 
Mozart, et de Metastase, fuller of common sense than 
any book I ever read on the arts; though I see, by 
the slight references made occasionally to painting, 
that the author’s knowledge therein is warped and 
limited by the elements of general teaching in the 
schools around him; and I have not yet, therefore, 
looked at what he has separately written on painting. 
But one or two passagdfe out of this book on music 
are closely to our present purpose ; • 

Counterpoint is related to mathematics : a fool, 
with patience, becomes a respectable savant in that; 
but for the part of genius, melody, it has no rules. 
No art is so utterly deprived of precepts for the pro- 
duction of the beautiful. So much the better for it 
and for us. Cimarosa, when first at Prague his air 
was executed, Pria che spunti in ciel 1 ’Aurora, never 
heard the pedants say to him, Your air is fine, be- 
cause you have followed such and such a rule estab- 
lished by Pergolese in such an one of his airs; but 



li OF THE TRUE IDEAL [part iv 

it would be finer still if you had conformed yourself 
to such another rule from which Galluppi never 
deviated. 

Yes ; ‘ so much the better for it, and for us ’ ; but 
I trust the time will soon come when melody in 
painting will be understood, no less than in music, 
and when people will find that, there also, the great 
melodists have no rules, and cannot have any, and 
that there are in this, as in sound, ‘ no precepts for 
the production of the beautiful.’ 

§ 12. Again : ‘ Behold, my friend, an example of 
that simple way of answering which embarrasses 
much. One asked him (Haydn) the reason for a 
harmony-^for a passage’s being assigned to one in- 
strument rather than another ; but all he ever 
answered was, “ I have done it, because it does 
well Farther on. Do Stendhal relates an anecdote 
of Haydn ; I believe one well known, but so much 
to our purpose that I repeat it. Haydn had agreed 
to give some lessons in counterpoint to an English 
nobleman. ‘ “ For our first lesson ”, said the pupil, 
already learned in the art — drawing at the same time 
a quatuor of Haydn’s from his pocket, ” for our 
first lesson may we examine this quatuor; and will 
you tell me the reasons of certain modulations, which 
I cannot entirely approve because they are contrary 
to the principles?” Haydn, a little surprised, de- 
clared himself ready to answer. The nobleman 
began; and at the very first measures found matter 
for objection. Haydn, who invented habitually, and 
who was th^. contrary of a pedant, found himself 
much embarrassed, and answered always, ” I have 
done that because it has a good effect. I put that 
passage there because it does well.” The English- 
man, who judged that these answers proved nothing, 
recommenced his proofs, and demonstrated to him, 
by very good reasons, that his quatuor was good for 
nothing. ‘‘ But, my lord, arrange this quatuor then 
to your fancy — ^play it so, and you will see which of 
the two ways is the best.” ” But why is yours the 
best which is contrary to the rules?” ” Because it 



CHAP, vii] II. NATURALIST 95 

is the pleasantest.” The nobleman replied. Haydn 
at last lost patience, and said, ” I see, my lord, it is 
you who have the goodness to give lessons to me, and 
truly I am forced to confess to you that I do not 
deserve the honour.” The partizan of the rules 
departed, still astonished that in following the rules 
to the letter one cannot infallibly produce a Matri- 
monio Segreto.* 

This anecdote, whether in all points true or not, is 
in its tendency most instructive, except only in that it 
makes one false inference or admission, namely, that 
a good composition can be contrary to the rules. 
It may be contrary to certain principles, supposed 
in ignorance to be general; but every great com- 
position is in perfect harmony with all true rules, and 
involves thousands too delicate for ear, or eye, or 
thought, to trace; still it is possible to reason, with 
infinite pleasure and profit, about these principles, 
when the thing is once done; only, all our reasoning 
will not enable any one to do another thing like it, 
because all reasoning falls infinitely short of the 
divine instinct. Thus we may reason wisely over the 
way a bee builds its comb, and be profited by find- 
ing out certain things about the angles of it. But 
the bee knows nothing about those mattters. It 
builds its comb in a far more inevitable way. And, 
from a bee to Paul Veronese, all master-workers 
work with this awful, this inspired unconsciousness. 

§ 13. I said just now that there was no exception 
to this law, that the grmt men never knew how or 
why they did things. It is, of course^ only with 
caution that such a broad statement should be made ; 
but I have seen much of different kinds of artists, and 
I have always found the knowledge of, and attention 
to, rules so accurately in the inverse ratio to the 
power of the painter, that I have myself no doubt 
that the law is constant, and that men’s smallness 
may be trigonometrically estimated by the attention 
which, in their work, they pay to principles, especi- 
ally principles of composition. The general way in 
which the great men speak is of ‘‘ trying to do ’ this 



OF THE TRUE IDEAL [paet iv 

or that, just as a child would tell of something he 
had seen and could not utter. Thus, in speaking of 
the drawing of which I have given an etching farther 
on (a scene on the St Gothard i). Turner asked if I 
had been to see ‘ that litter of stones which I endeav- 
oured to represent and William Hunt, when I 
aeked him one day as he was painting, why he put 
on such and such a colour, answered, ‘ I don’t know; 
I am just aiming at it and Turner, and he, and 
all the other men I have known who could paint, 
always spoke and speak in the same way; not in 
any selfish restraint of their knowledge, but in pure 
simplicity. While all the men whom I know, who 
cannot paint, are ready with admirable reasons for 
everything they have done; and can show, in the 
most conclusive way, that Turner is wrong, and how 
ho might be improved. 

§ 14. And this is the reason for the somewhat 
singular, but very palpable truth that the Chinese, 
and Indians, and othei* semi-civilized nations, can 
colour better than we do, and that an Indian shawl 
and China vase are still, in invention of colour, 
inimitable by us. It is their glorious ignorance of 
all rules that does it; the pure and true instincts 
have play, and do their work — instincts so subtle, 
that the least warping or compression breaks or 
blunts them; and the moment we begin teaching 
people any rules about colour, and make them do 
this or that, we crush the instinct, generally for ever. 
Hence, hitherto, it has been an actual necessity, in 
order to obtain power of colouring, that a nation 
should be nalf-savage : everybody could colour in 
the twelfth and thirteenth centuries ; but we were 
ruled and legalized into grey in the fifteenth; only 
a little salt simplicity of their sea natures at Venice 
still keeping their precious, shell-fishy purpleness and 
power; and now that is gone; and nobody can colour 
anywhere, except the Hindoos and Chinese : but that 
need not be so, and will not be so long; for, in a 
little while, people will find out their mistake, and 
1 See Plate XXI, in Yol. lY, Chap. III. 



97 


CHAP, vii] II. NATURALIST 

give up talking about rules of colour, and then every- 
body will colour again, as easily as they now talk. 

§ 15. Such, then, being the generally passive or 
instinctive character of right invention, it may be 
asked how these unmanageable instincts are to be 
rendered practically serviceable in historical or 
poetical painting, — especially historical, in which 
given facts are to be represented. Simply by the 
sense and self-control of the whole man ; not by 
control of the particular fancy or vision. He who 
habituates himself, in his daily life, to seek for the 
stern facts in whatever he hears or sees, will have 
these facts again brought before him by the involun- 
tary imaginative power in their noblest associations; 
and he who seeks for frivolities and fallacies, will 
have frivolities and fallacies again presented to him 
in his dreams. Thus if, in reading history for the 
purpose of painting from it, the painter severely 
seeks for the accurate circumstances of every event; 
as, for instance, determining the exact spot of ground 
on which his hero fell, the way he must have been 
looking at the moment, the height the sun was at 
(by the hour of the day), and the way in which the 
light must have fallen upon his face, the actual num- 
ber and individuality of the persons by him at the 
moment, and such other veritable details, ascertain- 
ing and dwelling upon them without the slightest 
care for any desirableness or poetic propriety in 
them, but for their o\^ truth’s sake; then these 
truths will afterwards rise up and fojjpa the body 
of his imaginative vision, perfected and united as. 
his inspiration may teach. But if, in reading the' 
history, he does not regard these facts, but thinks 
only how it might all most prettily, and properly,, 
and impressively have happened, then there is no- 
thing but prettiness and propriety to form the body 
of his future imagination, and his whole ideal be- 
comes false. So, in the higher or expressive part 
of the work, the whole virtue of it depends on his 
being able to quit his own personality, and enter- 
successively into the hearts and thoughts of eacl^ 

M. P., III. H 



p OF THE TRUE IDEAL [part iv 

person; and in all this he is still passive in gather- 
ing the truth he is passive, not determining what 
the truth to be gathered shall be; and in the after 
vision he is passive, not determining, but as his 
dreams will have it, what the truth to be repre- 
sented shall be; only according to his own noble- 
neos is his power of entering into the hearts of noble 
persons, and the general character of his dream of 
them 

§ 16. It follows from all this, evidently, that a 
great idealist never can be egotistic. The whole of 
his power depends upon his losing sight and feeling 
of his own existence, and becoming a mere witness 
and mirror of truth, and a scribe of visions — always 
passive in sight, passive in utterance — lamenting con- 
tinually that he cannot completely reflect nor clearly 
utter all he has seen. Not by any means a proud 
state for a man to be in. But the man who has no 
invention is always setting things in order, and 
putting the world to lights, and mending, and 
beautifying, and pluming himself on his doings as 
supreme in all ways. 

§ 17. There is still the question open. What are 
the principal directions in which this ideal faculty 
is to exercise itself most usefully for mankind? 

This question, however, is not to the purpose of 
our present work, which respects landscape-painting 
only; it must be one of those left open to the reader’s 
thoughts, and for future inquiry in another place. 
One or two essential points I briefly notice. 

In Chap. IV, § 5, it was sahj, that one of the first 
functions of imagination was traversing the scenes 
of history, and forcing the facts to become again 
visible. But there is so little of such force in written 
history, that it is no marvel there should be none 
hitherto in painting. There does not exist, as far 
as I know, in the world a single example of a good 
historical picture (that is to say, of one which, allow- 

1 The reader should, of course, refer for fuller details on this 
subject to the chapters on Inclination in Vol. II, of which I 

only glancing now at the practical results. 



II. NATURALIST 


CHAP. VIl] 


90 


ing for necessary dimness in art as compared with 
nature, yet answers nearly the same ends in our 
min ds as the sight of the real event would have 
answered) ; the reason being, the universal endeavour 
to get effects instead of facts, already shown as the 
root of false idealism. True historical ideal, founded 
on sense, correctness of knowledge, and purpose of 
usefulness, does not yet exist; the production of it 
is a task which the closing nineteenth century may 
propose to itself. 

§ 18. Another point is to be observed. I do not, 
as the reader may have lately perceived, insist on 
the distinction between historical and poetical paint- 
ing, because, as noted in the 22nd paragraph of the 
third chapter, all great painting must be both. 

Nevertheless, a certain distinction must generally 
exist between men who, like Horace Vemet, David, 
or Domenico Tintoret, would employ themselves in 
painting, more or less graphically, the outward 
verities of passing events — battles, councils, &c. — 
of their day (who, supposing them to work worthily 
of their mission, would become, properly so called, 
historical or narrative painters) ; and men who 
sought, in scenes of perhaps less outward importance, 

‘ noble grounds for noble emotion — who would be, 
in a certain separate sense, poetical painters, some 
of them taking for subjects events which had actually 
happened, and others themes from the poets; or, 
better still, becoming poets themselves in the entire 
sense, and inventing th« story as they painted it. 
Painting seems to me only just to be beginning, in 
this sense also, to take its proper position beside 
literature, and the pictures of the ‘ Awakening Con- 
science * Huguenot and such others, to be the 
first fruits of its new effort. 

§ 19. Finally, as far as I can observe, it is a con- 
stant law that the greatest men, whether poets or 
historians, live entirely in their own age, and that 
the greatest fruits of their work are gathered out 
of their own age. Dante paints Italy in the thirteenth 
century; Chaucer, England in the fourteenth; 



ioo OF THE TRUE IDEAL [part iv 

Masacfcio, Florence in the fifteenth; Tintoret, Venice 
in the sixteenth; — all of them utterly regardless of 
anachronism and minor error of every kind, but 
getting always vital truth out of the vital present. 

§ 20. If it be said that Shakspeare wrote perfect 
historical plays on subjects belonging to the preced- 
ing centuries, I answer, that they are perfect plays 
jUiSt because there is no care about centuries in them, 
but a life which all men recognize for the human 
life of all time; and this it is, not because Shakspeare 
sought to give universal truth, but because, painting 
honestly and completely from the men about him, 
he painted that human nature which is, indeed, con- 
stant enough — a rogue in the fifteenth century being, 
at heart, what a rogue is in the nineteenth and was 
in the twelfth; and an honest or a knightly man 
being, in like manner, very similar to other such at 
any other time. And the work of these great ideal- 
ists is, therefore, always universal; not because it 
is not portrait, but because it is complete portrait 
down to the heart, which is the same in all ages : 
and the work of the mean idealists is not universal, 
not because it is portrait, but because it is half 
portrait — of the outside, the manners and the dress, 
not of the heart. Thus Tintoret and Shakspeare 
paint, both of them, simply Venetian and English 
nature as they saw it in their time, down to the 
root; and it does for all time; but as for any care 
to cast themselves into the particular ways and tones 
of thought, or custom, of past time in their historical 
work, you ij^ill find it in neither of them, nor in any 
other perfectly great man that I know of. 

§ 21. If there had been no vital truth in their 
present, it is hard to say what these men could have 
done. I suppose, primarily, they would not have 
existed; that they, and the matter they have to treat 
of, are given together, and that the strength of the 
nation and its historians correlatively rise and fall — 
Hemdotus springing out of the dust of Marathon. 
It is also hard to say how far our better general 
acquaintance with minor details of past history may 



101 


cHAP.viii] III, GROTESQUE 

make us able to turn the shadow on the imaginative 
dial backwards, and naturally to ll've, and even live 
strongly if we choose, in past periods; but this main 
truth will always be unshaken, that the only historical 
painting deserving the name is portraiture of our 
own living men and our own passing times and that 
all efforts to summon up the events of bygone periods, 
though often useful and tquching, must come under 
an inferior class of poetical painting; nor will it, I 
believe, ever be much followed as their main work 
by the strongest men, but only by the weaker and 
comparatively sentimental (rather than imaginative) 
groups. This marvellous hrst half of the nineteenth 
century has in this matter, as in nearly all others, 
been making a double blunder. It has, under the 
name of improvement, done all it could to efface 
THE RECORDS which departed ages have left of them- 
selves, while it has declared the forgery of false 
RECORDS of these same ages to be the great work of 
its historical painters 1 I trust that in a few years 
more we shall come somewhat to our senses in the 
matter, and begin to perceive that our duty is to 
preserve what the past has had to say for itself, and 
to say for ourselves also what shall be true for the 
future. Let us strive, with just veneration for that 
future, first to do what is worthy to be spoken, and 
then to speak it faithfully; and, with veneration for 
the past, recognize that it is indeed in the power of 
love to preserve the mom^ent, but not of incantation 
to raise the dead. 


CHAPTER VIII 

OF THE TRUE IDEAL : THIRDLY, GROTESQUE 

§ 1. I HAVE already, in the Stones of Venice , had 
occasion to analyse, as far as I was able, the noble 
nature and power of grotesque conception : I am 
not sorry occasionally to refer the reader to that 
1 See Edinburgh Lectures, lect. iv. 



|p5 OF THE TRUE IDEAL [part iv 

work, the fact being that it and this are parts of one 
whole, divided merely as I had occasion to follow 
out one or other of its branches; for I have always 
considered architecture as an essential part of land- 
scape; and I think the study of its best styles and 
real meaning one of the necessary functions of the 
landscape-painter; as, in like manner, the architect 
cannot be a master-workman until all his designs 
are guided by understanding of the wilder beauty of 
pure nature. But, be this as it may, the discussion 
of the grotesque element belonged most properly to 
the essay on architecture, in which that element 
must always find its fullest development. 

§ 2. The Grotesque is in that chapter 1 divided 
principally into three kinds : 

(A) . Art arising from healthful but irrational play 
of the imagination in times of rest. 

(B) . Art arising from irregular and accidental con- 
templation of terrible things; or evil in general. 

(C) . Art arising from the confusion of the imagin- 
ation by the presence of truths which it cannot wholly 
grasp. 

It is the central form of this art, arising from 
contemplation of evil, which forms the link of con- 
nection between it and the sensualist ideals, as 
pointed out above in the second paragraph of the 
sixth chapter, the fact being that the imagination, 
when at play, is curiously like bad children, and 
likes to play with fire : in its entirely serious moods 
it dwells j)y preference on beautiful and sacred 
images, but in its mocking qr playful moods it is 
apt to jest, sometimes bitterly, with under-current 
of sternest pathos, sometimes waywardly, sometimes 
slightly and wickedly, with death and sin; hence 
an enormous mass of grotesque art, some most noble 
and useful, as Holbein’s Dance of Death, and Albert 
Diirer’s Knight and Deaths, going down gradually 
through various conditions of less and less seriousness 
into an art whose only end is that of ^ mere excite- 

1 On the Grotesque Renaissance, vol. iii. 

, 2 gee Appendix I, Vol. IV, ‘ Modem Grotesque.’ 



oHAP.vm] III. GROTESQUE M 

ment, or amusement by terror, like a child making 
mouths at another, more or less redeemed by the 
degree of wit or fancy in the grimace it makes, as 
in the demons of Teniers and such others; and, 
lower still, in the demonology of the stage. 

§ 3. The form arising from an entirely healthful 
and open play of the imagination, as in Shakspeare’s 
Ariel and Titania, and in Scott’s White Lady, is 
comparatively rare. It hardly ever is free from some 
slight taint of the inclination to evil; still more 
rarely is it, when so free, natural to the mmd; for 
the moment we begin to contemplate sinless beauty 
we are apt to get serious; and moral fairy tales, 
and such other innocent work, are hardly ever truly, 
that is to say, naturally, imaginative; but for the 
most part laborious inductions and compositions. 
The moment any real vitality enters them, they are 
nearly sure to become satirical, or slightly gloomy, 
and so connect themselves with the evil-enjoying 
branch. 

§ 4. The third form of the Grotesque is a thor- 
oughly noble one. It is that which arises out of 
the use or fancy of tangible signs to set forth an 
otherwise less expressible truth; including nearly 
the whole range of symbolical and allegorical art 
and poetry. Its nobleness has been sufficiently in- 
sisted upon in the place before referred to. (Chapter 
on ‘ Grotesque Renaissance *, §§ lxiii, lxiv, &c.) 
Of its practical use, especially in painting, deeply 
despised among us, be(fause grossly misunderstood, 
a few words must be added here. • 

A fine grotesque is the expression, in a moment, 
by a series of symbols thrown together in bold and 
fearless connection, of truths which it would have 
taken a long time to express in any verbal way, and 
of which the connection is left for the beholder to 
work out for himself; the gaps, left or overleaped 
by the haste of the imagination, forming the gro- 
tesque character. 

§ 6. For instance, Spenser desires to tell us, (1) 
that envy is the most untamable and unappeasable 



,%m OF THE TRUE IDEAL [part nr 

of tho passions, not to be soothed by any kindness; 
(2) that with continual labour it invents evil thoughts 
out of its own heart; (3) that even in this, its power 
of doing harm is partly hindered by the decaying 
and corrupting nature of the evil it lives in; (4) that 
it looks every way, and that whatever it sees is 
altered and discoloured by its own nature ; (5) which 
distsolouring, however, is to it a veil, or disgraceful 
dress, in the sight of others; (6) and that it never 
is free from the most bitter suffering, (7) which 
cramps all its acts and movements, enfolding and 
crushing it while it torments. All this it has re- 
quired a somewhat long and languid sentence for me 
to say in unsymbolical terms — not, by the way, that 
they are unsymbolical altogether, for I have been 
forced, whether I would or not, to use some figur- 
ative words; but even with this help the sentence 
is long and tiresome, and does not with any vigour 
represent the truth. It would take some prolonged 
enforcement of each sentence to make it felt, in 
ordinary ways of talking. But Spenser puts it all 
into a grotesque, and it is done shortly and at once, 
so that we feel it fully, and see it, and never forget 
it. I have numbered above the statements which 
had to be made. I now number them with the same 
numbers, as they occur in the several pieces of the 
grotesque : 

And next to him malicious Envy rode 

(1) Upon a ravenous wolfe, and (2, 3) still did chaw 
Between his cankred i teeth a venemous todo, 

That all the poison ran about his jaw. 

(4, 5) All in a kirtle of discoloivd say 

He clothed was, y-paynted full of eies ; 

(6) And in his bosome secretly there lay 

An hatefull snake, the which his taile uptyes 

(7) In many folds, and mortall sting implyes. 

There is the whole thing in nine lines; or, rather, 
in one image, which will hardly occupy any room at 
all on the mind’s shelves, but can be lifted out, 
whole, whenever we want it. All noble grotesques 
1 Oankred — because he cannot then bite hard. 



CHAP, vm] III. GROTESQUE ibs 

are concentrations of this kind, and the noblest con- 
vey truths which nothing else could convey; and 
not only so, but convey thenri, in minor cases with 
a delightfulnoss, in the higher instances with an 
awfulness, which no mere utterance of the symbolized 
truth would have possessed, but which belongs to 
the effort of the mind to unweave the riddle, or to 
the sense it has of there being an infinite power and 
meaning in the thing seen, beyond all that is appar- 
ent therein, giving the highest sublimity even to the 
most trivial object so presented and so contemplated. 

‘ Jeremiah, what seest thou ? ’ 

‘ I see a seething pot, and the face thereof is toward the north, 
Out of the north an evil shall break forth upon all the 
inhabitants of the land.* 

And thus in all ages and among all nations, 
grotesque idealism has been the element through 
which the most appalling and eventful truth has 
been wisely conveyed, from the most sublime words 
of true Revelation, to the ^t* hy Tjfxloyos Bacn\c6st 
&c., of the oracles, and the more or less doubtful 
teaching of dreams ; and so down to ordinary poetry. 
No element of imagination has a wider range, a more 
magnificent use, or so colossal a grasp of sacred 
truth. 

§ 6. How, then, is this noble power best to be 
employed in the art of painting? 

We hear it not unfrequently asserted that sym- 
bolism or personification should not be introduced 
in painting at all. Such assertions |re in their 
grounds unintelligible, and in their substance absurd. 
Whatever is in words described as visible, may with 
all logical fitness i be rendered so by colours, and 
not only is this a legitimate branch of ideal art, 
but I believe there is hardly any other so widely 
useful and instructive ; and I heartily wish that 
every great allegory which the poets ever invented 
were powerfully put on canvass, and easily accessible 

1 Though, perhaps, only in a subordinate degree. See farther 
on, § 8. 



OF THE TRUE IDEAL [part tv 

by all men, and that our artists were perpetually 
exciting themselves to invent more. And as far as 
authority bears on the question, the simple fact is 
that allegorical painting has been the delight of the 
greatest men and of the wisest multitudes, from the 
beginning of art, and will be till art expires. Or- 
cagpa’s Triumph of Death; Simon Memmi’s frescoes 
in the Spanish Chapel; Giotto’s principal works at 
Assisi, and partly at the Arena; Michael Angelo’s 
two best statues, the Night and Day; Albert Dhrer’s 
noble Melancholy, and hundreds more of his best 
works; a full third, I should think, of the works of 
Tintoret and Veronese, and nearly as large a portion 
of those of Raphael and Rubens, are entirely sym- 
bolical or personifiant; and, except in the case of 
the last-named painter, are always among the most 
interesting works the painters executed. The 
greater and more thoughtful the artists, the more 
they delight in symbolism, and the more fearlessly 
they employ it. Dead symbolism, second-hand sym- 
bolism, pointless symbolism, are indeed objectionable 
enough; but so are most other things that are dead, 
second-hand, and pointless. It is also true that both 
symbolism and personification are somewhat more 
apt than most things to have their edges taken ofE 
by too much handling; and what with our modem 
Fames, Justices, and various metaphorical ideals, 
largely used for signs and other such purposes, there 
is some excuse for our not well knowing what the 
real power of personificatioil' is. But that power is 
gigantic an^. inexhaustible, and ever to be grasped 
with peculiar joy by the painter, because it permits 
him to introduce picturesque elements and flights of 
fancy into his work, which otherwise would be 
utterly inadmissible; to bring the wild beasts of the 
desert into the room of state, fill the air with inha- 
bitants as well as the earth, and render the least 
(visibly) interesting incidents themes for the most 
thrilling drama. Even Tintoret might sometimes 
have been hard put to it, when he had to fill a large 
panel in the Ducal Palace with the portrait of a 



CHAP, vni] III. GROTESQUE 107 

nowise interesting Doge, unless he had been able to 
lay a winged lion beside him, ten feet long from the 
nose to the tail, asleep upon the Turkey carpet; 
and Rubens could certainly have made his flatteries 
of Mary of Medicis palatable to no one but herself, 
without the help of rosy-cheeked goddesses of 
abundance, and seven-headed hydras of rebellion. 

§ 7. For observe, not only does the introduction 
of these imaginary beings permit greater fantasticism 
of incident f but also infinite fantasticism of treat- 
ment; and, I believe, so far from the pursuit of the 
false ideal having in any wise exhausted the realms 
of fantastic imagination, those realms have hardly 
yet been entered, and that a universe of noble dream- 
land lies before us, yet to be conquered. For, hither- 
to, when fantastic creatures have been introduced, 
either the masters have been so realistic in temper 
that they made the spirits as substantial as their 
figures of flesh and blood, as Rubens, and, for the 
most part, Tintoret; or else they have been weak 
and unpractised in realization, and have painted 
transparent or cloudy spirits because they had no 
power of painting grand ones. But if a really great 
painter, thorougnly capable of giving substantial 
truth, and master of the elements of pictorial effect 
which have been developed by modern art, would 
solemnly, and yet fearlessly, cast his fancy free in 
the spiritual world, and faithfully follow out such 
masters of that world ^s Dante and Spenser, there 
seems no limit to the splendour of thought which 
painting might express. Consider, for instance, how 
the ordinary personifications of Charity oscillate be- 
tween the mere nurse of many children, of Reynolds, 
and the somewhat painfully conceived figure with 
flames issuing from the heart, of Giotto; and how 
much more significance might be given to the repre- 
sentation of Love, by amplifying with tenderness the 
thought of Dante, ‘ Tanta rossa, che a pena fora 
dentro al foco nota ’ that is to say, by representing 

^ So red, that in the midst of the fire she could hardly have 
been seen. 



^ i# OF THE TRUE IDEAL [paet iv 

the loTelxness of her face and form as all flushed 
with glow of crimson light, and, as she descended 
through heaven, all its clouds coloured by her 
presence fils they are by sunset. In the hands of a 
feeble painter, such an attempt would end in mere 
caricature; but suppose it taken up by Correggio, 
adding to his power of flesh-painting the (not incon- 
sistent) feeling of Angelico in design, and a portion 
of Turner’s knowledge of the clouds. There is no- 
thing impossible in such a conjunction as this. 
Correggio,^ trained in another school, might have 
even himself shown some such extent of grasp; and 
in Turner’s picture of the Dragon of the Hesperides, 
Jason, vignette to Voyage of Columbus (‘ Slowly 
along the evening sky they went ’), and such others, 
as well as in many of the works of Watts and 
Rossetti, is already visible, as I trust, the dawn of 
a new era of art, in a true unison of the grotesque 
with the realistic power. 

§ 8. There is, however, unquestionably, a severe 
limit, in the case of all inferior masters, to the degree 
in which they may venture to realize grotesque con- 
ception, and partly, also, a limit in the nature of 
the thing itself, there being many grotesque ideas 
which may be with safety suggested dimly by words 
or slight lines, but which will hardly bear being 
painted into perfect definiteness. It is very diffi- 
cult, in reasoning on this matter, to divest ourselves 
of the prejudices which ha'^e been forced upon us 
by the base grotesque of men like Bronzino, who, 
having no true imagination, are apt, more than 
others, to try by startling realism to enforce the 
monstrosity that has no terror in itself. But it is 
nevertheless true, that, unless in the hands of the 
very greatest men, the grotesque seems better to 
be expressed merely in line, or light and shade, or 
mere abstract colour, so as to mark it for a thought 
rather than a substantial fact. Even if Albert Diirer 
had perfectly painted his Knight and Death, I ques- 
tion if we should feel it so great a thought as we 
do in the dark engraving. Blake, perfectly power- 



CHAP, vni] III. GROTESQUE , 109 

ful in the etched grotesque of the book of Job, fails 
always more or less as soon as he adds colour; not 
merely for want of power (his eye for colour being 
naturally good), but because his subjects seem, in a 
sort, insusceptible of completion; and the two in- 
expressibly noble and pathetic woodcut grotesques 
of Alfred RetheUs, Death the Avenger, and Death 
the Friend, could not, I think, but with disadvan- 
tage, be advanced into pictorial colour. 

And what is thus doubtfully true of the pathetic 
grotesque, is assuredly and always true of the jjest- 
ing grotesque. So far as it expresses any transient 
flash of . wit or satire, the less labour of line, or 
colour, given to its expression the better; elaborate 
jesting being always intensely painful. 

§ 9. For these several reasons, it seems not only 
permissible, but even desirable, that the art by which 
the grotesque is expressed should be more or less 
imperfect, and this seems a most beneficial ordin- 
ance as respects the hum^n race in general. For the 
grotesque being not only a most forceful instrument 
of teaching, but a most natural manner of expres- 
sion, springing as it does at once from any tendency 
to playfulness in minds highly comprehensive of 
truth; and being also one of the readiest ways in 
which such satire or wit as may be possessed by 
men of any inferior rank of mind can be for per- 
petuity expressed, it becomes on all grounds desir- 
able that what is suggested in times of play should 
be rightly sayable withcput toil; and what occurs to 
men of inferior power or knowledge. Buyable with- 
out any high degree of skill. Hence it is an infinite 
good to mankind when there is full acceptance of 
the grotesque, slightly sketched or expressed; and, 
if field for such expression be frankly granted, an 
enormous mass of intellectual power is turned to 
everlasting use, which, in this present century of 
ours, evaporates in street gibing or vain revelling; 
all the good wit and satire expiring in daily talk, 
(like foam on wine), which in the thirteenth and 
fourteenth centuries had a permitted and useful ex- 



xio OF 3:HE TBUE [part iv 

pressi<^ in the arts of 8Ci:4ptur© and illumination, 
like foam fixed into chalcedony. It is with a view 
(not the least important a»ion^ manj Others bearing 
upon art) to the reopening of this greOt field of human 
intelligence, long entirely closed, thot I am striving 
to introduce Gothic architecture into daily domestic 
use; and to revive the art of illumination i properly 
sc. called; not the art of miniature-painting jn books, 
or on vellum, which has ridiculously been confused 
with it; but of making writing, simple writing, beau- 
tiful to the eye, by investing it with the great chord 
of perfect colour, blue, purple, scarlet, white, ahd 
gold, and in that chord of colour, permittijhg the 
continual play of the fancy of the writer in every 
species of grotesque imagination, carefully exclud- 
ing shadow; the distinctive difference between illu- 
mination and painting proper, being, that illumination 
admits no shadows, hut only gradations of pure 
colour. And it is in this respect that illumination is 
specially fitted for grotesque expression; for, when I 
used the term ‘ pictorial dolour ’, just nCw, in spaak- 
ing of the completion of the grotesque of Death the 
Avenger, I meant to distinguish such colour from 
the abstract, shadeless hues which are eminently 
fitted for grotesque thought. The requirement, 
respecting the slighter grotes(me, is only that it shall 
be incompletely expressed. It may have light and 
shade without colour (as in etching and sculpture), 
or colour without light and shade (illumination), 
but must not, except in the hands of the greatest 
masters, have both. And for some conditions of the 
playful grotesque, the abstract ^olour is a much more 
delightful element of expression than the abstract 
light and shade. 

§ 10. Such being the manifold and precious uses 
of the true grotesque, it only remains for us to note 
carefully how it is to be distinguished from the false 
and vicious grotesque which results from idleness, 
instead of noble rest; from malice, instead of the 
solemn contemplation of necessary evil; and from 
general degradation of the human spirit, instead of 





CHAP, vmj III. GROTESQUE ill 

its subjection, or confusion, bv thoughts too 
for it. It is easy for the reaaer to conceive h<3f 
different the fruits of j;wo such different states of 
mind must be; and yet* how like in many respects, 
and apt to be mistake^j^ one for the other; how 
the jest which springs from mere fatuity, and vacant 
want of penetration or purpose, is everlastingly, in- 
finitely, separated from, and yet may sometimes be 
mistaken for, the bright, playful, fond, far-sighted 
jest of Plato, or the bitter, purposeful, sorrowing 
jest of Aristophanes; how, again, the horror which 
springs from guilty love of foulness and sin, may 
be often mistcien for the inevitable horror which a 
great mind must sometimes feel in the full and 
penetrative sense of their presence; how, finally, the 
vague and foolish inconsistencies of undisciplined 
dream or reverie may be mistaken for the compelled 
inconsistencies of thoughts too great to be well sus- 
tained, or clearly uttered. It is easy, I say, to under- 
stand what a difference there must indeed be between 
these; and yet how difficult it may be always to 
define it, or lay down laws for the discovery of it, 
except by the just instinct of minds set habitually 
in all things to^iscern right from wrong. 

§ 11. Neverfleless, one good and characteristic 
instance may be of service in marking the leading 
directions in which the contrast is discernible. On 
Plate I, I have put, beside each other, a piece of 
true grotesque, from the Lombard-Gothic, and of 
false grotesque from cladlical (Roman) architecture. 
They are both griffins ; the one on the left carries on 
his back one of the main pillars of the porch of the 
cathedral of Verona; the one on the right is on 
the frieze of the temple of Antoninus and Faustina 
at Rome, much celebrated by Renaissance and bad 
modem architects. 

In some respects, however, this classical griffin 
deserves its reputation. It is exceedingly fine in lines 
of composition, and, I believe (I have not examined 
the original closely), very exquisite in execution. 
For these reasons, it is all the better for our purpose. 



112 OF THE TRUE IDEAL [part iv 

I do not want to compare the worst false grotesque 
with the best true, but rather, on the contrary, the 
best false with the simplest true, in order to see 
how the delicately wrought lie fails in the presence 
of the rough truth; for rough truth in the present 
case it is, the Lombard sculpture being altogether 
untoward and imperfect in execution 
' § 12. ‘Well, but ’, the reader says, ‘ what do you 
mean by calling either of them true? There never 
were such beasts in the world as either of these?’ 

No, never : but the difference is, that the Lombard 
workman did really see a griffin in his imagination, 
and carved it from the life, meaning to declare to 
all ages that ho had verily seen with his immortal 
eyes such a griffin as that; but the classical work- 
man never saw a griffin at all, nor anything else; 
but put the whole thing together by line and rule. 

§ 13. ‘ How do you know that?’ 

Very easily. Look at the two, and think over 
them. You know a griffin is a beast composed of 
lion and eagle. The classical workman set himself 
to fit these together in the most ornamental way 
possible. He accordingly carves a sufficiently satis- 
factory lion’s body, then attaches very gracefully 
cut wings to the sides : then, because he cannot get 
the eagle’s head on the broad lion’s shoulders, fits 
the two together by something like a horse’s neck 
(some griffins being wholly composed of horse and 
eagle), then, finding the horse’s neck look weak and 
unformidable, he strengthens it by a series of bosses, 
like vertebrae, in front, and by a series of spiny 
cusps, instead of a mane, on the ridge; next, not 
to lose the whole leonine character about the neck, 
he gives a remnant of the lion’s beard, turned into 
a sort of griffin’s whisker, and nicely curled and 
pointed; then an eye, probably meant to look grand 
and abstracted, and therefore neither lion’s nor 

’ If there be any inaccuracy in the right-hand griffin, I am 
sorry, but am not answerable for it, as the plate has been faith- 
fully reduced from a large French lithograph, the best I could 
find. The other is from a sketch of my own. 



CHAP, vni] III. GROTESQUE v ’U3 

eagle’s; and, finally, an eagle’s beak, very sufficiently 
studied from a real one. The whole head being, 
it seems to him, still somewhat wanting in weight 
and power, he brings forward the right wing be- 
hind it, so as to enclose it with a bro^ line. This 
is the finest thing in the composition, and very 
masterly, both in thought, and in choice of the 
exactly right point where the lines of wing and beak 
should intersect (and it may be noticed in passing, 
that all men, who can compose at all, have this 
habit of encompassing or governing broken lines with 
broad ones, wherever it is possible, of which we shall 
see many instances hereafter). The whole griffin, 
thus gracefully composed, being, nevertheless, when 
all is done, a very composed griffin, is set to very 
quiet work, and raising his left foot, to balance his 
right wing, sets it on the tendril of a flower so 
lightly as not even to bend it down, though, in order 
to reach it, his left leg is made half as long again 
as his right. 

§ 14. We may be pretty sure, if the carver had 
ever seen a griffin, he would have reported of him 
as doing something else than that with his feet. Let 
us see what the Lombardic workman saw him doing. 

Remember, first, the griffin, though part lion and 
part eagle, has the united povyer of both. He is not 
merely a bit of lion and a bit of eagle, but whole 
lion, incorporate with whole eagle. So when we 
really see one, we may be quite sure we shall not 
find him wanting in anything necessary to the might 
either of beast or bird. 

Well, among things essential to the might of a 
lion, perhaps, on the whole, the most essential are 
his teeth. He could get on pretty well even with- 
out his claws, usually striking his prey down with a 
blow, woundless; but he could by no means get 
on without his teeth. Accordingly, we see that the 
real or Lombardic griffin has the carnivorous teeth 
bare to the root, and the peculiar hanging of the 
jaw at the back, which marks the flexible and gaping 
mouth of the devouring tribes. 

M. P., III. 


I 



0L4 OF THE TRUE IDEAL [? art iv 

Again; among things essential to the might of an 
©agle^ next to his wings (which are of course promin- 
ent in both examples), are his claws. It is no use 
his being able to tear anything with his beak, if 
he cannot first hold it in his claws; he has com- 
paratively no leonine power, of striking with his feet, 
but a magnificent power of grip with them. Accord- 
in^ly, we see that the real griffin, while his feet are 
heavy enough to strike like a lion’s, has them also 
extended far enough to give them the eagle’s grip 
with the back claw; and has, moreover, some of the 
bird-like wrinkled skin over the whole foot, marking 
this binding power the more; and that he has be- 
sides verily got something to hold with his feet, 
other than a flower, of which more presently. 

§ 15. Now observe, the Lombardic workman did not 
do all this because he had thought it out, as you and 
I are doing together; he never thought a bit about 
it. He simply saw the beast; saw it as plainly as 
you see the writing on this page, and of course could 
not be wrong in anything he told us of it. 

Well, what more does he tell us? Another thing, 
remember, essential to an eagle is that it should 
fly fast. It is no use its having wings at all if it is 
to be impeded in the use of them. Now it would 
be difficult to impede him more thoroughly than by 
giving him two cocked ears to catch the wind. 

Look, again, at the two beasts. You see the false 
griffin has them so set, and, consequently, as he 
flew, there would be a coiitinual humming of the 
wind on eaph side of his head, and he would have 
an infallible earache when he got home. But the 
real griffin has his ears flat to his head, and all the 
hair of them blown back, even to a point, by his 
fast flying, and the aperture is downwards, that he 
may hear anything going on upon the earth, where 
his prey is. In the false griffin the aperture is 
upwards. 

§ 16. Well, what more? As he is made up of the 
natures of lion and eagle, we may be very certain 
that a real griffin is, on the whole, fond of eating, 



116 


CHAP, viii] III. GR0TES<5tJE 

and that his throat will look as if he occasionally 
took father large pieces, besides being flexible enough 
to let him bend and stretch his head in every direc- 
tion as he flies. 

Look again at the two beasts. You see the false 
one has got those bosses upon his neck like vertebra , 
which must be infinitely in his way when he is swal- 
lowing, and which are evidently inseparable, so that 
he cannot stretch his neck any more than a horse. 
But the real griffin is ail loose about the neck, evi- 
dently being able to make it almost as much longer 
as he likes; to stretch and bend it anywhere, and 
swallow anything, besides having some of the grand 
strength of the bull’s dewlap in it when at rest. 

§ 17. What more? Having both lion and eagle 
in him, it is probable that the real griffin will have 
an infinite look of repose as well as power of activity. 
One of the notablest things about a lion is his 
magnificent indolence, his look of utter disdain of 
trouble when there is no occasion for it; as, also, 
one of the notablest things about an eagle is his 
look of inevitable vigilance, even when quietest. 
Look again at the two beasts. You see the false 
griffin is quite sleepy and dead in the eye, thus con- 
tradicting his ess^gle’s nature, but is putting himself 
to a great deal of unnecessary trouble with nis paws, 
holding one in a most painful position merely to 
touch a flower, and bearing the whole weight of his 
body on the other, thj^s contradicting his lion’s 
nature. 

But the real griffin is primarily, with his eagle’s 
nature, wide awake; evidently quite ready for what- 
ever may happen; and with his lion’s nature, laid all 
his length on his belly, prone and ponderous; his 
two paws as simply put out before him as a drowsy 

R ’s on a drawingroom hearth-rug; not but that 
8 got something to do with them, worthy of 
such paws; but he takes not one whit more trouble 
about it than is absolutely necessary. He has merely 
got a poisonous winged dragon to hold, and for such 
a little matter as that, he may as well do it lying 



m OF THE TRUE IDEAL [part iv 

down and at his ease, looking out at the same time 
for any other piece of work in his way. He takes 
the dragon by the middle, one paw under the wing, 
another above, gathers him up into a knot, puts two 
or three of his claws well into his back, crashing 
through the scales of it and wrinkling all the flesh 
Up from the wound, flattens him down against the 
pound, and so lets him do what he lilces. The 
dragon tries to bite him, but can only bring his head 
round far enough to get hold of his own wing, which 
he bites in agony instead; flapping the griffin’s dew- 
lap with it, and wriggling his tail up against the 
griffin’s throat; the griffin being, as to these minor 
proceedings, entirely indifferent, sure that the 
dragon’s body cannot drag itself one hair’s breadth 
off those ghastly claws, and that its head can do no 
harm but to itself. 

§ 18. Now observe how in all this, through every 
separate part and action of the creature, the imagin- 
ation is always right. It evidently cannot err; it 
meets every one of our requirements respecting the 
griffin as simply as if it were gathering up the bones 
of the real creature out of some ancient rock. It 
does not itself know or care, any more than the 
peasant labouring with his spade and axe, what is 
wanted to meet our theories or fancies. It knows 
simply what is there, and brings out the positive 
creature, errorless, unquestionable. So it is through- 
out art, and in all that the imagination does; if 
anything be wrong it is no’t the imagination’s fault, 
but some «inferior faculty’s, which would have its 
foolish say in the matter, ^and meddled with the 
imagination, and said, the bones ought to be put 
together tail first, or upside down. 

§ 19. This, however, we need not be amazed at, 
because the very essence of the imagination is already 
defined to be the seeing to the heart; and it is not 
therefore wonderful that it should never err; but 
it is wonderful, on the other hand, how the compos- 
ing legalism does nothing else than err. One would 
have thought that, by mere chance, in this or the 



117 


CHAP, viii] III. GROTESQUE 

other element of griffin, the griffin-composer might 
have struck out a truth; that he might have had 
the luck to set the ears back, or to give some grasp 
to the claw. But, no; from beginning to end it 
is evidently impossible for him to be anything but 
wrong; his whole soul is instinct with lies; no 
veracity can come within hail of him; to him, all 
regions of right and life are for ever closed. 

§ 20. And another notable point is, that while the 
imagination receives truth in this simple way, it is 
all the while receiving statutes of composition also, 
far more noble than those for the sake of which the 
truth was lost by the legalist. The ornamental 
lines in the classical griffin appear at first finer than 
in the other; but they only appear so because they 
are more commonplace and more palpable. The 
subtlety of the sweeping and rolling curves in the 
real griffin, the way they waver and change and 
fold, down the neck, and along the wing, and in and 
out among the serpent coils, is incomparably grander, 
merely as grouping of ornamental line, than any- 
thing in the other; nor is it fine as ornamental only, 
but as massively useful, giving weight of stone 
enough to answer the entire purpose of pedestal 
sculpture. Note, especially, the insertion of the 
three plumes of the dragon’s broken wing in the 
outer angle, just under the large coil of his body; 
this filling of the gap being one of the necessities, 
not of the pedestal bl^ck merely, but a means of 
getting mass and breadth, which all composers 
desire more or less, but which they seMom so per- 
fectly accomplish. 

So that taking the truth first, the honest imagin- 
ation gains everything; it has its griffinism, and 
grace, and usefulness, ajl at once : but the false 
composer, caring for nothing but himself and his 
rules, loses everything — griffinism, grace, and all. 

§ 21. I believe the reader will now sufficiently see 
how the terms ‘ true ’ and ‘ false ’ are in the most 
accurate sense attachable to the opposite branches of 
what might appear at first, in both cases, the merest 



Ill OF THE TRUE IDEAL [part iv 

wildness of inconsistent reverie. But they are even 
to be attached, in a deeper sense than that in which 
we have hitherto used them, to these two composi- 
tions. For the imagination hardly ever works in this 
intense way, unencumbered by the inferior facul- 
ties, unless it be under the influence of some solemn 
purpose or sentiment. And to all the falseness and 
all the verity of these two ideal creatures this farther 
falsehood and verity have yet to be added, that the 
classical griffin has, at least in this place, no other 
intent than that of covering a level surface with 
entertaining form; but the Lombardic griffin is a 
profound expression of the most passionate sym- 
bolism. Under its eagle’s wings are two wheels 
which mark it as connected, in the mind of him who 
wrought it, with the living creatures of the vision 
of Ezekiel : ‘ When they went, the ^*heels went by 
them, and whithersoever the spirit was to go, they 
went, and the wheels were lifted up over against 
them, for the spirit of the living creatures was in 
the wheels.’ Thus signed, the winged shape be- 
comes at once one of the acknowledged symbols of 
the Divine power; and, in its unity of lion and eagle, 
the workman of the middle ages always meant to 
set forth the unity of the human and divine natures 2. 
In this unity it bears up the pillars of the Church, 
set for ever as the corner stone. And the faithful 
and true imagination beholds it, in this unity, with 
everlasting vigilance and calrp omnipotence, restrain 
the seed of the serpent crushed upon the earth; 
leaving the head of it free, o^y for a time^ that it 
may inflict in its fury profounder destruction upon 
itself — in this also full of deep meaning. The 
Divine power does not slay the evil creature. It 
wounds and restrains it onjy. . Its final and deadly 
wound is inflicted by itself, 

^ At the extremities of the wings — not seen in the plate. 

* Compare the Vurgaiorio^ canto xxix, &c. 



CHAP. IX] 


OF FINISH 


119 


CHAPTER IX 

OF FINISH 

§ 1. I AM afraid the reader must be, by this time, 
almost tired of hearing about truth. But I cannot 
help this; the more I have examined the various 
forms of art, and exercised myself in receiving their 
differently intended impressions, the more I hSve 
found this truthfulness a final test, and the only 
test of lasting power; and, although our concern 
in this part of our inquiry is, professedly, with the 
beauty which blossoms out of truth, still I find my- 
self compelled always to gather it by the stalk, not 
by the petals. I cannot hold the beauty, nor be 
sure of it for a moment, but by feeling for that strong 
stem. 

We have, in the preceding chapters, glanced 
through the various operations of the imaginative 
power of man ; with this almost painfully monotonous 
result, that its greatness and honour were always 
simply in proportion to the quantity of truth it 
grasped. And now the question, left undetermined 
some hundred pages back (Chap. II, § 6), recurs to 
us in a simpler form than it could before. How far 
is this true imagination to be truly represented? 
How far should the pei^fect conception of Pallas be 
so given as to look like Pallas herself, rather than 
like the picture of Pallas? 

§ 2. A question, this, at present of notable inter- 
est, and demanding instant attention. For it seemed 
to us, in reasoning about Dante’s views of art, that 
he was, or might be, right in desiring realistic com- 
pleteness; and yet, in what we have just seen of 
the grotesque ideal, it seemed there w’as a certain 
desirableness in incompleteness. And the schools of 
art in Europe are, at this moment, set in two hostile 
ranks, not nobly hostile, but spitefully and scorn- 
fully; having for one of the main grounds of their 



OF FINISH 


120 


[part IV 


dispute the apparently simple question, how far a 
picture may be carried forward in detail, or how 
soon it may be considered as finished. 

I purpose, therefore, in the present chapter, to 
examine, as thoroughly as I can, the real significa- 
tion of this word, Finish, as applied to art, and to 
see if in this, as in other matters, our almost tire- 
some test is not the only right one; whether there 
be not a fallacious finish and a faithful finish, and 
whether the dispute, which seems to be only about 
completion and incompletion, has not therefore, at 
the bottom of it, the old and deep grounds of fallacy 
and fidelity. 

§ 3. Observe, first, there are two great and separate 
senses in which we call a thing finished, or well- 
finished. One, which refers to the mere neatness 
and completeness of the actual work, as we speak of 
a well-finished knife-handle or ivory toy (as opposed 
to ill-cut ones); and, secondly, a sense which refers 
to the effect produced by the thing done, as we call 
a picture well-finished if it is so full in its details, 
as to produce the effect of reality on the spectator. 
And, in England, we seem at present to value highly 
the first sort of finish which belongs to workmanship, 
in our manufactures and general doings of any kind, 
but to despise totally the impressive finish which 
belongs to the work; and therefore we like smooth 
ivories better than rough ones — but careless scrawls 
or daubs better than the iliost complete paintings. 
Now, I bel^ve that we exactly reverse the fitness of 
judgment in this matter, arfd that we ought, on 
the contrary, to despise the finish of workmanship, 
which is done for vanity’s sake, and to love the finish 
of work, which is done for truth’s sake — that we 
ought, in a word, to finish our ivory toys more 
roughly, and our pictures more delicately. 

Let us think over this matter. 

§ 4. Perhaps one of the most remarkable points of 
difference between the English and Continental 
nations is in the degree of finish given to their 
ordinary work. It is enough to cross from Dover to 



CHAP. IX] OF FINISH 121 

Calais to feel this difference; and to travel farther 
only increases the sense of it. English windows for 
the most part fit their sashes, and their woodwork 
is neatly planed and smoothed : French windows 
are larger, heavier, and framed with wood that looks 
as if it had been cut to its shape with a hatchet; 
they have curious and cumbrous fastenings, and can 
only be forced asunder or together by some ingenuity 
and effort, and even then not properly. So with 
everything else — French, Italian, and German, and, 
as far as I know, Continental. Foreign drawers do 
not slide as well as ours; foreign knives do not cut 
so well; foreign wheels do not turn so well; and 
we commonly plume ourselves much upon this, be- 
lieving that generally the English people do their 
work better and more thoroughly, or as they say, 
‘ turn it out of their hands in better style *, than 
foreigners. I do not know how far this is really the 
case. There may be a flimsy neatness, as well as a 
substantial roughness; it does not necessarily follow 
that the window which shuts easiest will last the 
longest, or that the harness which glitters the most 
is assuredly made of the toughest leather. I am 
afraid, that if this peculiar character of finish in our 
workmanship ever arose from a greater heartiness 
and thoroughness in our ways of doing things, it does 
so only now in the case of our best manufacturers; 
and that a great deal of the work done in England, 
however good in appearance, is but treacherous and 
rotten in substance. Still, I think that there is really 
in the English mind, for the most part, a stronger 
desire to do things as well as they can be done, and 
less inclination to put up with inferiorities or in- 
sufficiencies, than in general characterize the temper 
of foreigners. There is in this conclusion no ground 
for national vanity; for though the desire to do 
things as well as they can be done at first appears 
like a virtue, it is certainly not so in all its forms. 
On the contrary, it proceeds in nine cases out of ten 
more from vanity than conscientiousness; and that, 
moreover, often a weak vanity. I suppose that as 



122 


OF FINISH 


[PAET ly 

much finish is displayed in the fittings of the private 
carriages of our young rich men as in any other de- 
partment of English manufacture; and that our St 
James’s Street cabs, dogcarts, and liveries are sin- 
gularly perfect in their way. But the feeling with 
which this perfection is insisted upon (however de- 
sk able as a sign of energy of purpose) is not in 
itself a peculiarly amiable or noble feeling; neither 
is it an ignoble disposition which would induce a 
country gentleman to put up with certain deficiencies 
in the appearance of his country-made carriage. It 
is true that such philosophy may degenerate into 
negligence, and that much thought and long dis- 
cussion would be needed before we could determine 
satisfactorily the limiting lines between virtuous 
contentment and faultful carelessness ; but at all 
events we have no right at once to pronounce our- 
selves the wisest people because we like to do all 
things in the best way. There are many httle things 
which to do admirably is to waste both time and 
cost; and the real question is not so much whether 
we have done a given thing as well as possible, as 
whether we have turned a given quantity of labour 
to the best account. 

§ 5. Now, so far from the labour’s being turned 
to good account which is given to our English 
* finishing ’, I believe it to be usually destructive of 
the best powers of our workmen’s minds. For it is 
evident, in the first place, th^t there is almost always 
a useful and a useless finish; the hammering and 
welding which are necessary^ to produce a sword 
blade of the best quality, are useful finishing; the 
polish of its surface, useless i. In nearly all work 
this distinction will, more or less, take place be- 
tween substantial finish and apparent finish, or what 
may be briefly characterized as ‘ Make ’ and * Polish 
And so far as finish is bestowed for purposes of 
‘ make I have nothing to say against it. Even the 

1 With his Yemen sword for aid; 

Ornament it carried none, 

But the notches on the blade. 



OF FINISH 


123 


CHAP. IX] 

vanity which displays itself in giving strength to 
our work is rather a virtue than a vice. But so far 
as finish is bestowed for purposes of ‘ polish \ there 
is much to be said against it; this first, and very 
strongly, that the qualities aimed at in common 
finishing, namely, smoothness, delicacy, or fineness, 
cannot in reality exists in a degree worth admiring, 
in anything done by human hands. Our best finish- 
ing is but coarse and blundering work after all. We 
may smooth and soften, and sharpen till we are 
sick at heart; but take a good magnifying-glass to 
our miracle of skill, and the invisible edge is a jagged 
saw, and the silky thread a rugged cable, and the 
soft surface a granite desert. Let all the ingenuity 
and all the art of the human race be brought to bear 
upon the attainment of the utmost possible finish, 
and they could not do what is done in the foot of 
a fly, or the film of a bubble. God alone can finish; 
and the more intelligent the human mind becomes, 
the more the infiniteness of interval is felt between 
human and divine work in this respect. So then it 
is not a little absurd to weary ourselves in struggling 
towards a point which we never can reach, and to 
exhaust our strength in vain endeavours to produce 
qualities which exist inimitably and inexhaustibly 
in the commonest things around us. 

§ 6. But more than this : the fact is, that in multi- 
tudes of instances, instead of gaining greater fine- 
ness of finish by our wyk, we are only destroying 
the fine finish of nature, and substituting coarseness 
and imperfection. For instance, when a *ock of any 
kind has lain for some time exposed to the weather. 
Nature finishes it in her own way; first, she takes 
wonderful pains about its forms, sculpturing it into 
exquisite variety of dint and dimple, and rounding 
or hollowing it into contours, which for fineness no 
human hand can follow; then she colours it; and 
every one of her touches of colour, instead of being 
a powder mixed with oil, is a minute forest of living 
trees, glorious in strength and beauty, and conceal- 
ing wonders of structure, which in all probability are 



1*^4 


OF FINISH 


[part IV 

mysteries even to the eyes of angels. Man comes, 
and digs up this finished and marvellous piece of 
work, which in his ignorance he calls a ‘ rough 
stone He proceeds to finish it in hia fashion, 
that is, to split it in two, rend it into ragged blocks, 
and, finally, to chisel its surface into a large number 
of lumps and knobs, all equally shapeless, colourless, 
deathful, and frightful And the block, thus dis- 
figured, he calls ‘ finished and proceeds to build 
therewith, and thinks himself great, forsooth, and 
an intelligent animal. Whereas, all that he has 
really done is, to destroy with utter ravage a piece 
of divine art, which, under the laws appointed by 
the Deity to regulate His work in this world, it must 
take good twenty years to produce the like of again. 
This he has destroyed ^ and has himself given in its 
place a piece of work which needs no more intelli- 
gence to do than a pholas has, or a worm, or the 
spirit which throughout the world has authority over 
rending, rottenness, and decay. I do not say that 
stone must not be cut; it needs to be cut for certain 
uses; only I say that the cutting it is not ‘ finish- 
ing but wnfinishing, it; and that so far as the mere 
fact of chiselling goes, the stone is ruined by the 
human touch. It is with it as with the stones of the 
Jewish altar : ‘ If thou lift up thy tool upon it, thou 
hast polluted it ’. In like manner, a tree is a finished 
thing. But a plank, though ever so polished, is not. 
We need stones and plank^^ as we need food; but 
we no more bestow an additional admirableness upon 
stone in hdwing it, or upon ^ tree in sawing it, than 
upon an animal in killing it, 

§ 7. Well, but it will be said, there is certainly a 
kind of finish in stone-cutting, and in every other 
art, which ia meritorious, and which consists in 
smoothing and refining as much as possible. Yes, 
assuredly there is a meritorious finish. First, as it 
has just been said, that which fits a thing for its 
uses — as a stone to lie well in its place, or a cog 
of an engine-wheel to play well on another; and, 

1 See the base of the new Army and Navy Clubhouse. 



CHAP. IX] OF FINISH 125 

secondly,* a finish belonging properly to the arts; 
but that finish does not consist in smoothing or 
polishing, but in the completeness of the expression 
of ideas ^ For in painting, there is precisely the same 
difference between the ends proposed in finishing 
that there is in manufacture. Some artists finish 
for the finish sake; dot their pictures all over, 
as in some kinds of miniature-painting (when a wash 
of colour would have produced as good an effect) ; or 
polish their pictures all over, making the execution 
so delicate that the touch of the brush cannot be 
seen, for the sake of the smoothness merely, and of 
the credit they may thus get for great labour; which 
kind of execution, seen in great perfection in many 
works of the Dutch school, and in those of Carlo 
Dolce, is that polished ‘ language ’ against which I 
have spoken at length in various portions of the first 
volume; nor is it possible to speak of it with too 
great severity or contempt, where it has been made 
an ultimate end. 

But other artists finish for the impression’s sake, 
not to show their skill, nor to produce a smooth 
piece of work, but that they may, with each stroke, 
render clearer the expression of knowledge. And 
this sort of finish is not, properly speaking, so much 
completing the picture as adding to it. It is not 
that what is painted is more delicately done, but 
that infinitely more is painted. This finish is always 
noble, and, like all other noblest things, hardly ever 
understood or appreciated. I must here endeavour, 
more especially with respect to the state of quarrel 
between the schools of living painters,® to illustrate 
it thoroughly. 

§ 8. In sketching the outline, suppose of the trunk 
of a tree, as in Plate II, Fig. 1, it matters compara- 
tively little whether the outline be given with a bold, 
or a delicate line, so long as it is outline only. The 
work is not more ‘ finished ’ in one case than in the 
other ; it is only prepared for being seen at a greater 
or less distance. The real refinement or finish of 
the line depends, not on its thinness, but on its 



12©^ OF FINISH [part iv 

truly following the contours of the tree,* which it 
conventionally represents; conventionally, I say, 
because there is no such line rotind the tree, in 
reality; and it is set down not as an imitation, but 
a limitation of the form. But if we are to add 
shade to it as in Fig. 2, the outline must instantly 
be made proportionally delicate, not for the sake of 
delicacy as such, but because the outline will how, 
in many parts, stand not for limitation of form 
merely, but for a portion of the shadow within that 
form. Now, as a limitation it was true, but as a 
shadow it would be false, for there is no line of black 
shadow at the edge of the stem. It must, therefore, 
be madb so delicate as not to detach itself from the rest 
of the shadow where shadow exists, and only to be 
seen in the light where limitation is still necessary. 

Observe, then, the ‘ finish ’ of Fig. 2 as compared 
with Fig. 1 consists, not in its greater delicacy, but 
in the addition of a truth (shadow), and the removal, 
in a great degree, of a conventionalism (outline). 
All true finish consists in one or other of these things. 
Now, therefore, if we are to ‘ finish ’ farther, we 
must know more or see more about the tree. And 
as the plurality of persons who draw trees know 
nothing of them, and will not look at them, it 
results necessarily that the effort to finish is not 
only vain, but unfinishes — does mischief. In the 
lower part of the plate. Figs. 3, 4, 5, and 6 are fac- 
similes of pieces of line engraving, meant to repre- 
sent trunks of trees; S and 4 are the commonly 
accredited t^pes of tree-drawing among engravers 
in the eighteenth century ; 5 sfiid 6 are quite modern ; 
3 is from a large and important plate by Boydell, 
from Claude’s Molten Calf, dated 1781; 4 by Boydell 
in 1776, from Rubens’s Waggoner; 6 from a bom- 
bastic engraving, published about twenty years ago 
by Meulemeester of Brussels, from Raphael’s Moses 
at the Burning Bush; and 6 from the foreground 
of Miller’s Modern Italy, after Turner 

1 I take this example from Miller, because, on the whole, he 
is the best engraver of Turner whom we have. 





OF FINISH 


CHAP. IX] 


127 


AH- these represent, as far as the engraving goeSf 
simply nothing. They are not ‘ finished/' in any 
sense but this, that the paper has been covered wita 
lines. 4 is the best, because, in the origiad ^Ork 
of Kubens, the lines of the boughs, and their manner 
of insertion in the trunk, have been so strongly 
marked, that no engraving could quite efiace them; 
and, inasmuch as it represents these facta^, in the 
bpiLighs, that piece of engraving is more finished than 
thd other examples, while its own networked texture 
is still false and absurd; for there is no texture of 
this knitted-stocking-like description on boughs; and 
if there were, it would not be seen in the shadow, 
but in the light. Miller’s is spirited, and looks 
lustrous, but has no resemblance to the original 
bough of Turner’s, which is pale, and does not glitter. 
The Netherlands work is, on the whole, the worst; 
because, in its ridiculous double lines, it adds affect- 
ation and conceit to its incapacity. But in all th^se 
cases the engravers have worked in total ignorance 
both of what is meant by ‘ drawing ’, and of the 
form of a tree, covering their paper with certain 
lines, which they have been taught to plough in 
copper, as a husbandman ploughs in clay. 

§ 9. In the next three examples we have instances 
of endeavours at finish by the hands of artists them- 
selves, marking three stages of knowledge or insight, 
and three relative stages of finish. Fig. 7 is Claude’s 
(Liber Veritatis^ No. 140, facsimile by Boydell). It 
still displays an appalling ignorance of the forms 
of trees, but yet is, in mode of execution, better — 
that is, more finished — than the engravings, because 
not altogether mechanical, and showing some dim, 
far-away, blundering memory of a few facts in stems, 
such as their variations of texture and roundness, 
and bits of young shoots of leaves. 8 is Salvator’s, 
facsimiled from part of his original etching of the 
Finding of (Edipus. It displays considerable power 
of handling — not mechanical, but free and firm, and 
is just so much more finished than any of the others 
as it displays more intelligence about the way in 



128 OF FINISH [part iv 

which boughs gather themselves out of the stem, 
and about the varying character of their curves. 
Finally, Fig. 9 is good work. It is the root of the 
apple-tree in Albert Diirer’s Adam and Eve, and 
fairly represents the wrinkles of the bark, the smooth 
portions emergent beneath, and the general anatomy 
of growth. All the lines used conduce to the repre- 
sentation of these facts; and the work is therefore 
highly finished. It still, however, leaves out, as not 
to be represented by such kind of lines, the more 
delicate gradations of light and shade. I shall now 
‘ finish ’ a little farther, in the next plate (III), the 
mere insertion of the two houghs outlined in Fig. 1. 
I do this simply by adding assertions of more facts. 
First, I say that the whole trunk is dark, as com- 
pared with the distant sky. Secondly, I say that 
it is rounded by gradations of shadow, in the various 
forms shown. And, lastly, I say that (this being 
a bit of old pine stripped by storm of its bark) the 
wood is fissured in certain directions, showing its 
grain, or muscle ^ seen in complicated contortions at 
the insertion of the arm and elsewhere. 

§ 10. Now this piece of work, though yet far from 
complete (we will better it presently), is yet more 
finished than any of the others, not because it is 
more delicate or more skilful, but simply because it 
tells more truth, and admits fewer fallacies. That 
which conveys most information, with least inac- 
curacy, is always the highest finish; and the question 
whether we prefer art so finished, to art unfinished, 
is not one of taste at all. It is simply a question 
whether \,e like to know much or little; to see 
accurately or see falsely; and those whose taste in 
art (if they choose so to call it) leads them to like 
blindness better than sight, and fallacy better than 
fact, would do well to set themselves to some other 
pursuit than that of art. 

§ XI. In the above plate we have examined chiefly 
the grain and surface of the boughs; we have not 
yet noticed the finish of their curvature. If the 
reader will look back to the No. 7 (Plate II), which, 





CHAP, IX] Of fiSlSH 120 

in this respect, is the of all the set, he will 

immediately observe the exemplification it gives of 
Claude’s principal theory about trees; namely, that 
the boughs ai*ways parted from each other, two at a 
time, in the manner of the prongs of an ill-made 
table-fork. It may, perhaps, not be at once believed 
that this is indeed Claude’s theory respecting tree- 
structure, without some farther examples of his 
practice. I have, therefore, assembled on Plate IV, 
some (jf the most characteristic passaget of ramifi- 
cation in the Liber Veritatis; the plates themselves 
are sufficiently cheap (as they should be) and acces- 
sible to nearly every one, so that the accuracy of the 
facsimiles may be easily tested. I have given in 
Appendix I the numbers of the plates from which the 
examples are taken, and ib will be found that they 
have been lather improved than libelled, only omit- 
ting, of course, the surrounding leafage, in order to 
show accurately the branch outlines, with winch 
alone wo are at present concerned. And it would 
be difficult to bring together a series more totally 
futile and foolish, more singularly wrong (as the 
false griffin was), every way at once : they are stiff, 
and yet have no strength; curved, and yet have no 
flexibility; monotonous, and yet disorderly; un- 
natural, and yet uninventive. They are, in fact, of 
that commonest kind of tree bough which a child 
or beginner first draws experimentally; nay, I am 
well assured, that if this set of branches had been 
drawn by a schoolboy,^ ‘ out of his own head ’, his 
master would hardly have cared to sbpw them as 
signs of any promise in him. 

§ 12. ‘Well, but do not the trunks of trees fork, 
and fork mostly into two arms at a time?’ 

Yes; but under as stern anatomical law as the 
limbs of an animal; and those hooked junctions in 
Plate IV are just as accurately representative of the 
branching of wood as Plate A, fig. 2, is of a neck and 
shoulders. We should object to such a represent- 
ation of shoulders, because we have some interest 
in, and knowledge of, human form; w^e do not object 

M. p., HI. K 



130 OF FINISH [part iv 

to Claude’s trees, because we have no interest in, 
nor knowledge of, trees. And if it be still alleged 
that such work is nevertheless enough to give any 
one an ‘ idea ’ of a tree, I answer that it never gave, 
nor ever will give, an idea of a tree to any one who 
loves trees; and that, moreover, no idea, whatever 
its pleasantness, is of the smallest value, which is 
not founded on simple facts. What pleasantness 
may be in wrong ideas we do not here inquire; the 
only question for us has always been, and must 
always be. What are the facts? 

§ 13. And assuredly those boughs of Claude’s are 
not facts; and every one of their contours is, in 
the worst sense, unfinished, without even the ex- 
pectation or faint hope of possible refinement ever 
coming into them. I do not mean to enter here into 
the discussion of the characters of ramification ; that 
must bo in our separate inquiry into tree-structure 
generally; but I will merely give one piece of 
Turner’s tree-drawing as an example of what finished 
work really is, even in outline. In Plate V Fig. 1 is 
the contour (stripped, like Claude’s, of its foliage) 
of one of the distant tree-stems dn the drawing of 
Bolton Abbey. In order to show its perfectness 
better by contrast with bad work (as we have had, 
I imagine, enough of Claude), I will take a bit of 
Constable; Fig. 2 is the principal tree out of the 
engraving of the Lock on the Stour (Leslie’s Life 
of Conbtahle). It differs from the Claude outlines 
merely in being the kind of 'work which is produced 
by an uninventive person dashing about idly, with 
a brush, instead of drawing determinately wrong, 
with a pen : on the one hand worse than Claude’s, 
in being lazier; on the other a little better, in being 
more free, but, as representative of tree-form, of 
course still wholly barbarous. It is w'orth while to 
turn back to the description of the uninventive 
painter at work on a tree (Vol. II, chapter on Imagin- 
ative Association, § 11), for this trunk of Constable’s 
is curiously illustrative of it. One can almost see 
him, first bonding it to the right; then, having 





CHAP. IX] 


OF FINISH 


181 


gone long enough to the right, turning to the left; 
then, having gone long enough to the left, away 
to the right again; then dividing it; and ‘ because 
there is another tree in the picture with two long 
branches (in this case there really is), he knows 
that this ought to have three or four, which must 
undulate or go backwards and forwards ’, &o. &c. 

§ 14. Then study the bit of Turner work : note 
first its quietness, unattractiveness, apparent care- 
lessness whether you look at it or not; next note 
the subtle curvatures within the narrowest limits, 
and, when it branches, the unexpected, out-of-the- 
way things it does, ]ust what nobody could have 
thought of its doing; shooting out like a letter Y, 
with a nearly straight branch, and then correcting 
its stiffness with a zig-zag behind, so that the boughs, 
ugly individually, are beautiful in unison. (In what 
I have hereafter to say about trees, I shall need 
to dwell much on this character of unexpectedness, 
A bough is never drawn rightly if it is not wayward, 
so that although, as just now said, quiet at first, 
not caring to be looked at, the moment it is looked 
at, it seems bent on astonishing you, and doing the 
last things you expect it to do.) But our present 
purpose is only to note the finish of the Turner 
curves, which, though they seem straight and stiff 
at first, are, when you look long, seen to be all 
tremulous, perpetually wavering along every ed^e 
into endless melody o^ change. This is finish m 
line, in exactly the same sense that a fine melody 
is finished in the association of its notes*. 

§ 15. And now, farther, let us take a little bit of 
the Turnerian tree in light and shade. . I said above 
I would better the drawing of that pine trunk, which, 
though it has incipient shade, and muscular action, 
has no texture, nor local colour. Now, I take about 
an inch and a half of Turner’s ash trunks (one of the 
nearer ones in this same drawing of Bolton Abbey) 
(Fig. 3, Plate V), and this I cannot better; this is per- 
fectly finished; it is not possible to add more truth 
to it on that scale. Texture of bark, anatomy of 



132 OF FINISH [part iv 

muscle beneath, reflected lights in recessed hollows, 
stains of dark moss, and flickering shadows from 
the foliage above, all are there, as clearly as the 
human hand can mark them. I place a bit of trunk 
by Constable (Fig. 6) l from another plate in Leslie ’s 
Life of him (a dell in Helmingham Park, Suffolk), 
for the sake of the same comparison in shade that 
we have above in contour. You see Constable does 
not know whether he is drawing moss or shadow : 
those dark touches in the middle are confused in 
his mind between the dark stains on the trunk and 
its dark side; there is no anatomy, no cast shadow, 
nothing but idle sweeps of the brush, vaguely cir- 
cular. The thing is much darker than Turner’s, but 
it is not, therefore, finished; it is only blackened. 
And ‘ to blacken ’ is indeed the proper word for all 
attempts at finish*? without knowledge. All true finish 
is added fact ; smd Turner’s word for finishing a picture 
was always tiiis significant one, ‘ carry forward 
But labour without added knowledge can only blacken 
or stain a picture, it cannot finish it. . 

§ 16. And this is especially to be remembered as 
we pass from comparatively large and distant ob- 
jects, such as this single trunk, to the more divided 
and nearer features of foreground. Some degree of 
ignorance may be hidden, in completing what is far 
away; but there is no concealment possible in close 
work, and darkening instead of finishing becomes 
then the engraver’s only possible resource. It has 
always been a wonderful thmg to me to hear people 
talk of making foregrounds ‘ vigorous ’, marked 
‘ forcible ’, and so on. If you will lie down on your 
breast on the next bank you come to (which is 

1 Fig. 5 is not, however, so lustrous as Constable’s ; I cannot 
help this, having given the original plate to my good friend, 
Mr Cousen, with strict charge to facsimile it faithfully ; but 
the figure is all the faker, as a representation of Constable’s art, 
for those mezzotints in Leslie’s life of him have many qualities 
of drawing which are quite wanting in Constable’s blots of 
colour. The comparison shall be made elaborately, lietween 
picture and picture, in the section on Vegetation. 



I^I NIK V: (lool) AND J’.AIJ Tk1,1'-I )KA\ViNG 


.V./’., ///.] 


I f(l( C fi. Ti2 






/ /// 1 


Pl \ n VI T ( »Kl ( I >1 M) 1 b Af AGE 

l/acc / 13 



)F FINISH 


133 


bringing it dose enough, I should think, to give it 
all the forc§ it is capable of), you will see, in the 
cluster of leaves and grass close to your face, some- 
thing as delicate as this, which I have actually so 
drawn, on the opposite page, a mystery of soft 
shadow in the depths of the grass, with indefinite 
forms of leaves, which you cannot trace nor count, 
within it, and out of that, the nearer leaves coming 
in every subtle gradation of tender light and flicker- 
ing form, quite beyond all delicacy of pencilling to 
follow; and yet you will rise up from that bank 
(certainly not making it appear coarser by drawing 
a little back from it), and profess to represent it by 
a few blots of ‘ forcible ’ foreground colour. ‘ Well, 
but I cannot draw every leaf that I see on the bank. ’ 
No, for as we saw, at the beginning of this chapter, 
that no human work could be finished so as to express 
the delicacy of nature, so neither can it be finished 
so as to express the redundance of nature. Accept 
that necessity; but do not deny it; do not call your 
work finished, when you have, in engraving, subf. 
stituted a confusion of coarse black scratches, or in 
water-colour a few edgy blots, for ineffable organic 
beauty. Follow that beauty as far as you can, 
remembering that just as far as you see, know, and 
represent it, just so far your work is finished; as 
far as you fall short of it, your work is unfinished, 
and as far as you substitute any other thing for it, 
your work is spoiled. • 

§ 17. How far Turner followed it, is not easily 
shown; for his finish is so delicate as be nearly 
uncopiable. I have just said it was not possible 
to finish that ash trunk of his, farther, on such a 
scale 1. By using a magnifying-glass, and giving the 
same help to the spectator, it might perhaps be pos- 
sible to add and exhibit a few more details ; but even 
as it is, I cannot by line engraving express all that 
there is in that piece of tree-trunk, on the same 
scale. I have therefore magnified the upper part of 

^ It is of the exact size of the original, the whole drawing 
being about 15| inches by H in. 



134 OF, FINISH [part iv 

it in Fig. 4 (Plate V), so that the reader may better 
see the beantiful lines of curvature into which even 
its slightest shades and spots are cast. Every quarter 
of an inch of Turner’s drawings will bear magnifying 
in the same way; much of the finer work in them 
can hardly be traced, except by the keenest sight, 
until it is magnified. In his painting of Ivy Bridge 
the veins are drawn on the wings of a butterfly, 
not above three lines in diameter; and in one of his 
smaller drawings of Scarborough, in my own posses- 
sion, the muscle-shells on the beach are rounded, 
and some shown as shut, some as open, though none 
are twice as large as the letters of this type; and 
yet this is the man who was thought to belong to 
the ‘ dashing ’ school, literally because most people 
had not patience or delicacy of sight enough to trace 
his endless detail. 

§ 18. * Suppose it was so ’, perhaps the reader 
replies; ‘ still I do not like detail so delicate that 
it can hardly be seen. Then you like nothing in 
Nature (for you will find she always carries her detail 
too far to be traced). This point, however, we shall 
examine hereafter ; it is not the question now 
whether we like finish or not; our only inquiry here 
is, what finish means; and I trust the reader is be- 
ginning to be satisfied that it does indeed mean no- 
thing but consummate and accumulated truth, and 
that our old monotonous test must still serve us 
here as elsewhere. And it v^'li become us to consider 
seriously why (if indeed it be so) we dislike this 
kind of finish — dislike an accumulation of truth. For 
assuredly all authority is against us, and no truly 
great man can he named in the arts — hut it is that 
of one who finished to his utmost. Take Leonardo, 
Michael Angelo, and Raphael for a triad, to begin 
with. They all completed their detail with such 
subtlety of touch and gradation, that, in a careful 
drawing by any of the three, you cannot see where 
the pencil ceased to touch the paper; the stroke of 

1 An oil painting (about 3 ft. by 4 ft. 6 in.), and very broad 
in its masses. In the possession of E. Bicknell, Esq. 



OP FINISH 


135 


CHAP. IX] 

it is so tender, that, when you look close to the 
drawing you can see nothing ; you only see the 
effect of it a little way back I Thus tender in execu- 
tion — and so complete in detail, that Leonardo must 
needs draw every several vein in the little agates and 
pebbles of the gravel under the feet of the St Anne 
in the Louvre. Take a quartette after the triad — 
Titian, Tintoret, Bellini, and Veronese. Examine 
the vine-leaves of tlie Bacchus and Ariadne, (Titian’s) 
in the National Gallery; examine the borage 
blossoms, painted petal by petal, though lying loose 
on the table, in Titian’s Supper at Emmaus, in the 
Louvre, or the snail-shells on the ground in his 
Entombment i ; examine the separately designed 
patterns on every drapery of Veronese, in his Mar- 
riage in Cana; go to Venice and see how Tintoret 
paints the strips of black bark on the birch trunk 
that sustains the platform in his Adoration of the 
Magi; how Bellini fills the rents of his ruined walls 
with the most exquisite clusters of the erba della 
Madonna 2. You will find them all in a tale. Take 
a quintette after the quartette — Francia, Angelico, 
Diirer, Hemling, Perugino — and still the witness 
is one, still the same striving in all to such utmost 
perfection as their knowledge and hand could reach. 

Who shall gainsay these men? Above all, who 
shall gainsay them when they and Nature say pre- 
cisely the same thing? for where does Nature pause 
in her finishing — that finishing which consists not in 
the smoothing of surface, but the filling of space, 
and the multiplication of life and thought? 

Who shall gainsay them? I, for one, dare not; 
but accept their teaching, with Nature’s, in all 
humbleness. 

‘ But is there, then, no good in any work which 
does not pretend to perfectness? Is there no saving 

1 These snail-shells are very notable, occurriDg as they do in, 
perhaps, the very grandest and broadest of all Titian’s 
compositions. 

2 Linaria Cymbalaria, the ivy-leaved toadflax of English 
gardens. 



136 OF THE USE OF PICTURES [part iv 

clause from this terrible requirement of completion? 
And if there be none, what is the meaning of all you 
have said elsewhere about rudeness as the glory of 
Gothic work, and, even a few pages back, about the 
danger of finishing, for our modern workmen?’ 

Indeed there are many saving clauses, and there 
is ^much good in imperfect work. But we had better 
cast the consideration of these drawbacks and ex- 
ceptions into another chapter, and close this one, 
without obscuring, in any wise, our broad conclusion 
that ‘ finishing ’ means in art simply ‘ telling more 
truth and that whatever we have in any sort 
begun wisely, it is good to finish thoroughly. 


CHAPTER X 

OF THE USE OF PICTURES 

§ 1. I AM afraid this will be a difficult chapter; 
one of drawbacks, qualifications, and exceptions. 
But the more I see of useful truths, the more I find 
that, like human beings, they are eminently biped; 
and, although, as far as apprehended by human in- 
telligence, they are usually seen in a crane-like, 
posture, standing on one leg, whenever they are to 
be stated so as to maintain themselves against all 
attack it is quite necessary th/?y should stand on two, 
and have their complete balance on opposite fulcra. 

§ 2. I dcxibt not that one, objection, with which 
as well as with another we may begin, has struck 
the reader very forcibly, after comparing the illus- 
trations above given from Turner, Constable, and 
Claude. He will wonder how it was that Turner, 
finishing in this exquisite way, and giving truths 
by the thousand, where other painters gave only one 
or two, yet, of all painters, seemed to obtain least 
acknowledgeable resemblance to nature, so that the 
world cried out upon him for a madman, at the 
moment when he was giving exactly the highest and 



CHAP, x] OF THE USE OF PICTUBES 187 

most Consummate truth that had ever been seen in 
landscape. 

And he will wonder why still there seems reason 
for this outcry. Still, after what analysis and proof 
of his being right have as yet been given, the reader 
may perhaps be saying to himself : ‘ All this reason- 
ing is of no use to me. Turner does not give me the 
idea of nature; I do not feel before one of his pic- 
tures as I should in the real scene. Constable tatkes 
me out into the shower, and Claude into the sun; 
and De Wint makes me feel as if I were walking in 
the fields; but Turner keeps me in the house, and 
I know always that I am looking at a picture.’ 

I might answer to this : Well, what else should 
he do? If you want to feel as if you were in a 
shower, cannot you go and get wet without help from 
Constable? If you want to feel as if you were walk- 
ing in the fields, cannot you go and walk in them 
without help from De Wint? But if you want to 
sit in your room and look at a beautiful picture, 
why should you blame the artist for giving you one? 
This was the answer actually made to me by various 
journalists, when first I showed that Turner was 
truer than other painters : ‘ Nay ’, said they, ‘ we 
do not want truth, we want something else than 
truth ; we would not have nature, but something 
better than nature.’ 

§ 3. I do not mean to accept that answer, although 
it seems at this moment to make for me : I have 
never accepted it. As* I raise my eyes from the 
paper, to think over the curious mingling in it, of 
direct error, and far-away truth, I see upon the room- 
walls, first. Turner’s drawing of the chain of the 
Alps from the Superga above Turin; then a study 
of a block of gneiss at Chamouni, with the purple 
Aiguilles-Rougos behind it; another, of the towers 
of the Swiss Fribourg, with a cluster of pine forest 
behind them; then another Turner, Isola Bella, with 
the blue opening to the St Gothard in the distance; 
and then a fair bit of thirteenth-century illumina- 
tion, depicting, at the top of the page, the Saluta- 



188 OF THE USE OF PICTURES [part iv 

tion; and beneath, the painter who painted it, sitting 
in his little convent cell, with a legend above him 
to this effect 

jego jojjfa atpax librum. 

I, John, wrote this book. 

None of these things are bad pieces of art; and 
yet — ^if it were offered me to have, instead of them, 
so many windows, out of which I should see, first, 
the real chain of the Alps from the Superga; then 
the real block of gneiss, and Aiguilles-Rouges ; then 
the real towers of Fribourg, and pine forest; the 
real Isola Bella; and, finally, the true Mary and 
Elizabeth; and beneath them, the actual old monk 
at work in his cell — would very unhesitatingly 
change my five pictures for the five windows; and 
so, I apprehend, would most people, not, it seems 
to me, unwisely. 

‘ Well, then ’, the reader goes on to question me, 
‘ the more closely the picture resembles such a 
window, the better it must be?’ 

Yes. 

‘ Then if Turner does not give me the impression 
of such a window, that is, of Nature, there must 
be something wrong in Turner?’ 

Yes. 

‘ And if Constable and De Wint give me the impres- 
sion of such a window, there must be something 
right in Constable and De Wint?’ 

Yes. 

‘ And something more right than in Turner?’ 

No. 

‘ Will you explain yourself?’ 

I have explained myself, long ago, and that fully; 
perhaps too fully for the simple sum of the explana- 
tion to be remembered. If the reader will glance 
back to, and in the present state of our inquiry 
reconsider in the first volume. Part I, Sec. I, Chap. 
V, and Part II, Sec. I, Chap. VII, he will find our 
present difficulties anticipated. There are some 
truths, easily obtained, which give a deceptive re- 



CHAP. X] OF THE USE OF PICTUIIES 189 

semblance to Nature; others only to be obtained 
with difficulty, which cause no deception, but give 
inner and deep resemblance. These two classes of 
truths cannot be obtained together; choice must be 
made between them. The bad painter gives the 
cheap deceptive resemblance. The good painter gives 
the precious non -deceptive resemblance. Constable 
perceives in a landscape that the grass is wet, the 
meadows flat, and the boughs shady; that is to 
say, about as much as, I suppose, might In general 
be apprehended, between them, by an intelli- 
gent fawn, and a skylark. Turner perceives at a 
glance the whole sum of visible truth open to human 
intelligence. So Berghem perceives nothing in a 
figure, beyond the flashes of light on the folds of its 
dress; but Michael Angelo perceives every flash of 
thought that is passing through its spirit : and Con- 
stable and Berghem may imitate windows; Turner 
and Michael Angelo can by no means imitate win- 
dows. But Turner and Michael Angelo are never- 
theless the best. 

§ 4. ‘ Well, but ’, the reader persists, ‘ you 
admitted just now that because Turner did not get 
his work to look like a window there was something 
wrong in him.’ 

I Hid so ; if he were quite right he would have 
all truth, low as well as high; that is, he would be 
Nature and not Turner : but that is impossible to 
man. There is much ^lat is wrong in him; much 
that is infinitely wrong in all human effort. But, 
nevertheless, in some an infinity of Betterness above 
other human effort. 

‘ Well, but you said you would change your 
Turners for windows, why not, therefore, for Con- 
stables ? ’ 

Nay, I did not say that I would change them 
for windows merely, but for windows which com- 
manded the chain of the Alps and Isola Bella. 
That is to say, for all the truth that there is in 
Turner, and all the truth besides which is not in 
him; but I would not change them for Constables, 



140 OF THE USE OF PICTURES [part iv 

to have a small piece of truth which is not in Turner, 
and none of the mighty truth which there is. 

§ 5. Thus far, then, though the subject is one 
requiring somewhat lengthy explanation, it involves 
no real difficulty. There is not the slightest incon- 
sistency in the mode in which throughout this work 
I Ahave desired the relative merits of painters to be 
judged. I have always said, he who is closest to 
Nature is best. All rules are useless, all genius is 
useless, all labour is useless, if you do not give facts; 
the more facts you give the greater you are; and 
there is no fact so unimportant as to be prudently 
despised, if it bo possible to represent it. Nor, but 
that I have long known the truth of Herbert’s lines, 

Some men are 

Full of themselves, and answer their own notion, 

would it have been without intense surprise that I 
heard querulous readers asking, ‘ how it was pos- 
sible ’ that I could praise Pre-Raphaelitism and 
Turner also. For, from the beginning of this book 
to this page of it, I have never praised Turner highly 
for any other cause than that he gave facta more 
delicately, more Pre-Raphaelitically, than other men. 
Careless readers, who dashed at the descriptions 
and missed the arguments, took up their own con- 
ceptions of the cause of my liking Turner, and said 
to themselves : ‘ Turner cannot draw, Turner is 

generalizing, vague, visionary,; and the Pre-Raphael- 
ites are hard and distinct. How can any one like 
both?’i. But I never said .that Turner could not 

1 People of any sense, however, confined themselves to 
wonder. I think it was only in The Art Journal of September 
1st, 1854, that any writer had the meanness to charge me with 
insincerity. ‘ The pictures of Turner atid the works of the 
Pre-Raphaelites are the very antipodes of each other ; it is, 
therefore, impossible that one and the same individual can with 
any show of sincerity [Note, by the way, the Art-Union has no 
idea that real sincerity is a thing existent or possible at all. 
All that it expects or hopes of human nature is, that it should 
have show of .sincerity.] stand forth as the thick and thin [I 
perceive the writer intends to teach me English, as well as 



CHAP. X] OF THE USE OF PICTUKES 141 

draw. I never said that he was vague or visionary. 
What I said was, that nobody had ever drawn so 
well: that nobody was so certain, so wn- visionary ; 
that nobody had ever given so many hard and down- 
right facts. Glance back to the first volume, and 
note the expressions now. ‘ He is the only painter 
who ever drew a mountain or a stone i ; the only 
painter who can draw the stem of a tree; the only 
painter who has ever drawn the sky, previous artists 
having only drawn it typically or partially, but he 
absolutely and universally.’ Note how he is praised 
in his rock drawing for ‘ not selecting a pretty or 
interesting morsel here or there, but giving the 
whole truth, with all the relations of its parts ’ 2. 
Observe how the great virtue of the landscape of 
Cima da Conegliano and the early sacred painters is 
said to be giving ‘ entire, exquisite, humble, real- 
ization — a strawberry-plant in the foreground with 
a blossom, arid a berry just set^ and one half ripe, 
and one ripe, all patiently and innocently painted 
from the real thing, and therefore most divine.' 
Then re-read the following paragraph (§ 10), care- 
fully, and note its conclusion, that the thoroughly 
great men are those who have done everything 
thoroughly, and who have never despised anything, 


honesty.] eulogist of both. With a certain knowledge of art, 
such as may be possessed by the author of English Painters, 
[Note, farther, that the eminent critic does not so much as 
know the title of the book ^e is criticizing.] it is not difficult 
to praise any bad or mediocre picture that may be qualified 
with extravagance or mysticism. This author owes the public 
a heavy debt of explanation, which a lifetime spent in ingenious 
reconciliations would not suffice to discharge. A fervent 
admiration of certain pictures by Turner, and, at the same 
time, of some of the severest productions of the Pre-Raphaelites, 
presents an insuperable problem to persons whose taste in art 
18 regulated by definite principles.’ 

1 Part II, Sec. I, Chap. VII, § 46. 

2 Part II. Sec. IV, Chap. IV, § 23., and Part II, Sec. I, 
Chap. VII, ^ 9. The whole of the Preface to the Second 
Edition is written to maintain this one point of specific detail 
agaiust the advocates of generalization. 



142 OF THE USE OF PICTURES [part iv 

however small, of God’s making; with the instance 
given* of Wordsworth % daisy casting its shadow on 
a stone; and the following sentence, ‘ Our painters 
must come to this before they have done their duty. ’ 
And yet, when our painters did come to this, did 
do their duty, and did paint the daisy with its 
shadow (this passage having been written years be- 
fore Pre-Raphaelitism was thought of), people won- 
dered how I could possibly like what was neither 
more nor less than the precise fulfilment of my own 
most earnest exhortations and highest hopes. 

§ 6. Thus far, then, all I have been saying is 
absolutely consistent, and tending to one simple 
end. Turner is praised for his truth and finish; that 
truth of which I am beginning to give examples. 
Pre-Raphaelitism is praised for its truth and finish; 
and the whole duty inculcated upon the artist is that 
of being in all respects as like Nature as possible. 

And yet this is not all I have to do. There is 
more than this to be inculcated upon the student, 
more than this to be admitted or established, be- 
fore the foundations of just judgment can be laid. 

For, observe, although I believe any sensible person 
would exchange his pictures, however good, for win- 
dows, he would not feel, and ought not to feel, that the 
arrangement was entirely gainful to him. He would 
feel it was an exchange of a less good of one kind, 
for a greater of another kind, but that it was de- 
finitely exchange f not pure gain, not merely getting 
more truth instead of less. The picture would be a 
serious loss; something gone which the actual land- 
scape could never restore, though it might give some- 
thing better in its place, as age may give to the heart 
something better than its youthful delusion, but 
cannot give again the sweetness of that delusion. 

§ 7. What is this in the picture which is precious 
to us, and yet is not natural? Hitherto our argu- 
ments have tended, on the whole, somewhat to the 
depreciation of art; and the reader may every now 
and then, so far as he has been convinced by them, 
have been inclined to say, ‘ Why not give up this 



CHAP, x] 0 ¥ THE USE OF PICTURES 14a 

whole science of Mockery at once, since its onl^^ 
virtue is in representing facts, and it cannot, 
best, represent them completely, besides being liabl4 
to all manner of shortcomings and dishonesties— 
why not keep to the facts, to real fields, and hills, 
and men, and let this dangerous painting alone?* 

No, it would not be well to do this. Painting has 
its peculiar virtues, not only consistent with, but 
even resulting from, its shortcomings and weaknesses. 
Let us see vmat these virtues are. 

§ 8. I must ask permission, as I have sometimes 
done before, to begin apparently a long way from the 
point. 

Not long ago, as I was leaving one of the towns 
of Switzerland, early in the morning, I saw in the 
clouds behind the houses an Alp which I did not 
know, a grander Alp than any I knew, nobler than 
the Schreckhorn or the Monch; terminated, as it 
seemed, on one side by a precipice of almost un- 
imaginable height; on the other, sloping away for 
leagues in one field of lustrous ice, clear and fair 
and blue, flashing here and there into silver under 
the morning sun. For a moment I received a sensa- 
tion of as much sublimity as any natural object could 
possibly excite; the next moment, I saw that my 
unknown Alp was the glass roof of one of the work- 
shops of the town, rising above its nearer houses, 
and rendered aerial and indistinct by some pure blue 
wood smoke which rose from intervening chimneys. 

It is evident, that so *far as the mere delight of 
the eye was concerned, the glass roof was l^iere equal, 
or at least equal for a moment, to the Alp. Whether 
the power of the object over the heart was to be 
small or great, depended altogether upon what it 
was understood for, upon its being taken possession 
of and apprehended in its full nature, either as a 
granite mountain or a group of panes of glass; and 
thus, always, the real majesty of the appearance of 
the thing to us, depends upon the degree in which 
we ourselves possess the power of understanding it, 
— that penetrating, possession -taking power of the 



144 OF THE USE OF PICTURES [paet iv 

imagination, which has been long ago defined i as 
the very life of the man, considered as a seeing 
creature. For though the casement had indeed been 
an Alp, there are many persons on whose minds it 
would have produced no more effect than the glass 
roof. It would have been to them a glittering object 
of a certain apparent length and breadth, and 
whether of glass or ice, whether twenty feet in length, 
or twenty leagues, would have made no difference 
to them; or, rather, would not have been in any 
wise conceived or considered by them. Examine the 
nature of your own emotion (if you feel it) at the 
sight of the Alp, and you find all the brightness 
of that emotion hanging, like dew on gossamer, on 
a curious web of subtle fancy and imperfect know- 
ledge. First, you have a vague idea of its size, 
coupled with wonder at the work of the great 
Builder of its walls and foundations, then an appre- 
hension of its eternity, a pathetic sense of its per- 
petualness, and your own transientness, as of the 
grass upon its sides; then, and in this very sad- 
ness, a sense of strange companionship with past 
generations in seeing what they saw. They did not 
see the clouds that are floating over your head; nor 
the cottage wall on the other side of the field; nor 
the road by which you are travelling. But they saw 
that. The wall of granite in the heavens was the 
same to them as to you. They have ceased to look 
upon it; you will soon ce^se to look also, and the 
granite wall will be for others. Then, mingled with 
these mo»e solemn imaginations, come the under- 
standings of the gifts and glories of the Alps, the 
fancying forth of all the fountains that well from 
its rocky walls, and strong rivers that ane born out 
of its ice, and of all the pleasant valleys that wind 
between its cliffs, and all the chfilets that gleam 
among its clouds, and happy farmsteads couched 
upon its pastures; while together with the thoughts 
of these, rise strange sympathies with all the un- 
known of human life, and happiness, and death, 
1 Yol. II. Chapter on ‘ Penetrative Imagination.’ 



CHAP. X] OF THE USE OP PICTURES 145 

signified by that narrow white flame of the everlast- 
ing snow, seen so far in the morning sky. 

These images, and far more than these, lie at 
the root of the emotion which you feel at the sight 
of the Alp. You may not trace them in your heart, 
for there is a great deal more in your heart, of evil 
and good, than you ever can trace; but they stir you 
and quicken you for all that. Assuredly, so far as you 
feel more at beholding the snowy mountain than any 
other object of the same sweet silvery grey, these 
are the kind of images which cause you to do so; 
and, observe, these are nothing more than a greater 
apprehension of the facts of the thing. We call the 
power ‘ Imagination ’, because it imagines or con- 
ceives; but it is only noble imagination if it imagines 
or conceives the truth. And, according to the degree 
of knowledge possessed, and of sensibility to the 
pathetic or impressive character of the things known, 
will be the degree of this imaginative delight. 

§ 9. But the main point to be noted at present 
is, that if the imagination can be excited to this 
its peculiar work, it matters comparatively little 
what it is excited by. If the smoke had not cleared 
partially away, the glass roof might have pleased 
me as well as an Alp, until I had quite lost sight 
of it; and if, in a picture, the imagination can be 
once caught, and, without absolute affront fi:*om 
some glaring fallacy, set to work in its own field, 
the imperfection of thq historical details themselves 
is, to the spectator’s enjoyment, of small conse- 
quence. o 

Hence it is, that poets, and men of strong feeling 
in general^ are apt to be among the very worst judges 
of painting. The slightest hint is enough for them. 
Tell them that a white stroke means a ship, and a 
black stain, a thunderstorm, and they will be per- 
fectly satisfied with both, and immediately proceed 
to remember all that they ever felt about ships and 
thunderstorms, attributing the whole current and 
fulness of their own feelings to the painter’s work; 
while probably, if the picture be really good, and 
M. P., III. L % 



1*6 OF THE USE OF PICTURES [part iv 

full of stern fact, the poet, or man of feeling, will 
find some of its fact in his way^ out of the particular 
course of his own thoughts — be offended at it, take 
to criticizing and wondering at it, detect, at last, 
some imperfection in it — such as must be inherent in 
all human work — and so finally quarrel with, and 
reject the whole thing. Thus, Wordsworth writes 
nifany sonnets to Sir George Beaumont and Haydon, 
none to Sir Joshua or to Turner. 

§ 10. Hence, also the error into which many super- 
ficial artists fall, in speaking of ‘ addressing the 
imagination ’ as the only end of art. It is quite true 
that the imagination must be addressed; but it may 
be very suffiGiently addressed by the stain left by an 
ink-bottle thrown at the wall. The thrower has little 
credit, though an imaginative observer may find, per- 
haps, more to amuse him in the erratic nigrescence 
than in many a laboured picture. And thus, in a 
slovenly or ill-finished picture, it is no credit to the 
artist that he has ‘ addressed the imagination 
nor is the success of such an appeal any criterion 
whatever of the merit of the work. The duty of an 
artist is not only to address and awaken, but to 
guide the imagination; and there is no safe guidance 
but that of simple concurrence with fact. It is no 
matter that the picture takes the fancy of A or B, 
that C writes sonnets to it, and D feels it to be 
divine. This is still the only question for the artist, 
or for us : ‘ Is it a fact? Are things really so?’ 
* Is the picture an Alp among pictures, full, firm, 
eternal; or only a glass house, frail, hollow, con- 
temptible, demolishable ; calling, at all honest hands, 
for detection and demolition?’ 

§ 11. Hence it is also that so much grievous diffi- 
culty stands in the way of obtaining real opinion 
about pictures at all. Tell any man, of the slightest 
imaginative power, that such and such a picture 
is good, and means this or that : tell him, for in- 
stance, that a Claude is good, and that it means 
trees, and grass, and water; and forthwith, what- 
ever faith, virtue, humility, and imagination there 



CHAP. X] 0¥ THE USE OF PICTURES 147 

are in the man, rise up to help Claude, and to declare 
that indeed it is all ‘ excellent good, i ’faith’; and 
whatever in the course of his life he has felt of 
pleasure in trees and grass, he will begin to reflect 
upon and enjoy anew, supposi^ all the while it is 
the picture he is enjoying, ^nce, when once a 
painter’s reputation is accredited, it must be a stub- 
born kind of person indeed whom he will not please, 
or seeni to please; for all the vain and weak people 
pretend to be pleased with him, for their own credit’s 
sake, and all the humble and imaginative people 
seriously and honestly fancy they are pleased with 
him, deriving indeed, very certainly, delight from his 
work, but a delight whicn, if they were kept in the 
same temper, they would equally derive (and, indeed, 
constantly do derive) from the grossest daub that 
can be manufactured in imitation by the pawnbroker. 
Is, therefore, the pawnbroker’s imitation as good 
as the original? Not so. There is the certain test 
of goodness and badness, which I am always striv- 
ing to get people to use. As long as they are satis- 
fied if they find their feelings pleasantly stirred and 
their fancy gaily occupied, so long there is for them 
no good, no bad. Anything may please, or any- 
thing displease, them; and their entire manner of 
thought and talking about art is mockery, and all 
their judgments are laborious injustices. But let 
them, in the teeth of their pleasure or displeasure, 
simply put the calm question. Is it so? Is that the 
way a stone is shaped, the way a cloud is wreathed, 
the way a leaf is veined? and they are safe. They 
will do no more injustice to themselves nor to other 
men; they will learn to whose guidance they may 
trust their imagination, and from whom they must 
for ever withhold its reins. 

§ 12. ‘Well, but why have you dragged in this 
poor spectator’s imagination at all, if you have no-* 
thing more to say for it than this ; if you are merely 
going to abuse it, and go back to your tiresome 
facts?* 

Nay; I am not going to abuse it. On the con- 



%m OF THE USE OF PICTURES [part iv 

I have to assert, in a temper profoundly vener- 
ant of it, that though we must not suppose every- 
thing is right when this is aroused, we may be sure 
that something is wrong when this is not aroused. 
The something wrong may be in the spectator or 
in the picture; and if the picture be demonstrably 
in accordance with truth, the odds are, that it is 
in the spectator ; but there is wrong somewhere ; for 
the work of the picture is indeed eminently to get 
at this imaginative power in the beholder, and all 
its facts are of no use whatever if it does not. No 
matter how much truth it tells if the hearer be asleep. 
Its first work is to wake him, then to teach him. 

§ 13. Now, observe, while, as it penetrates into 
the nature of things, the imagination is pre-eminently 
a beholder of things as they arc, it is, in its creative 
function, an eminent beholder of things when and 
where they are not; a seer, that is, in the prophetic 
sense, calling ‘ the things that are not as though 
they were and for ever delighting to dwell on that 
which is not tangibly present. And its great func- 
tion being the calling forth, or back, that which is 
not visible to bodily sense, it has of course been 
made to take delight in the fulfilment of its proper 
function, and pre-eminently to enjoy, and spend its 
energy on, things past and future, or out of sight, 
rather than things present, or in sight. So that if 
the imagination is to be called to take delight in any 
object, it will not be always well, if we can help 
it, to put the real object there ^ before it. The imagin- 
ation woul(^ on the whole rather have it not there; 
the reality and substance are' rather in the imagin- 
ation’s way; it would think a good deal more of 
the thing if it could not see it. Hence, that strange 
and sometimes fatal charm, which there is in all 
things as long as we wait for them, and the moment 
we have lost them; but which fades while we poss- 
ess them; that sweet bloom of all that is far away, 
which perishes under our touch. Yet the feeling of 
this is not a weakness ; it is one of the most glorious 
gifts of the human mind, making the whole infinite 



CHAP. X] OF THE USE OF PICTURES 140 

future, and imperishable past, a richer inheritance, 
if faithfully inherited, than the changeful, frail, jSeet- 
ing present; it is also one of the many witnesses 
in us to the truth that these present and tangible 
things are not meant to satisfy us. The instinct be- 
comes a weakness only when it is weakly indulged, 
and when the faculty which was intended by God 
to give back to us what we have lost, and gild for 
us what is to come, is so perverted as only to darken 
what we possess. But, perverted or pure, the in- 
stinct itself is everlasting, and the substantial 
presence even of the things which we love the best, 
will inevitably and for ever be found wanting in one 
strange and tender charm, which belonged to the 
dreams of them. 

§ 14. Another character of the imagination is 
equally constant, and, to our present inquiry, of yet 
greater importance. It is eminently a weariable 
faculty, eminently delicate, and incapable of bearing 
fatigue; so that if wo give it too many objects at 
a time to employ itself upon, or very grand ones 
for a long time together, it fails under the effort, 
becomes jaded, exactly as the limbs do by bodily 
fatigue, and incapable of answering any farther appeal 
till it has had rest. And this is the real nature of 
the weariness which is so often felt in travelling, 
from seeing too much. It is not that the monotony 
and number of the beautiful things seen have made 
them valueless, but that the imaginative power has 
been overtaxed; and, instead of letting it rest, the 
traveller, wondering to find himself dull, and in- 
capable of admiration, seeks, for something more 
admirable, excites and torments, and drags the poor 
fainting imagination up by the shoulders : ‘ Look at 
this, and look at that, and this more wonderful still I’ 
— until the imaginatit^o faculty faints utterly away, 
beyond all farther torment, or pleasure, dead for 
rhany a day to come; and the despairing prodigal 
takes to horse-racing in the Campagna, good now 
for nothing else than that; whereas, if the imagin- 
ation had only been laid down on the grass, among 



150 OF THE USE OF PICTURES [part iv 

simple things, and left quiet for a little while, it 
would have come to itself gradually, recovered its 
strength and colour, and soon been fit for work 
again. So that, whenever the imagination is tired, 
it is necessary to find for it something, not more 
admirable but less admirable; such as in that weak 
state it can deal with; then give it peace, and it 
will recover. 

§ 16 . I well recollect the walk on which I first 
found out this; it was on the winding road from 
Sallenche, sloping up the hills towards St Gervais, 
one cloudless Sunday afternoon. The road circles 
softly between bits of rocky bank and mounded pas- 
ture; little cottages and chapels gleaming out from 
among the trees at every turn. Behind me, some 
leagues in length, rose the jagged range of the moun- 
tains of the R^posoir; on the other side of the valley, 
the mass of the Aiguille de Varens, heaving its seven 
thousand feet of clifi into the air at a single effort, 
its gentle gift of waterfall, the Nant d’Arpenaz, like 
a pillar of cloud at its feet; Mont Blanc and all its 
aiguilles, one silver flame, in front of me; marvellous 
blocks of mossy granite and dark glades of pine 
around me; but I could enjoy nothing, and could not 
for a long while make out what was the matter with 
me, until at last I discovered that if I confined my- 
self to one thing — and that a little thing — a tuft 
of moss, or a single crag at the top of the Varens, 
or a wreath or two of foam at the bottom of the 
Nant d’Arpenaz, I began to enjoy it directly, be- 
cause then I had mind enough to put into the thing, 
and the enjoyment arose from the quantity of the 
imaginative energy I could bring to bear upon it; 
but when I looked at or thought of all together, 
moss, stones, Varens, Nant d’Arpenaz, and Mont 
Blanc, I had not mind enough to give to all, and 
none were of any value. The conclusion which would 
have been formed, upon this, by a German philoso- 
pher, would have been that the Mont Blanc was 
of no value; that he and his imagination only were 
of value; that the Mont Blanc, in fact, except so 



CHAP. X] OP THE USE OP PICTUEES 151 

far as he was able to look at it, eould not be con- 
sidered as having any existence. But the only con- 
clusion which occurred to me as reasonable under 
the circumstances (I have seen no ground for alter- 
ing it since) was, that I was an exceedingly small 
creature, much tired, and, at the moment, not a 
little stupid, for whom a blade of grass, or a wreath 
of foam, was quite food enough and to spare, and 
that if I tried to take any more, I should make 
myself ill. Whereupon, associating myself frater- 
nally with some ants, who were deeply interested in 
the conveyance of some small sticks over the road, 
and rather, as I think they generally are, in too 
great a hurry about it, I returned home iii a little 
while with great contentment, thinking how well 
it was ordered that, as Mont Blanc and his pine 
forests could not be everywhere, nor all the world 
come to see them, the human mind, on the whole, 
should enjoy itself most surely in an ant-like manner, 
and be happy and busy with the bits of stick and 
grains of crystal that fall in its way to be handled, 
in daily duty. 

§ 16. It follows evidently from the first of these 
characters of the imagination, its dislike of substance 
and presence, that a picture has in some measure 
even an advantage with us in not being real. The 
imagination rejoices in having something to do, 
springs up with all its willing power, flattered and 
happy; and ready with its fairest colours and most 
tender pencilling, to prove itself worthy of the trust, 
and exalt into sweet supremacy the shadow that 
has been confided to its fondness. And thus, so far 
from its being at all an object to the painter to make 
his work look real, he ought to dread such a con- 
summation as the loss of one of its most precious 
claims upon the heart. So far from striving to con- 
vince the beholder that what he sees is substance, 
his mind should be to what he paints as the fire to 
the body on the pile, burning away the ashes, leav- 
ing the unconquerable shade — an immortal dream. 
So certain is this, that the slightest local success in 



OF THE USE OF PICTUEES [part iv 

giving the deceptive appearance of reality — the imita- 
tion, for instance, of the texture of a bit of wood, 
with its grain in relief — ^will instantly destroy the 
charm of a whole picture ; the imagination feels itself 
insulted and' injured, and passes by with cold con- 
tempt; nay, however beautiful the whole scene may 
be, as of late in much of our highly wrought paint- 
ing for the stage, the mere fact of its being decep- 
tively real is enough to make us tire of it; we may 
be surprised and pleased for a moment, but the 
imagination will not on those terms be persuaded 
to give any of its help, and, in a quarter of an hour, 
we wish the scene would change. 

§ 17. * Well, but then, what becomes of all these 
long dogmatic chapters of yours about giving nothing 
but the truth, and as much truth as possible?’ 

The chapters are all quite right. ‘ Nothing but the 
Truth I say still. ‘ As much Truth as possible 
I say still. . But truth so presented, that it will need 
the help of the imagination to make it real. Be- 
tween the paintei and the beholder, each doing his 
proper part, the reality should be sustained; and 
after the beholding imagination has come forward and 
done its best, then, with its help and in the full 
action of it, the beholder should bo able to say, I 
feel as if I were at the real place, or seeing the real 
incident. But not without that help. 

§ 18. Farther, in consequence of that other charac- 
ter of the imagination, f atigiiableness , it is a great 
advantage to the picture that it need not present 
too much a^i once, and that what it does present 
may bo so chosen and ordered as not only to be 
more easily seized, but to give the imagination 
rest, and, as it were, places to lie down and stretch 
its limbs in; kindly vacancies, beguiling it back 
into action, with pleasant and cautious sequence of 
incident; all jarring thoughts being excluded, all 
vain redundance denied, and all just and sweet tran- 
sition permitted. 

And thus it is that, for the most part, imperfect 
sketches, engravings, outlines, rude sculptures, and 



CHAP, x] OF THE USE OF PICTURES 153 

other forms of abstraction, possess a charm which 
the most finished picture frequently wants. For not 
only does the finished picture excite the imagin- 
ation less, but, like nature itself, it taxes it more. 
None of it can be enjoyed till the imagination is 
brought to bear upon it; and the details of the com- 
pleted picture are so numerous, that it needs greater 
strength and willingness in the beholder to follow 
them all out; the redundance, perhaps, being not 
too great for the mind of a careful observer , but too 
great for a casual or careless observer. So that 
although the perfection of art will always consist 
in the utmost acceptable completion, yet, as every 
added idea will increase the difficulty of apprehen- 
sion, and every added touch advance the dangerous 
realism which makes the imagination languid, the 
difference between a noble and ignoble painter is in 
nothing more sharply defined than in this — ^that 
the first wishes to put into his work as much truth 
as possible, and yet to keep it looking wn-real; the 
second wishes to get through his work lazily, with 
as little truth as possible, and yet to make it look 
real; and, so far as they add colour to their abstract 
sketch, the first realizes for the sake of the colour, 
and the second colours for the sake of the real- 
ization 

§ 10. And then, lastly, it is another infinite 
advantage possessed by the picture, that in these 
various differences from reality it becomes the ex- 
pression of the power and intelligence of a compan- 
ionable human soul. In all this choice, aig-angement, 
penetrative sight, and kindly guidance, we recog- 
nize a supernatural operation, and perceive, not 
merely the landscape or incident as in a mirror, but, 
besides, the presence of what, after all, may per- 
haps, be the most wonderful piece of divine work in 
the whole matter — the great human spirit through 
which it is manifested to us. So that, although with 

1 Several other points connected with this subject have 
already been noticed in the last chapter of the /Stones of 
Venice^ § 21, &c. 



154 OF THE USE OF HOTURES [part iv 

respect to many important scenes, it might, as we 
saw above, be one of the most precious gifts that 
could be given us to see them with our own eyesy 
yet also in many things it is more desirable to be 
permitted to see them with the eyes of others; and 
although, to the small, conceited, and affected 
painter displaying his narrow knowledge and tiny 
desterities, our only word may be, ‘ Stand aside from 
between that nature and me ’ : yet to the great 
imaginative painter — greater a million times in every 
faculty of soul than we — our word may wisely be, 

‘ Come between this nature and me — this nature 
which is too great and too wonderful for me; temper 
it for me, interpret it to me; let me see with your 
eyes, and hear with your ears, and have help and 
strength from your great spirit.’ 

All the noblest pictures have this character. They 
are true or inspired ideals, seen in a moment to be 
ideal; that is to say, the result of all the highest 
powers of the imagination, engaged in the discovery 
and apprehension of the purest truths, and having 
so arranged them as best to show their preciousness 
and exalt their clearness. They are always orderly, 
always one, ruled by one great purpose throughout, 
in the fulfilment of which every atom of the detail is 
called to help, and would be missed if removed; 
this peculiar oneness being the result, not of obedi< 
ence to any teachable law, but of the magnificence 
of tone in the perfect mind, which accepts only what 
is good for its great purposes., rejects whatever is 
foreign or<. redundant, and instinctively and instan- 
taneously ranges whatever it accepts, in sublime 
subordination and helpful brotherhood. 

§ 20. Then, this being the greatest art, the lowest 
art is the mimicry of it — the subordination of nothing 
to nothing; the elaborate arrangement of sightless- 
ness and emptiness; the order which has no object; 
the unity which has no life, and the law which has 
no love; the light which has nothing to illumine, 
and shadow which has nothing to relieve i. 

1 * Though my pictures should have nothing else, they shall 



CHAP.X] OF THE USE OF PICTURES 155 

§ 21. And then, between these two, conies the 
wholesome, happy, and noble — ^though not noblest 
— art of simple transcript from nature; into which, 
so far as our modern Pre-Raphaelitism falls, it will 
indeed do sacred service in ridding us of the old 
fallacies and componencies, but cannot itself rise 
above the level of simple and happy usefulness. So 
far a^ it is to be great, it must add — and so far as 
it is great, has already added — ^the great imaginative 
element to all its faithfulness in transcript. And 
for this reason, I said in the close of my Edinburgh 
Lectures i that Pre-Raphaelitism, as long as it con- 
fined itself to the simple copying of nature, could not 
take the character of the highest class of art. But 
it has already, almost unconsciously, supplied the 
defect, and taken that character, in all its best 
results; and, so far as it ought, hereafter, it will 
assuredly do so, as soon as it is permitted to main- 
tain itself in any other position than that of stern 
antagonism to the composition-teachers around it. 
I say ‘ so far as it ought ’, because, as already noticed 
in that same place, we have enough, and to spare, 
of noble invent ful pictures : so many have we, that 
we let them moulder away on the walls and roofs 
of Italy without one regretful thought about them. 
But of simple transcripts from nature, till now we 
have had none; even Van Eyck and Albert Durer 
having been strongly filled with the spirit of grot- 
esque idealism; so that the Pre-Raphaelites have, to 
the letter, fulfilled Steele’s description of the author, 
who ‘ determined to write in an entirely new manner, 
and describe things exactly as they took place.* 

§ 22. We have now, I believe, in some sort an- 


have Chiaroscuro.’ CoiiSTABLE (in Leslie’s Life of him). It 
is singular to reflect what that fatal Chiaroscuro has done to 
art, 111 the full extent of its influence. It has been not only 
shadow, but shadow of Death ; passing over the face of the 
ancient art, as death itself might over a fair human counten- 
ance ; whispering, as it reduced it to the white projections and 
hghtless orbits of the skull, ‘Thy face shall have nothing else, 
but it shall have Chiaroscuro.’ 



156 OF THE USE OF PICTURES [part iv 

swered most of the questions which were suggested 
to us during our statement of the nature oi great 
art. I could recapitulate the answers; but perhaps 
the reader is already sufficiently wearied of the recur- 
rence of the terms ‘ Ideal ‘ Nature ‘ Imagin- 
ation ‘ Invention and will hardly care to see them 
again interchanged among each other, in the form- 
alities of a summary. What difficulties may yet 
occur to him will, I think, disappear as he either 
re-reads the passages which suggested them, or 
follows out the consideration of the subject for him- 
self : this very simple, but very precious, conclusion 
being continually remembered by him as the sum 
of ail; that greatness in art (as assuredly in all 
other things, but more distinctly in this than in 
most of them), is not a teachable nor gainable thing, 
but the expression of the mind of a God-made great 
man; that teach, or preach, or labour as you will, 
everlasting difference is set between one man’s capa- 
city and another’s; and that this God-given supre- 
macy is the priceless thing, always just as rare in 
the world at one time as another. What you can 
manufacture, or communicate, you can lower the 
price of, but this mental supremacy is incommuni- 
cable; you will never multiply its quantity, nor 
lower its price; and nearly the best tiling that men 
can generally do is to set themselves, not to the at- 
tainment, but the discovery of this; learning to know 
gold, when we see it, from iron-glance, and diamonds 
from flint-sand, being for most of us a more profit- 
able employment than trying to make diamonds out 
of our own charcoal. And for this God-made supre- 
macy, I generally have used, and shall continue to 
use, the word Inspiration, not carelessly nor lightly, 
but in all logical calmness and perfect reverence. 
We English have many false ideas about reverence : 
we should bo shocked, for instance, to see a market- 
woman come into church with a basket of eggs on 
her arm : we think it more reverent to lock her out 
till Sunday; and to surround the church with re- 
spectability of iron railings, and defend it with 



CHAP, x] OF THE USE OF PICTUEES 157 

pacing inhabitation of beadles. I believe this to be 
irreverence ; and that it is more truly reverent, when 
the market-woman, hot and hurried, at six in the 
morning, her head much confused with calculations 
of the probable price of eggs, can nevertheless get 
within church porch, and church aisle, and church 
chancel, lay the basket down on the very steps of 
the altar, and receive thereat so much of help and 
hope as may serve her for the day’s work. In like 
manner we are solemnly, but I think not wisely, 
shocked at any one who comes hurriedly into church, 
in any figurative way, with his basket on his arm; 
and perhaps, so long as we feel it so, it is better to 
keep the basket out. But, as for this one commodity 
of high mental supremacy, it cannot be kept out, 
for the very fountain of it is in the church wall, and 
there is no other right word for it but this of Inspir- 
ation; a word, indeed, often ridiculously perverted, 
and irreverently used of fledgling poets and pompous 
orators — no one being offended then, and yet cavilled 
at when quietly used of the spirit that is in a truly 
great man; cavilled at, chiefly, it seems to me, be- 
cause we expect to know inspiration by the look of 
it. Let a man have shaggy hair, dark eyes, a rolling 
voice, plenty of animal energy, and a facility of 
rhyming or sentencing, and — ^improvisatore or senti- 
mentalist — we call him ‘ inspired * willingly enough; 
but let him be a rough, quiet worker, not proclaim- 
ing himself melodiously in anywise, but familiar with 
us, unpretending, and letting all his littlenesses and 
feebleness(‘s be scon, unhindered — wearing an ill- 
cut coat withal, and, though he be such a man as 
is only sent upon the earth once in five hundred 
years, for some special human teaching, it is irrever- 
ent to call him ‘ inspired ’. But, be it irreverent or 
not, this word I must always use; and the rest of 
what work I have here before me, is simply to prove 
the truth of it, with respect to the one among these 
mighty spirits whom we have just lost; who divided 
his hearers, as many an inspired speaker has done 
before now, into two great sects — a large and a 



■158 NOVELTY OF LANDSCAPE [part iv 

narrow; these searching the Nature-scripture calmly, 
* whether those things were so and those standing 
haughtily on their Mars hill, asking, ‘ what will this 
babbler say?’ 


CHAPTER XI 

OF THE NOVELTY OF LANDSCAPE 

§ 1. Having now obtained, I trust, clear ideas, 
up to a certain point, of what is generally right and 
wrong in all art, both in conception and in workman- 
ship, we have to apply these laws of right to the 
particular branch of art which is the subject of our 
present inquiry, namely, landscape-painting. Re- 
specting which, after the various meditations into 
which we have been led on the high duties and ideals 
of art, it may not improbably occur to us first to 
ask — whether it be worth inquiring about at all. 

That question, perhaps the reader thinks, should 
have been asked and answered before I had written, 
or he read, two volumes and a half about it. So I 
had answered it, in my own mind; but it seems 
time now to give the grounds for this answer. If, 
indeed, the reader has never suspected that land- 
scape-painting was anything but good, right, and 
healthy work, I should be sorry to put any doubt 
of its being so into his mind; but if, as seems 
to me more likely, he, living in this busy and perhaps 
somewhat calamitous age, has some suspicion that 
landscape-fainting is but an idle and empty business, 
not worth all our long talk about it, then, perhaps, 
he will be pleased to have such suspicion done away, 
before troubling himself farther with these dis- 
quisitions. 

§ 2. I should rather be glad, than otherwise, that 
he had formed some suspicion on this matter. If 
he has at all admitted the truth of anything hitherto 
said ^respecting great art, and its choices of subject, 
it seems to me he ought, by this time, to be ques- 



oHAP.xiJ NOVELTY OF LANDSCAPE lB» 

tioning with himself whether road -side weeds, old 
cottages, broken stones, and such other materials, 
be worthy matters for grave men to busy themselves 
in the imitation of. And I should like him to probe 
this doubt to the deep of it, and bring all his inis- 
givings out to the broad, light, that we may see how 
we are to deal with them, or ascertain if indeed they 
are too well founded to be dealt with. 

§ 3. And to this end I would ask him now to 
imagine himself entering, for the first time in his 
life, the room of the 01(1 Water-Colour Society; and 
to suppose that he has entered it, not for the sake 
of a quiet examination of the paintings one by one, 
but in order to seize such ideas as it may generally 
suggest respecting the state and meaning of modern, 
as compared with elder, art. I suppose him, of 
course, that he may be capable of such a comparison, 
to be in some degree familiar with the different forms 
in which art has developed itself within the periods 
historically known to us; but never, till that moment, 
to have seen any completely modern work. So pre- 
pared, and so unprepared, he would, as his meas 
began to arrange themselves, be first struck by the 
number of paintings representing blue mountains, 
clear lakes, and ruined castles or cathedrals, and he 
would say to himself : ‘ There is something strange 
in the mind of these modern people I Nobody ever 
oared about blue mountains before, or tried to paint 
the broken stones of old walls.’ And the more he 
considered the subject, the more he would feel the 
peculiarity; and, as he thought over the arj of Greeks 
and Romans, he would still repeat, with increasing 
certainty of conviction : ‘ Mountains I I remember 
none. The Greeks did not seem, as artists, to know 
that such things were in the world, They carved, or 
variously represented, men, and horses, and beaSts, 
and biSfds, and all kinds of living creatures — ^yes, 
even down to cuttle-fish; and trees, in a sort of way; 
but not so much as the outline of a mountain; and 
as for lakes, they merely showed they knew' the 
difference between salt and fresh water by the fish 



im NOVELTY OF“ LANDSCAPE [part iv 

ikey put into each/ Then he wopld pass on to 
mediaBval art : and still he lyotild be obliged to re- 
peat : ‘ Mountains I I remember none. Some care- 
less and jagged arrangements of blue spires or spiked 
on the horizon, and, here and there, an attempt at 
representing an overhanging rock -With a hole through 
it; but merely in order to divide, the light behind 
some human figure. Lakes 1 No, nothing of the 
kind — only blue bays of sea put in to fill up the 
background when the painter could not think of any- 
thing else. Broken-down buildings I No; for the 
most part very complete and well-appointed build- 
ings, if any; and never buildings at all, but to give 
place or explanation to some circumstance of human 
conduct.’ And then he would look up again to the 
modern pictures, observing, with an increasing aston- 
ishment, that here the human interest had, in many 
oase^,. altogether disappeared. That* mountains, in- 
stead of ' beirm used only as a blue ground for the 
relief of the heads of saints, were themselves the 
exclusive subjects of reverent contemplation; that 
their ravines, and peaks, and forests, were all painted 
with an appearance of as much enthusiasm as had 
formerly been devoted to the dimples of beauty, or 
the frowns of (asceticism; and that all the living in- 
terest which was still supposed necessary to the 
scene, might be supplied by a traveller in a slouched 
hat, a beggar in a scarlet cloak, or, in default of 
these, even by a heron or a wild duck. 

§ 4. And if he could entirely divest himself of his 
own modern habits of thought, and regard the sub- 
jects in question with the feelings of a knight or 
monk of the middle ages, it might be a question 
whether those feelings would not rapidly verge to- 
wards contempt. ‘ What!’ he might perhaps mutter 
to himself, ‘ here are human beings spending the 
whole of their lives in making pictures of bits of 
stone and runlets of water, withered sticks and flying 
fogs, and actually not a picture of the go48 or the 
heroes I none of the saints or the martyrs f none of 
the angels and demons! none of councils or battles, 



CHAP. XI] NOVELTY OF LANDSCAPE 161 

or any other single thing wortiji the thought of a 
manl Trees and clouds indeed 1 as if I should not 
see as many trees as I cared to see, and more, in 
the first half of my day’s journey to-morrow, or as if 
it mattered to any man whether the sky were clear or 
cloudy, so long as his armour did not get too hot in 
the sun I’ 

§ 5. There can bo no question that this would 
have been somewhat the tone of thought with which 
either a Lacedsemonian, a soldier of Rome in her 
strength, or a knight of the thirteenth century, would 
have been apt to regard these particular forms of 
our present art. Nor can there be any question that, 
in many respects, their judpnent would have been 
just. It is true that the indignation of the Spartan 
or Roman would have been equally excited against 
any appearance of luxurious industry ; but the mediae- 
val knight would, to the full, have admitted the 
nobleness of art; only he would have had it em- 
ployed in decorating his church or his prayer-book, 
not in imitating moors and clouds. And the feelings 
of all the three would have agreed in this — that 
their main ground of offence must have been the 
want of seriousness and purpose in what they saw. 
They would all have admitted the nobleness of what- 
ever conduced to the honour of the gods, or the 
power of the nation ; but they would not have under- 
stood how the skill of human life could be wisely 
spent in that which did no honour either to Jupiter 
or to the Virgin; and which in no wise tended, ap- 
parently, either to the accumulation of viealth, the 
excitement of patriotism, or the advancement of 
morality. 

§ 6. And exactly so far forth their judgment would 
be just, as the landscape-painting could indeed be 
shown, for others as well as for them, to be art of 
this nugator}^ kind; and so far forth unjust, as that 
painting could be shown to depend upon, or culti- 
vate, certain sensibilities which neither the Greek 
nor mediaeval knight possessed, and which have re- 
sulted from some extraordinary change in human 

M. P., III. M 



m NOVELTY OF LANDSCAPE [part iv 

nature since their time. We have no right to assume, 
without very accurate examination of it, that this 
change has been an ennobling one. The simple fact, 
that we are, in some strange way, different from all 
the great races that have existed before us, cannot 
at once be received as the proof of our own great- 
ness; nor can it be granted, without any question, 
that we have a legitimate subject of complacency in 
being under the influence of feelings, with which 
neither Miltiades nor the Black Prince, neither 
Homer nor Dante, neither Socrates nor St Francis, 
could for an instant have sympathized. 

§ 7. Whether, however, this fact be one to excite 
our pride or not, it is assuredly one to excite our 
deepest interest. The fact itself is certain. For 
nearly six thousand years the energies of man have 
pursued certain beaten paths, manifesting some con- 
stancy of feeling throughout all that period, and in- 
volving some fellowship at heart, among the various 
nations who by turns succeeded or surpassed each 
other in the several aims of art or policy. So that, 
for these thousands of years, the whole human race 
might be to some extent described in general terms. 
Man was a creature separated from all others by his. 
instinctive sense of an Existence superior to his 
own, invariably manifesting this sense of the being 
of a God more strongly in proportion to his own 
perfectness of mind and body; and making enormous 
and self-denying efforts, in order to obtain some 
persuasion of the immediate presence or approval of 
the Divinity. So that, on the whole, the best things 
he did were done as in flie presence, or for the 
honour, of his gods; and, whether in statues, to 
help him to imagine them, or temples raised to 
their honour, or acts of self-sacrifice done in the 
hope of their love, he brought whatever was best 
and skilfullest in him into their service, and lived 
in a perpetual subjection to their unseen power. 
Also, he was always anxious to know something de- 
finite about them; and his chief books, songs, and 
pictures were filled with legends about them, or 



CHAP. XI] NOTELTY OF LANDSCAPE* ^ 163 

specially devoted to illustration of their lives and 
nature. 

§ 8. Next to these gods he was always anxious to 
know something about his human ancestors; fond of 
exalting the memory, and telling or painting the 
history of old rulers and benefactors; yet full of 
an enthusiastic confidence in himself, as having in 
many ways advanced beyond the best efforts of past 
time; and eager to record his own doings for future 
fame. He was a creature eminently warlike, placing 
his principal pride in dominion; eminently beautiful, 
and having great delight in his own beauty; setting 
forth this beauty by every species of invention in 
dress, and rendering his arms and accoutrements 
superbly decorative of his form. He took, however, 
very little interest in anything but what belonged to 
humanity; caring in no wise for the external world, 
except as it influenced his own destiny; honouring 
the lightning because it could strike him, the sea 
because it could drown him, the fountains because 
they gave him drink, and the grass because it yielded 
him seed ; but utterly incapable of feeling any special 
happiness in the love of such things, or any earnest 
emotion about them, considered as separate from 
man; therefore giving no time to the study of them; 
knowing little of herbs, except only which were 
hurtful, and which healing; of stones, only which 
would glitter brightest in a crown, or last the longest 
in a wall; of the wild beasts, which were best for 
food, and which the stoutest quarry for the hunter; 
thus spending only on the lower creatures and in- 
animate things his waste energy, his dullest thoughts, 
his most languid emotions, and reserving all his 
acuter intellect for researches into his own nature 
and that of the gods; all his strength of will for 
the acquirement of political or moral power; all his 
sense of beauty for things immediately connected 
with his own person and life; and all his deep affec- 
tions for domestic or divine companionship. 

Such, in broad light and brief terms, was man for 
five thousand years. Such he is no longer. Let us 



NOVELTY OF LANDSCAPE [part iv 

consider what he is now, comparing the descriptions 
clause by clause. 

§ 9. I. He was invariably sensible of the existence 
of gods, and went about all his speculations or works 
holding this as an acknowledged fact, making his 
best efforts in their service. Now he is capable of 
Qoing through life with hardly any positive idea on 
this subject — doubting, fearing, suspecting, analys- 
ing — doing everything, in fact, hut believing; hardly 
ever getting quite up to that point which hitherto 
was wont to be the starting point for all generations. 
And human work has accordingly hardly any refer- 
ence to spiritual beings, but is done either from a 
patriotic or personal interest — either to benefit man- 
kind, or reach some selfish end, not (I speak of 
human work in the broad sense) to please the gods. 

II. He was a beautiful creature, setting forth this 
beauty by all means in his power, and depending 
upon it for much of his authority over his fellows. 
So that the ruddy cheek of David, and the ivory skin 
of Atrides, and the towering presence of Saul, and 
the blue eyes of Coeur de Lion, were among chief 
reasons why they should be kings; and it was one 
of the aims of all education, and of all dress, to make 
the presence of the human form stately and lovely. 
Now it has become the task of grave philosophy 
partly to depreciate or conceal this bodily beauty; 
and even by those who esteem it in their hearts, it 
is not made one of the great ends of education : man 
has become, upon the whole, an ugly animal, and is 
not ashamed of his ugliness. 

III. He was eminently warlike. He is now grad- 
ually becoming more and more ashamed of all the 
arts and aims of battle. So that the desire of 
dominion which was once frankly confessed or 
boasted of as a heroic passion, is now sternly repro- 
bated or cunningly disclaimed. 

IV. He used to take no interest in anything but 
what immediately concerned himself. Now, he has 
deep interest in the abstract natures of things, in- 
quires as eagerly into the laws which regulate the 



CHAP. XI] NOVELTY OF LANDSCAPE ' 165 

economy of the material world, as into those of his 
own being, and manifests a passionate admiration 
of inanimate objects, closely resembling, in its eleva- 
tion and tenderness, the affection which he bears 
to those living souls with which he is brought into 
the nearest fellowship. 

§ 10. It is this last change only which is to be 
the subject of our present inquir^^; but it cannot 
be doubted that it is closely connected with ail the 
others, and that we can only thoroughly understand 
its nature by considering it in this connection. For, 
regarded by itself, we might, perhaps, too rashly 
assume it to be a natural consequence of the pro- 
gress of the race. There appears to be a diminution 
of selfishness in it, and a more extended and heartfelt 
desire of understanding the manner of God ’s working ; 
and this the more, because one of the permanent 
characters of this change is a greater accuracy in the 
statement of external facts. When the eyes of men 
were fixed first upon themselves, and upon nature 
solely and secondarily as bearing upon their inter- 
ests, it was of less consequence to them what the 
ultimate laws of nature were, than what their im- 
mediate effects were upon human beings. Hence 
they could rest satisfied with phenomena instead of 
principles, and accepted without scrutiny every fable 
which seemed sufficiently or gracefully to account 
for those phenomena. But so far as the eyes of men 
are now withdrawn from themselves, and turned 
upon the inanimate things about them, the results 
cease to be of importance, and the kws become 
essential. 

§ 11. In these respects, it might easily appear to 
us that this change was assuredly one of steady and 
natural advance. But when we contemplate the 
others above noted, of which it is clearly one of the 
branches or consequences, we may suspect ourselves 
of over-rashness in our self-congratulation, and admit 
the necessity of a scrupulous analysis both of the 
feeling itself and of its tendencies. 

Of course a complete analysis, or anything like it. 



THE PATHETIC FALLACY [paet iv 

would involve a treatise on the whole history of 
the world. I shall merely endeavour to note some 
of the leading and more interesting circumstances 
bearing on the subject, and to show sufficient 
practical ground for the conclusion, that landscape- 
painting is indeed a noble and useful art, though 
<^ne not long known by man. I shall therefore ex- 
amine, as best I can, the effect of landscape, 1st, on 
the Classical mind; 2ndly, on the Medissval mind; 
and lastly, on the Modern mind. But there is one 
point of some interest respecting the effect of it on 
any mind, which must be settled first; and this I 
will endeavour to do in the next chapter. 


CHAPTER XII 

OF THE PATHETIC FALLACY 

§ 1. German dulnece, and English affectation, 
have of late much multiplied among us the use of 
two of the most objectionable words that were ever 
coined by the troublesomeness of metaphysicians, — 
namely, ‘ Objective ’ and ‘ Subjective 

No words can bo more exquisitely, and in all points, 
useless; and I merely speak of them that I may, 
at once and for ever, get them out of my way, and 
out of my reader’s. But to get that done, they must 
be explained. 

The word ‘ Blue say certain philosophers, means 
the sensation of colour which the human eye receives 
in looking at the open sky, 6r at a bell gentian. 

Now, say they farther, as this sensation can only 
be felt when the eye is turned to the object, and 
as, therefore, no such sensation is produced by the 
object when nobody looks at it, therefore the thing, 
when it is not looked at, is not blue; and thus (say 
they) there are many qualities of things which depend 
as much on something else as on themselves. To 
be sweet, a thing must have a taster; it is only 
sweet while it is being tasted, and if the tongue 



CHAP. XII] THE PATHETIC FALLACY ‘ 167 

had not the capacity of taste, then the sugar would 
not have the quality of sweetness. 

And then they agree that the qualities of things 
which thus depend upon our perception of them, 
and upon cur human nature as affected by them, 
shall be called Subjective; and the qualities of 
things which they always have, irrespective of any 
other nature, as roundness or squareness, shall be 
called Objective. 

From these ingenious views the step is very easy 
to a farther opinion, that it does not much matter 
what things are in themselves, but only what they 
are to us; and that the only real truth of them 
is their appearance to, or effect upon, us. From 
which position, with a hearty desire for mystification, 
and much egotism, selfishness, shallowness, and im- 
pertinence, a philosopher may easily go so far as to 
believe, and say, that everything in the world de- 
pends upon his seeing or thinking of it, and that 
nothing, therefore, exists, but what he sees or thinks 
of. 

§ 2. Now, to get rid of ail these ambiguities and 
troublesome words at once, be it observed that the 
word ‘ Blue ’ does not mean the sensation caused 
by a gentian on the human eye; but it means the 
'power of producing that sensation; and this power 
is always there, in the thing, whether we are there 
to experience it or not, and would remain there 
though there were not left a man on the face of the 
earth. Precisely in the same way gunpowder has a 
power of exploding. It will not explodg if you put 
no match to it. But it has always the power of so 
exploding, and is therefore called an explosive com- 
pound, which it very positively and assuredly is, 
whatever philosophy may say to the contrary. 

In like manner, a gentian does not produce the 
sensation of blueness if you don’t look at it. But 
it has .always the power of doing so; its particles 
being everlastingly so arranged by its Maker. And, 
therefore, the gentian and the sky are always verily 
blue, whatever philosophy may say to the contrary; 



THE PATHETIC FALLXcY [paet iv 

mid if you do not see them blu6 when you look at 
theni) it is not their fault but yours 

§ 3. Hence I would say to these philosophers : If, 
instead of using the sonorous phrase, ‘ It is objec- 
tively so *, you will use the plain old phrase, ‘ It 
is so and if instead of the sonorous phrase, ‘ It 
is subjectively so ’, you will say, in plain old Eng- 
lish, ‘ It does so ’, or ‘It seems so to me you 
will, on the whole, be more intelligible to your fellow- 
creatures : and besides, if you find that a thing which 
generally ‘ does so ’ to other people (as a gentian 
looks blue to most men), does not so to you, on any 
particular occasion, you will not fall into the imper- 
tinence of saying, that the thing is not so, or did 
not so, but you will say simply (what you will be 
all the better for speedily finding out), that some- 
thing is the matter with you. If you find that you 
cannot explode the gunpowder, you will not declare 
that all gunpowder is subjective, and all explosion 
imaginary, but you will simply suspect and declare 
yourself to be an ill-made match. Which, on the 
whole, though there may be a distant chance of a 
mistake about it, is, nevertheless, the wisest conclu- 
sion you can come to until farther experiment 2 , 

1 It is quite true, that in all qualities involving sensation, 
there may be a doubt whether different people receive the same 
sensation from the same thing (compare Part II, Sec. I, Chap. V, 
§ 6 .) ; but, though this makes such facts not distinctly explic- 
able, it does not alter the facts themselves. I derive a certain 
sensation, which I call sweetness, from sugar. That is a fact. 
Another pert on feels a sensation, which he also calls sweetness, 
from sugar. *That is also a fact. The sugar’s power to produce 
these two sensations, which we suppose to be, and which are, in 
all probability, very nearly the same in both of us, and, on the 
whole, in the human race, is its sweetness. 

2 In fact (for I may as well, for once, meet our German 
friends in their own style), all that has been subjected to us on 
the subject seems object to this great objection ; that the sub- 
jection of all things (subject to no exceptions) to senses which 
are, in us, both subject and abject, and objects of perpetual 
contempt, cannot but make it our ultimate object to subject 
ourselves to the senses, and to remove whatever objections 
existed to such subjection. So that, finally, that which is the 



CHAP.xn] TSE PATHETIC FALLACY 169 

§ 4. Now, therefore, putting these tiresome and 
absurd words quite out of our way, we may go on 
at our ease to examine the point in question, namely, 
the difference between the ordinary, proper, and true 
appearances of things to us; and the extraordinary, 
or false appearances, when we are under the in- 
fluence of emotion, or contemplative fancy false 
appearances, I say, as being entirely unconnected with 
any real power or character in the object, and only 
imputed to it by us. 

For instance 

The spendthrift crocus, bursting through the mould 
Naked and shivering, with his cup of gold 2. 

This is very beautiful, and yet very untrue. The 
crocus is not a spendthrift, but a hardy plant; its 
yellow is not gold, but saffron. How is it that we 
enjoy so much the having it put into our heads that 
it is anything else than a plain crocus? 

It is an important question. For, throughout our 
past reasonings about art, we have always found that 
nothing could be good or useful, or ultimately plea- 


subject of examination or object of attention, uniting thus in 
itself the characters of subness and obness (so that, that which 
has no oVmess in it should be called sub-subjective, or a 
sub-subject, and that which has no subness in it should be 
called upper or ober-objective, or an ob-object) ; and we 
also, who suppose ourselves the objects of every arrange- 
ment, and are certainly the subjects of every sensual 
impression, thus uniting in ourselves, iu an obverse or 
adverse manner, the characters of obness and subness, must 
both become metaphysically dejected or rejected, nothing 
remaining in us objective, but subjectivity, and the very objec- 
tivity of the object being lost in the abyss of this subjectivity 
of the Human. 

There is, however, some meaning in the above sentence, if 
the reader cares to make it out ; but in a pure German sentence 
of the highest style there is often none whatever. See Appendix 
II, ‘German Philosophy.' 

1 Contemplative, in the sense explained in Part III, Sec. II, 
Chap. IV. 

2 Holmes (Oliver Wendell), quoted by Miss Mitford in her 
Recollections of a Literary Life. 



THE PATHETIC FALLACY [part iv 

surable, whicli was untrue. But here is something 
pleasurable in written poetry which is nevertheless 
untrue. And what is more, if we think over our 
favourite poetry, we shall find it full of this kind of 
fallacy, and that we like it all the more for being so. 

§ 5. It will appear also, on consideration of the 
matter, that this fallacy is of two principal kinds. 
Either, as in this case of the crocus, it is the fallacy 
of wilful fancy, which involves no real expectation 
that it will be believed; or else it is a fallacy caused 
by an excited state of the feelings, making us, for 
the time, more or less irrational. Of the cheating 
of the fancy we shall have to speak presently; but, 
in this chapter, I want to examine the nature of the 
other error, that which the mind admits when afiected 
strongly by emotion. Thus, for instance, in Alton 
Loc/ce, 

They rowed her in across the rolling foam — 

The cruel, crawling foam. 

The foam is not cruel, neither does it crawl. The 
state of mind which attributes to it these characters 
of a living creature is one in which the reason is 
unhinged by grief. All violent feelings have the 
same effect. They produce in us a falseness in all 
our impressions of external things, which I would 
generally characterize as the ‘ Pathetic fallacy ’. 

§ 6. Now we are in the habit of considering this 
fallacy as eminently a character of poetical descrip- 
tion, and the temper of mind in which we allow it, 
as one eminently poetical, because passionate. But, 
I believe, if we look well iifto the matter, that we 
shall find the greatest poets do not often admit this 
kind of falseness — that it is only the second order of 
poets who much delight in it 

1 I admit two orders of poets, but no third ; and by these 
two orders I mean the Creative (Shakspeare, Homer, Dante), 
and Reflective or Perceptive (Wordsworth, Keats, Tennyson). 
But both of these must be Jlrst-rsite in their range, though 
their range is different ; and with poetry second-rate in quality 
no one ought to be allowed to trouble mankind. There is 
quite enough of the best — much more than we can ever read 



cHAP.xn] Tfe PATHETIC FALLACY l7l 

Thus, when Dante describes the spirits falling from 
the bank of Acheron ‘ as dead leaves flutter from a 
bough *, he gives the most perfect image possible of 
their utter lightness, feebleness, passiveness, and 
scattering agony of despair, without, however, for 
an instant losing his own clear perception that these 
are souls, and those are leaves; he makes no con- 
fusion of one with the other. But when Coleridge 
speaks of 

The one red leaf, the last of its clan, 

That dances as often as dance it can, 

he has a morbid, that is to say, a so far false, idea 
about the leaf : he fancies a life in it, and will, 
which there are not; confuses its powerlessness with 
choice, its fading death with merriment, and the 
wind that shakes it with music. Here, however, 
there is some beauty, even in the morbid passage; 
but take an instance in Homer and Pope. Without 
the knowledge of Ulysses, Elpenor, his youngest 


or enjoy in the length of a life ; and it is a literal wrong or sin 
in any person to encumber us with inferior work. I have no 
patience with apologies made by young pseudo-poets, ‘that 
they believe there is some good in what they have written : 
that they hope to do better in time &c. Soyrie good ! If 
there is not all good, there is no good. If they ever hope to 
do better, why do they trouble us now ? Let them rather 
courageously bum all they have done, and wait for the better 
days. There are few men, ordinarily educated, who in 
moments of strong feeling could not strike out a poetical 
thought, and afterwards polish it so as to be presentable. 
But men of sense know better than so to was^e their time; 
and those who sincerely love poetry, know the touch of the 
master’s hand on the chords too well to fumble among them 
after him. Nay, more than this ; all inferior poetry is an in- 
jury to the good, inasmuch as it takes away the freshness of 
rhymes, blunders upon and gives a wretched commonalty to 
good thoughts ; and, in general, adds to the weight of human 
weariness in a most woful and culpable manner. There are 
few thoughts likely to come across ordinary men, which have 
not already been expressed by greater men in the best possible 
way; and it is a wiser, more generous, more noble thing to 
remember and point out the perfect words, than to invent 
poorer ones, wherewith to encumber temporarily the world. 



THE PATHETIC FALLACY [paet iv 

follower, has fallen from an upper chamber in the 
Circean palace, and has been left dead, unmissed 
by his leader, or companions, in the haste of their 
departure. They cross the sea to the Cimmerian 
land; and Ulysses summons the shades from Tar- 
tarus. The first which appears is that of the lost 
Elpenor, Ulysses, amazed, and in exactly the spirit 
of bitter and terrified lightness which is seen in 
Hamlet 1, addresses the spirit with the simple, 
startled words : 

Elpenor ! How earnest thou under the shadowy darkness ? 
Hast thou come faster on foot than I in iny black ship ? 

Which Pope renders thus : 

O, say, what angry power Elpenor led 
To glide in shades, and wander with the dead ? 

How could thy soul, by realms and seas disjoined, 
Outfly the nimble sail, and leave the lagging wind? 

I sincerely hope the reader finds no pleasure here, 
either in the nimbleness of the sail, or the laziness 
of the wind 1 And yet how is it that these conceits 
are so painful now, when they have been pleasant to 
us in the other instances? 

§ 7. For a very simple reason. They are not a 
'pathetic fallacy at all, for they are put into the 
mouth of the wrong passion — a passion which never 
could possibly have spoken thorn — agonized curiosity. 
Ulysses wants to know the facts of the matter; and 
the very last thing his mind could do at the moment 
would be to pause, or suggest in any wise what was 
not a fact.' The delay in #he first three lines, and 
conceit in the last, jar upon us instantly, like the 
most frightful discord in music. No poet of true 
imaginative power could possibly have written the 
passage 2. 

1 Well said, old mole ! can’st work i’ the groimd so fast ? 

2 It is worth while comparing the way a similar question is 
put by the exquisite sincerity of Keats : 

He wept, and his bright tears 
Went trickling down the golden bow he held. 

Thus, with h^f-shut, suffused eyes, he stood ; 



CHAP, xii] THE PATHETIC FALLACI iV? 

Therefore, we see that the spirit of truth must 
guide us in some sort, even in our enjoyment of 
fallacy. Coleridge’s fallacy has no discord in it, but 
Pope’s has set our teeth on edge. Without farther 
questioning, I .will endeavour to state the main bear- 
ings of this matter. 

§ 8. The temperament which admits the pathetic 
fallacy, is, as I said above, that of a mind and body 
in some sort too weak to deal fuljy with what is 
before them or upon them; borne away, or over- 
clouded, or over-dazzled by emotion; and it is a 
more or less noble state, according to the force of 
the emotion which has induced it. For it is no 
credit to a man that he is not morbid or inaccurate 
in his perceptions, when he has no strength of feel- 
ing to warp them; and it is in general a sign of 
higher capacity and stand in the ranks of being, that 
the emotions should be strong enough to vanquish, 
partly, the intellect, and make it believe what they 
choose. But it is still a grander condition when the 
intellect also rises, till it is strong enough to assert 
its rule against, or together with, the utmost efforts 
of the passions; and the whole man stands in an 
iron glow, white hot, perhaps, but still strong, and 
in no wise evaporating; even if he melts, losing 
none of his weight. 

So, then, we have the three ranks : the man who 
perceives rightly, because he does not feel, and to 
whom the primrose is very accurately the primrose, 
because he does not love it. Then, secondly, the 
man who perceives wrongly, because he feels, and 
to whom the primrose is anything else tfian a prim- 
rose : a star, or a sun, or a fairy’s shield, or a for- 
saken maiden. And then, lastly, there is the man 
who perceives rightly in spite of his feelings, and to 


While from beneath some cumb’roiis boughs hard by, 
With solemn step, an awful goddess came. 

And there was purport in her looks for him, 

Which he with eager guess began to read : 

Perplexed the while, melodiously he said, 

‘ Hov) cam'st thou over the unfooted sea ? ’ 



iu THE PATHETIC FALLACY [part iv 

whom the primrose is for ever nothing else .than 
itself — a little flower, apprehended in the very plain 
and leafy fact of it, whatever and how many soever 
the associations and passions may be, that crowd 
around it. And, in general, these three classes may 
be rated in comparative order, as the men who are 
not poets at all, and the poets of the second order, 
and the poets of the first; only however great a 
man may be, there are always some subjects which 
ought to throw him ofi his balance; some, by which 
his poor human capacity of thought should be con- 
quered, and brought into the inaccurate and vague 
state of perception, so that the language of the 
highest inspiration becomes broken, obscure, and wild 
in metaphor, resembling that of the weaker man, 
overborne by weaker things. 

§ 9. And thus, in full, there are four classes : the 
men who feel nothing, and therefore see truly; the 
men who feel strongly, think weakly, and see un- 
truly (second order of poets); the men wl^o feel 
strongly, think strongly, and see truly (first order of 
poets); and the men who, strong as human crea- 
tures can be, are yet submitted to influences stronger 
than they, and see in a sort untruly, because what 
they see is inconceivably above them. This last is 
the usual condition of prophetic inspiration. 

§ 10. I separate these classes, in order that their 
character may be clearly understood; but of course 
they are united each to the other by imperceptible 
transitions, and the same mind, according to the 
influences to which it is subjected, passes at diflerent 
times into ihe various stated. Still, the difference 
between the great and less man is, on the whole, 
chiefly in this point of alterahility. That is to say, 
the one knows too much, and perceives and feels 
too much of the past and future, and of all things 
beside and around that which immediately affects 
him, to be in any wise shaken by it. His mind is 
made up ; his thoughts have an accustomed current ; 
his ways are stedfast; it is not this or that new 
sight which will at once unbalance him. He is 



CHAP.XH] THE PATHETIC fALLACY ^ i75 

tender to impression at the surface, like airock with 
deep moss upon it; but there is too much mass of 
him to be moved. The smaller man, with the same 
degree of sensibility, is at once carried off his feet; 
he wants to do something he did not want to do 
before; he views all the universe in a new light 
through his tears; he is gay or enthusiastic, melan- 
choly or passionate, as things come and go to him. 
Therefore the high creative poet might even be 
thought, to a great extent, impassive (as shallow 
people think Dante stern), receiving indeed all feel- 
ings to the full, but having a great centre of reflec- 
tion and knowledge in which he stands serene, and 
watches the feeling, as it were, from far off. 

Dante, in his most intense moods, has entire com- 
mand of himself, and can look around calmly, at all 
moments, for the image or the word that will best 
tell what he sees to the upper or lower world. But 
Keats and Tennyson, and the poets of the second 
order, are generally themselves subdued by the feel- 
ings under which they write, or, at least, write as 
choosing to be so, and therefore admit certain expres- 
sions and modes of thought which are in some sort 
diseased or false. 

§ 11. Kow so long as we see that the feeling is 
true, we pardon, or are even pleased by, the con- 
fessed fallacy of sight which it induces : we are 
pleased, for instance, with those lines of Kingsley’s, 
above quoted, not because they fallaciously describe 
foam, but because they faithfully describe sorrow. 
But the moment the mind of the speaker becomes 
cold, that moment every such expression becomes un- 
true, as being for ever untrue in the external facts. 
And there is no greater baseness in literature than 
the habit of using these metaphorical expressions 
in cool blood. An inspired writer, in full impetu- 
osity of passion, may speak wisely and truly of 
‘ raging waves of the sea, foaming out their own 
shame but it is only the basest writer who cannot 
speak of the sea without talking of ‘ raging waves 
‘ remorseless floods % ‘ ravenous billows ’, (&c. ; and 



Itft THE PATHETIC FALLACY [part iv 

it is one of the signs of the highest power in a writer 
to check all such habits of thought, and to keep his 
eyes fixed firmly on the pure fact, out of which if 
any feeling comes to him or his reader, he knows it 
must be a true one. 

To keep to the waves, I forget who it is who 
represents a man in despair, desiring that his body 
may be cast into the sea, 

Jlliose changing mound^ and foam that j^assed away. 

Might mock the eye that questioned where I lay . 

Observe, there is not hero a single false, or even 
overcharged, expression. ‘ Mound * of the sea wave 
is perfectly simple and true; ‘ changing ’ is as 
familiar as may be; ‘ foam that passed away ’, strictly 
literal; and the whole line descriptive of the reality 
with a degree of accuracy which I know not any 
other verse, in the range of poetry, that altogether 
equals. For most people have not a distinct idea 
of the clumsiness and massiveness of a large wave. 
The word ‘ wave ’ is used too generally of ripples and 
breakers, and bendings in light drapery or grass : 
it does not by itself convey a perfect image. But 
the word ‘ mound ’ is heavy, large, dark, definite; 
there is no mistaking the kind of wave meant, nor 
missing the sight of it. Then the term ‘ changing ’ 
has a peculiar force also. Most people think of 
waves as rising and falling. But if they look at the 
sea carefully, they will perceive that the waves do 
not rise and fall. They change. Change both place 
and form, but they do not fajl; one wave goes on, 
and on, and" still on; now lower, now higher, now 
tossing its mane like a horse, now building itself 
together like a wall, now shaking, now steady, but 
still the same wave, till at last it seems struck by 
something, and changes, one knows not how — be- 
comes another wave. 

The close of the line insists on tliis image, and 
paints it still more perfectly — ‘ foam that passed 
away ’. Not merely melting, disappearing, but pass- 
ing on, out of sight, on the career of the wave. 



CHAP. XII] THE PATHETIC FALLACY 177 

Then, having put the absolute ocean fact as far as 
he may before our eyes, the poet leaves us to feel 
about it as we may, and to trace for ourselves the 
opposite fact, — the image of the green mounds that 
do not change, and the white and written stones 
that do not pass away ; and thence to follow out also 
the associated images of the calm life with the quiet 
grave, and the despairing life with the fading foam : 

‘ Let no man move his bones/ 

* As for Samaria, her king is cut off like the foam upon the 
water.’ 

But nothing of this is actually told or pointed out, 
and the expressions, as they stand, are perfectly 
severe and accurate, utterly uninfluenced by the 
firmly governed emotion of the writer. Even the 
word ‘ mock ’ is hardly an exception, as it may stand 
merely for ‘ deceive ’ or ‘ defeat ’, without implying 
any impersonation of the waves. 

§ 12. It may be well, perhaps, to give one or two 
more instances to show the peculiar dignity pos- 
sessed by all passages which thus limit their expres- 
sion to the pure fact, and leave the hearer to gather 
what he can from it. Here is a notable one from 
the Iliad. Helen, looking from the Scaean gate of 
Troy over the Grecian host, and telling Priam the 
names of its captains, says at last : 

I see all the other dark-eyed Greeks ; but two I cannot see, 
— Castor and Pollux — whom one mother bore with me. Have 
they not followed from fair Lacedaemon, or have they indeed 
come in their sea-wandering ships, but now v/ill not enter 
into the battle of men, fearing the shame and the scorn that 
is in Me ? 


Then Homer : 

So she spoke. But them, already, the life-giving earth 
possessed, there in Laceda3mon, in the dear fatherland. 

Note, here, the high poetical truth carried to the 
extreme. The poet has to speak of the earth in 
sadness, but he will not let that sadness affect or 

M. P., III. N 



THE PATHETIC FALLACY [part iv 

^ange his thoughts of it. No; though Cantor and 
Pollux be dead, yet the earth is our mother still, 
fruitful, life-giving. These are the facts of the thing. 
I see nothing else than these. Make what you will 
of them. 

§ 13. Take another very notable instance from 
Casimir de la Vigne’s terrible ballad. La Toilette de 
Constance, I must quote a few lines out of it here 
and there, to enable the reader who has not the 
book by him, to understand its close : 

Vite, Anna, vite ; au miroir 
Plus vite, Anna. Ij’heure s’avance, 

Et je vais au bal ce soir 

Chez I’ambassadeur de France 

Y pensez vous, ils sent fan^s, ces noeuds, 

Miiont d’hier, mon Dieu, com me tout passe ! 

Que du rdseau qui retient mes cheveux 
Les glands d’azur retombent avec gr^. 

Plus haut ! Plus bas ! Vous ne comprenez rien ! 

Que sur mon front oe saphir ^tincelle : 

Vous me piquez, mal-adroite. Ah, e’est bien, 

Bien, — chere Anna ! Je t’aime, je suis belle, 

Celui qu’eu vain je voudrais oublier 
(Anna, ma robe) il y sera, j’espere. 

(Ah, fi, profane, est-ce lA mon collier ? 

Quoi ! ces grains d*or b^nits par le Saint-P^re !) 

II y sera ; Dieu, s’il pressait ma main, 

En y pensant, k peine je respire : 

P^re Anselmo doit m ’entendre demain, 

Comment ferai je, Anna, pour tout lui dire ? 

Vile, un coup d’oeil au miroir, 

Le dernier. J’ai I’^surance 

Qu’on va m’adorer ce soir 
Chez I’ambassadeur de France. 

Pr^s du foyer, Constance s’admirait. 

Dieu ! sur sa robe il vole une 6tiucelle ! 

Au feu. Courez ; Quand I’espoir I’enivrait 
Tout perdre ainsi ! Quoi ! Mourir,— et si belle ! 
L’horrible feu ronge avec volupt6 
Ses bras, son sein, et I’entoure, et s’^leve, 

Et sans pitie d^vore sa beautd, 

Ses dixhuit ans, hdlas, et son doux r6ve 



cHAP.xii] THE PATHETIC FALLACY 179^ 

Adieu, bal, plaisir, amour ! 

On disait, Pauvre Constance ! 

Et on dansait, jusqu’au jour, 

Obez I’ambassadeur de France. 

Yes, that is the fact of it. Right or wrong, the- 
poet does not say. What you may think about it^ 
he does not know. He has nothing to do with that.- 
There lie the ashes of the dead girl in her chamber. 
There they danced, till the morning, at the Ambas- 
sador’s of France. Make what you will of it. 

If the reader will look through the ballad, of 
which I have quoted only about the third part, he 
will find that there is not, from beginning to end of 
it, a single poetical (so called) expression, except in 
one stanza. The girl speaks as simple prose as may 
be; there is not a word she would not have actually 
used as she w'as dressing. The poet stands by, im- 
passive as a statue, recording her words just as they 
come. At last the doom seizes her, and in the very 
presence of death, for an instant, his own emotions 
conquer him. He records no longer the facts only, 
but the facts as they seem to him. The fire gnaws 
with voluptuousness — without pity. It is soon past. 
The fate is fixed for ever; and he retires into his 
pale and crystalline atmosphere of truth. He closes 
all with the calm veracity. 

They said, ‘ Poor Constance ! ’ 

§ 14. Now in this there is the exact type of the con- 
summate poetical temperament. For, be it clearly 
and constantly remembered, that the greatness of a 
poet depends upon the two faculties, acuteness of 
feeling, and command of it. A poet is great, first in 
proportion to the strength of his passion, and then, 
that strength being granted, in proportion to his 
government of it; there being, however, always a 
point beyond which it would be inhuman and mon- 
strous if he pushed this government, and, therefore,- 
a point at which all feverish and wild fancy becomes 
just and true. Thus the destruction of the kingdom 
of Assyria cannot be contemplated firmly by a prophet: 



THE PATHETIC FALLACY [part iv 

of Israel. The fact is too great, too wonderful. It 
overthrows him, dashes him into a confused element 
of dreams. All the world is, to his stunned thought, 
full of strange voices. ‘ Yea, the fir-trees rejoice at 
thee, and the cedars of Lebanon, saying, “ Since thou 
art gone down to the grave, no teller is come up 
against us So, still more, the thought of the 
presence of Deity cannot be borne without this great 
astonishment. ‘ The mountains and the hills shall 
break forth before you into singing, and all the trees 
of the field shall clap their hands.’ 

§ 15. But by how much this feeling is noble when 
it is justified by the strength of its cause, by so 
much it is ignoble when there is not cause enough 
for it; and beyond all other ignobleness is the mere 
affectatiopi of it, in hardness of heart. Simply bad 
writing 'may almost always, as above noticed, be 
known by its adoption of these fanciful metaphorical 
expressions, as a sort of current coin; yet there is 
even a worse, at least a more harmful, condition of 
writing than this, in which such expressions are 
not ignorantly and feelinglessly caught up, but, by 
some master, skilful in handling, yet insincere, 
deliberately wrought out with chill and studied fancy ; 
as if we should try to make an old lava stream look 
red-hot again, by covering it with dead leaves, or 
white-hot, with hoar-frost. 

When Young is lost in veneration, as he dwells on 
the character of a truly good and holy man, he 
permits himself for a moment to be overborne by 
the feeling *80 far as to excltfim : 

Where shall I find him ? angels, tell me where. 

You know him ; he is near you ; point him out. 

Shall I see glories beaming from his brow, 

Or trace his footsteps by the rising flowers ? 

This emotion has a worthy cause, and is thus true 
and right. But now hear the cold-hearted Pope say 
to a shepherd girl : 

Where’er you walk, cool gales shall fan the glade ; 

Trees, where you sit, shall crowd into a shade ; 

Your praise the birds shall chant in every grove, 

And winds shall waft it to the powers above. 



OHAP.xn] The pathetic - fallacy ■ 181' 

But would you sing, and rival Orpheus’ strain, 

The wondering forests soon should dance again ; 

The moving mountains hear the powerful call, 

And headlong streams hang, listening, to their fall. 

This is not, nor could it for a moment be mis- 
taken for, the language of passion. It is simple 
falsehood, uttered by hypocrisy; definite absurdity, 
rooted in affectation, and coldly asserted in the 
teeth of nature and fact. Passion will indeed go 
far in deceiving itself; but it must be a strong pas- 
sion, not the simple wish of a lover to tempt his 
mistress to sing. Compare a very closely parallel 
passage in Wordsworth, in which the lover has lost 
his mistress : 

Three yearis had Barbara in her grave been laid. 

When thus his moan he made : 

‘ Oh, move, thou cottage, from behind yon oak, 

Or let the ancient tree uprooted lie. 

That in some other way yon smoke 
May mount into the sky. 

If still behind yon pine-tree’s rugged bough, 

Headlong the waterfall must come. 

Oh, let it, then, be dumb — 

Be anything, sweet stream, but that which thou art now.’ 

Here is a cottage to be moved, if not a mountain, 
and a waterfall to be silent, if it is not to hang listen- 
ing ; but with what different relation to the mind 
that contemplates them I Here, in the extremity 
of its agony, tho soul cries out wildly for relief, 
which at the same moment it partly knows to be 
impossible, but partly believes possible in a vague 
impression that a miracle might be wrought to give 
relief even to a less sore distress — that nature is 
kind, and God is kind, and that grief is strong : it 
knows not well what is possible to such grief. To 
silence a stream, to move a cottage wall — one might 
think it could do as much as that I 

§ 16. I believe these instances are enough to illus- 
trate the main point I insist upon respecting the 
pathetic fallacy — ^that so far as it is a fallacy, it is 
always the sign of a morbid state of mind, and com- 
paratively of a weak one. Even in the most inspired 



182 THE PATHETIC FALLACY [part iv 

prophet it is a sign of the incapacity of his human sight 
or thought to be^r what has been revealed to it. In 
ordinary poetry, if it is found in the thoughts of the 
poet himself, it is at once a sign of his belonging to 
the inferior school; if in the thoughts of the charac- 
ters imagined by him, it is right or wrong according 
to the genuineness of the emotion from which it 
springs; always, however, implying necessarily some 
degree of weakness in the character. 

Take two most exquisite instances from master 
hands. The Jessy of Shenstone, and the Ellen of 
Wordsworth, have both been betrayed and deserted. 
Jessy, in the course of her most touching complaint, 
says : , 

If through the garden’s flowery tribes I stray, 

Where bloom the jasmines that could once allure, 

‘ Hope not to find delight in us they say, 

‘ For we are spotless, Jessy ; we are pure,’ 

Compare with this some of the words of Ellen : 

‘ Ah, why ’, said Ellen, sighing to herself, 

* Why do not words, and kiss, and solemn pledge, 

Ana nature, that is kind in woman’s breast, 

And reason, that in man is wise and good, 

And fear of Him who is a righteous Judge, — 

Why do not these prevail for human life. 

To keep two hearts together, that began 
Their springtime with one love, and that have need 
Of mutual pity and forgiveness, sweet 
To grant, or be received ; while that poor bird — 

O, come and hear him ! Thou who hast to me 
Been faithless, hear him ; — though a lowly creature, 

One of Ood’s simple children, >hat yet know not 
The Universal Parent, how he sings ! 

As if he wished the firmament of heaven 

Should listen, and give back to him the voice ^ 

Of his triumphant constancy and love. 

The proclamation that he makes, how far 
His darkness doth transcend our fickle light.’ 

The perfection of both these passages, as far as 
regards truth and tenderness of imagination in the 
two poets, is quite insuperable. But, of the two 
characters imagined, Jessy is weaker than Ellen, 



188 


CHAP. XII] THE PATHETIC FALLACY 

exactly in so far as something appears to her to be 
in nature which is not. The flowers do not really 
reproach her. God meant them to comfort her, not 
to taunt her; they would do so if she saw them 
rightly. 

Ellen, on the other hand, is quite above the slight- 
est erring emotion. There is not the barest film of 
fallacy in all her thoughts. She reasons as calmly 
as if she did not feel. And, although the singing 
of the bird suggests to her the idea of its desiring 
to be heard in heaven, she does not for an instant 
admit any veracity in the thought. ‘As if ’, she 
says, — ‘ I know he means nothing of the kind; but 
it does verily seem as if.’ The reader will find, by 
examining the rest of the poem, that Ellen’s character 
is throughout consistent in this clear though passion- 
ate strength 

It then being, I hope, now made clear to the 
reader in all respects that the pathetic fallacy is 
powerful only so far as it is pathetic, feeble so far 
as it is fallacious, and, therefore, that the dominion 
of Truth is entire,, over this, as over every other 
natural and just state of the human mind, we may 
go on to the subject for the dealing with which this 
prefatory inquiry became necessary; and why neces- 
sary, we shall see forthwith. 

1 I cannot quit this subject without giving two more instances, 
both exquisite, of the pathetic fallacy, which I have just come 
upon, in Maude : 

For a great speculation had fail'd ; 

And ever he mutter’d and madden’d, and ever wann’d with 
despair ; • 

And out he walk’d, when the wind like a broken worldling 
wail’d. 

And the jlyiny gold of the ruirCd woodlands drove thro* the 
air. 

There has fallen a splendid tear 
From the passion-flower at the gate. 

The red rose cries, ‘ She is near, she is near ! ’ 

And the white rose weeps, * She is late* 

The larkspur listens, ‘ I hear, I hear !* 

And th^Mly whispers, ‘ / wait* 



CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE [part iv 


CHAPTER XIII 

OF CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE 

§ 1. Mt reason for asking the reader to give so 
much of his time to the examination of the pathetic 
fallacy was, that, whether in literature or in art, he 
will find it eminently characteristic of the modern 
mind; and in the landscape, whether of literature 
or art, he will also find the modern painter endeav- 
ouring to express something which ne, as a living 
creatui^, imagines in the lifeless object, while the 
classical and mediaeval painters were content with 
expressing the unimaginary and actual qualities of 
the object, itself. It will be observed that, accord- 
ing to principle stated long ago, I use the words 
painter arid poet quite indifferently, including in our 
inquiry the landscape of literature, as well as that of 
painting; and this the more because the spirit of 
classical landscape has hardly bepn expressed in any 
other way than by words. 

§ 2. Taking, therefore, this wide field, it is surely 
a very notable circumstance, to begin with, that this 
pathetic fallacy is eminently characteristic of modern 
painting. For instance, Keats, describing a wave, 
breaking, out at sea, says of it 

Down whose green back the short-lived foam, all hoar. 
Bursts gradual, with a wayward indolence. 

That is quite perfect, as an Sample of the modern 
manner. The idea of the peculiar action with which 
foam rolls down a long, large wave could not have 
been given by any other words ao well as by this 
‘ wayward indolence ’. But Homer would never have 
written, never thought of, such words. He could 
not bv any possibility have lost sight of the great 
fact that the wave, from the beginning to the end 
of it, do what it might, was still nothing else than 
salt water; and that salt water could not be either 



CHAP. XIII] CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE ' 185 

wayward or indolent. He will call the waves ‘ over- 
roofed ‘ full-charged *, * monstrous *, ‘ compact- 

black ‘ dark-clear ‘ violet-coloured ‘ wine- 
coloured and so on. But every one of these 
epithets is descriptive of pure physical nature. 

‘ Over-roofed ’ is the term he invariably uses of any- 
thing — ^rock, house, or wave — that nods over at the 
brow : the other terms need no explanation ; they 
are as accurate and intense in truth as words can 
be, but they never show the slightest feeling of any- 
thing animated in the ocean. Bl^ck or clear, mon- 
strous or violet-coloured, cold salt water it is always, 
and nothing but that. 

§ 3. ‘ Well, but the modern writer, by his admis- 
sion of the tinge of fallacy, has given an idea of 
something in the action of the wave which Homer 
could not, and surely, therefore, has made a step in 
advance? Also there appears to be a degree of 
sympathy and feeling in the one writer, which there 
is not in the other; and as it has been received for 
a first principle that writers are great in proportion 
to the intensity of their feelings, and Homer seems 
to have no feelings about the sea but that it is black 
and deep, surely in this respect also the modern 
writer is the greater?’ 

Stay a moment. Homer had some feeling about 
the sea ; a faith in the animation of it much stronger 
than Keats’s. But all this sense of something 
living in it, he separates in his mind into a great 
abstract image of a Sea Power. He never says the 
waves rage, or the waves are idle. But hg.says there 
is some\^at in, and greater than, the waves, which 
rages, and is idle, and that he calls a god. 

§ 4. I do not think we ever enough endeavour to 
enter into what a Greek’s real notion of a god was. 
We are so accustomed to the modern mockeries of 
the classical religion, so accustomed to hear and 
see the Greek gods introduced as living personages, 
or invoked for help, by men who believe neither in 
them nor in any other gods, that we seem to have 
infected the Greek ages themselves with the breath, 



(186 CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE [pakt iv 

and dimmed them with the shade, of our hypocrisy; 
and are apt to think that Homer, as we know that 
Pope, was merely an ingenious fabulist; nay, more 
than this, that all the nations of past time were 
ingenious fabulists also, to whom the universe was a 
lyrical drama, and by whom whatsoever was said 
^bout it was merely a witty allegory, or a graceful 
lie, of which the entire upshot and consummation 
was a pretty statue in the middle of the court, or at 
the end of the garden. 

This, at least, is one of our forms of opinion about 
Greek faith; not, indeed, possible altogether to any 
man of honesty or ordinary powers of thought ; but 
still so venomously inherent in the modern philo- 
sophy that all the pure lightning of Carlyle cannot 
as yet quite burn it out of any of us. And then, 
aide by side with this mere infidel folly, stands the 
bitter short-sightedness of Puritanism, holding the 
classical god to be either simply an idol — a block of 
stone ignorantly, though sincerely, worshipped—or 
else an actual diabolic or betraying power, usurping 
the place of God. 

§ 5. J3oth these Puritanical estimates of Greek 
deity are of course to some extent true. The cor- 
ruption of classical worship is barren idolatry; and 
that corruption was deepened, and variously directed 
to their own purposes, by the evil angels. But this 
was neither the whole, nor the principal part, of 
Pagan worship. Pallas was not, in the pure Greek 
miind, merely a powerful piece of ivory in a temple 
at Athens;^ neither was the 9 hoice of Leonidas be- 
tween the ‘alternatives granted him by the oracle, 
of personal death, or ruin to his country, altogether 
a work of the Devil’s prompting. 

§ 6. What, then, was actually the Greek god? In 
what way were these two ideas of human form, and 
divine power, credibly associated in the ancient heart, 
so as to become a subject of true faith, irrespective 
equally of fable, allegory, superstitious trust in stone, 
and demoniacal influence? 

It seems to me that the Greek had exactly the 



187 


CHAP. XIII] CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE 

same instinctive feeling about the elements that we 
have ourselves; that to Homer, as much as to 
Casimir de la Vigne, fire seemed ravenous and piti- 
less; to Homer, as much as to Keats, the sea-wave 
appeared wayward or idle, or whatever else it may 
be to the poetical passion. But then the Greek 
reasoned upon this sensation, saying to himself : ‘ I 
can light the fire, and put it out; I can dry this 
water up, or drink it. It cannot be the fire or the 
water that rages, or that is wayward. But it must 
be something in this fire and in the water, which I 
cannot destroy by extinguishing the one, or evaporat- 
ing the other, any more than I destroy myself by 
cutting off my finger; I was in my finger — some- 
thing of me at least was; I had a power over it, 
and felt pain in it, though I am still as much myself 
when it is gone. So there may be a power in the 
water which is not water, but to which the water is 
as a body; — which can strike with it, move in it, 
suffer in it, yet not be destroyed with it. This some- 
thing, this great Water Spirit, I must not confuse 
with the waves, which are only its body. They may 
flow hither and thither, increase or diminish. That 
must be indivisible — imperishable — a god. So of fire 
also; those rays which I can stop, and in the midst 
of which I cast a shadow, cannot be divine, nor 
greater than I. They cannot feel, but there may be 
something in them that feels — a glorious intelligence, 
as much nobler and more swift than mine, as these 
rays, which are its body, are nobler and swifter than 
my flesh; — the spirit of all light, and ^truth, and 
melody, and revolving hours.’ 

§ 7. It was easy to conceive, farther, that such 
spirits should be able to assume at will a human 
form, in order to hold intercourse with men, or to 
perform any act for which their proper body, whether 
of fire, earth, or air, was unfitted. And it would 
have been to place them beneath, instead of above, 
humanity, if, assuming the form of man, they could 
not also have tasted his pleasures. Hence the easy 
step to the more or less material ideas of deities. 



^8 CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE [part iv 

*which are apt at first to shock us, but which are 
indeed only dishonourable so far as they represent 
the gods as false and unholy. It is not the material- 
ism, but the vice, which degrades the conception; 
for the materialism itself is never positive or com- 
plete. There is always some sense of exaltation in 
the spiritual and immortal body; and of a power 
proceeding from the visible form through all the 
infinity of the element ruled by the particular god. 
The precise nature of the idea is well seen in the 
passage of the Iliad which describes the river Sca- 
mander defending the Trojans against Achilles. In 
order to remonstrate with the hero, the god assumes 
a human form, which nevertheless is in some way 
or other instantly recognized by Achilles as that of 
the river-god : it is addressed at once as a river, 
not as a man; and its voice is the voice of a river, 
* out of the deep whirlpools * Achilles refuses to 
obey its commands; and from the human form it 
returns instantly into its natural or divine one, and 
endeavours to overwhelm him with waves. Vulcan 
defends Achilles, and sends fire against the river, 
which suffers in its water-body, till it is able to bear 
no more. At last even the ‘ nerve of the river \ or 
‘ strength of the river ’ (note the expression), feels 
the fire, and this ‘ strength of the river ’ addresses 
Vulcan in supplications for respite. There is in this 
precisely the idea of a vital part of the river-body, 
which acted and felt, and which, if the fire reached, 
it was death, just as would be the case if it touched 
a vital paft of the human body. Throughout the 
passage the manner of conception is perfectly clear 
and consistent; and if, in other places, the exact 
connection between the ruling spirit and the thing 
ruled is not so manifest, it is only because it is 
almost impossible for the human mind to dwell long 
upon such subjects without falling into inconsisten- 

1 Compare Lay of the Last Minstrel, canto i, stanza 15, and 
canto V, stanza 2. In the first instance, the river-spirit is 
accurately the Homeric god, only Homer would have believed 
in it — Scott did not ; at least not altogether. 



CHAP. XIII] CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE ' 189 

cies, and gradually slat^ening its effort to grasp the 
entire truth ; until the more spiritual part of it slips 
from its hold, and only the human form of the god 
is left, to be conceived and described aB 'fubject to 
all the errors of humanity. But I do not believe that 
the idea ever weakens itself down to mere aUegory. 
When Pallas is said to attack and strike down Mars, 
it does not mean merely that Wisdom at that moment 
prevailed against Wrath. It means that there are 
indeed two great spirits, one entrusted to guide the 
human soul to wisdom and chastity, the other to 
kindle wrath and prompt to battle. It means that 
these two spirits, on the spot where, and at the 
moment when, a great contest was to be decided 
between all that they each governed in man, then 
and there assumed human form,’ and human weapons, 
and did verily and materially strike at each other, 
until the Spirit of W^rath was crushed. And when 
Diana is said to hunt with her nymphs in the woods, 
it does not mean merely, as Wordsworth puts it, 
that the poet or shepherd saw the moon and stars 
glancing between the branches of the trees, and 
wished to say so figuratively. It means that there 
is a living spirit, to which the light of the moon 
is a body; which takes delight in glancing between 
the clouds’ and following the wild beasts as they 
wander through the night; and that this spirit some- 
times assumes a perfect human form, and in this 
form, with real arrows, pursues and slays the wild 
beasts, which with its mere arrows of moonlight it 
could not slay; retaining, nevertheless, ajl the while, 
its power and being in the moonlight, and in all 
else that it rules. 

§ 8. There is not the smallest inconsistency or 
unspirituality in this conception. If there were, it 
would attach equally to the appearance of the angels 
to Jacob, Abraham, Joshua, or Manoah. In all those 
instances the highest authority which governs our 
own faith requires us to conceive divine power 
clothed with a human form (a form so real that it 
is recognized for superhuman only by its ‘ doing 



pQ CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE [part iv 

Wdiidrously ’), and retaining, nevertheless, sovereignty 
and bmnipresence in all the world. This is pre- 
cisely, as I understand it, the heathen idea of a 
God; and it is impossible to comprehend any single 
part of the Greek mind until we grasp this faithfully, 
not endeavouring to explain it away in any wise, but 
accepting, with frank decision and definition, the 
tangible existence of its deities; — blue-eyed — ^white- 
fleshed — human-hearted, — capable at their choice of 
meeting man absolutely in his own nature — feasting 
with him — ^talking with him — fighting with him, eye 
to eye, or breast to breast, as Mars with Diomed; or 
else, dealing with him in a more retired spirituality, 
as Apollo sending the plague upon the Greeks, when 
his quiver rattles at his shoulders as ho moves, and 
yet the darts sent forth of it strike not as arrows, 
but as plague; or, finally, retiring completely into 
the material universe which they properly inhabit, 
and dealing with man through that, as Scamander 
with Achilles through his waves. 

§ 9. Nor is there anything whatever in the various 
actions recorded of the gods, however apparently 
ignoble, to indicate weakness of belief in them. Very 
frequently things which appear to us ignoble are 
merely the simplicities of a pure and truthful age. 
When Juno beats Diana about the ears with her own 
quiver, for instance, we start at first, as if Homer 
could not have believed that they were both real 

f oddesscs. But what should Juno have done? Killed 
>iana with a look? Nay, she neither wished to do 
so, nor coi\ld she have done so, by the very faith 
of Diana’s goddess-ship. Diana is as immortal as 
herself. Frowned Diana into submission? But 
Diana has come expressly to try conclusions wdth 
her, and will by no means be frowned into sub- 
mission. Wounded her with a celestial lance? That 
sounds more poetical, but it is in reality partly more 
savage, and partly more absurd, than Homer. More 
savage, for it makes Juno more cruel, therefore less 
divine; and more absurd, for it only seems elevated 
in tone, because we use the word ‘ celestial ’, which 



.191 


CHAP.xm] CLASSICAX. LANDSCAPE 

means nothing. What sort of a thing is a ‘ celestial ’ 
lance? Not a wooden one. Of what then? Of 
moonbeams, or clouds, or mist. Well, therefore, 
Diana’s arrows were of mist too; and her quiver,, 
and herself, and Juno, with her lance, and all, vanish 
into mist. Why not have said at once, if that is all 
you mean, that two mists met, and one drove the 
other back? That would have been rational and 
intelligible, but not to talk of celestial lances. Homer 
had no such misty fancy; he believed the two god- 
desses were therein true bodies, with true weapons,, 
on the true earth; and still 1 ask, what should Juno 
have done? Not beaten Diana? No; for it is un- 
lady-like. Un-English-lady-like, yes; but by no 
means un-Greek-lady-like, nor even un-natural-lady- 
like. If a modern lady does not beat her servant 
or her rival about the ears, it is of tenor because she 
is too weak, or too proud, than because she is of 
purer mind than Homer’s Juno. . She will not strike 
them; but she will overwork the one or slander 
the other without pity; and Homer would not have 
thought that one whit more goddess-like than striking- 
them with her open hand. 

§ 10. If, however, the reader likes to suppose that 
while the Wo goddesses in personal presence thus 
fought with arrow and quiver, there was also a 
broader and vaster contest supposed by Homer be- 
tween the elements they ruled; and that the goddess 
of the heavens, as she struck the goddess of the 
moon on the flushing cheek, was at the same instant 
exercising omnipresent power in the heajens them- 
selves, and gathering clouds, with which, filled with 
the moon’s own arrows or beams, she was encumber- 
ing and concealing the moon; he is welcome to this- 
out-carrying of the idea, provided that he does not 
pretend to make it an interpretation instead of a. 
mere extension, nor think to explain away my real,, 
running, beautiful, beaten Diana, into a moon behind 
clouds 1. 

^ Compare the exqnisite lines of Longfellow on the sunset, 
in The Golden Legend: 



CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE [part iv 

5“ 11. It is only farther to be noted, that the Greek 
Conception of Godhead, as it was much more real 
than we usually suppose, so it was much more bold 
and familiar than to a modern mind would be pos- 
sible. I shall have something more to observe, in a 
little while, of the danger of our modern habit of 
endeavouring to raise ourselves to something like 
comprehension of the truth of divinity, instead of 
simply believing the words in which the Deity reveals 
Himself to us. The Greek erred rather on the other 
side, making hardly any effort t(^ conceive divine 
mind as above the human; and no more shrinking 
from frank intercourse with a divine being, or dread- 
ing its immediate presence, than that of the simplest 
of mortals. Thus Atrides, enraged at his sword’s 
breaking in his hand upon the helmet of Paris, after 
he had expressly invoked the assistance of Jupiter, 
exclaims aloud, as he would to a king who had be- 
trayed him, ‘ Jove, Father, there is not another god 
more evil-minded than thou I’ and Helen, provoked 
at Paris’s defeat, and oppressed with pouting shame 
both for him and for herself, when Venus appears 
at her side, and would lead her back to the delivered 
Paris, impatiently tells the goddess to ‘ go and take 
care of Paris herself.’ 

§^12. The modern mind is naturally, but vulgarly 
and unjustly, shocked by this kind of familiarity. 
Rightly understood, it is not so much a sign of mis- 
understanding of the divine nature as of good under- 
standing of the human. The Greek lived, in all 
things, a healthy, and, in a cerj;ain degree, a perfect, 
life. He had no morbid or 'sickly feeling of any 
kind. He was accustomed to face death without the 
slightest shrinking, to undergo all kinds of bodily 
hardship without complaint, and to do what he sup- 
posed right and honourable, in most cases, as a 
matter of course. Confident of his own immortality. 


The day is done, and slowly from the scene 
The stooping aun npgathers his spent shafts, 
And puts thorn back into his golden quiver. 



CHAP, xiii] CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE 193 

and of the power of abstract justice, he expected to 
be dealt with in the next world as was right, and 
left the matter much in his god’s hands; but being 
thus immortal, and finding in his own soul some- 
thing which it seemed quite as difficult to master, 
as to rule the elements, he did not feel that it was 
an appalling superiority in those gods to have bodies 
of water, or fire, instead of flesh, and to have various 
work to do among the clouds and waves, out of his 
human way; or sometimes, even, in a sort of service 
to himself. Was not the nourishment of herbs and 
flowers a kind of ministering to his wants? were not 
the gods in some sort his husbandmen, and spirit- 
servants? Their mere strength or omnipresence did 
not seem to him a distinction absolutely terrific. It 
might be the nature of one being to be in two places 
at once, and of another to be only in one; but that 
did not seem of itself to infer any absolute lordliness 
of one nature above the other, any more than an 
insect must be a nobler creature than a man, because 
it can see on four sides of its head, and the man 
only in front. They could kill him or torture him, it 
w’as true; but even that not unjustly, or not for ever. 
There was a fate, and a Divine Justice, greater than 
they; so that if they did wrong, and he right, he 
might fight it out with them, and have the better 
of them at last. In a general way, they were wiser, 
stronger, and better than he; and to ask counsel 
of them, to obey them, to sacrifice to them, to thank 
them for all good, this was well; but to be utterly 
downcast before them, or not to toll them^his mind 
in plain Greek if they seemed to him to be conducting 
themselves in an ungodly manner — this would not 
be well. 

§ 13. Such being their general idea of the gods, 
we can now easily understand the habitual tone of 
their feelings towards what was beautiful in nature. 
With us, observe, the idea of the Divinity is apt to 
get separated from the life of nature; and imagining 
our God upon a cloudy throne, far above the earth, 
and not in the flowers or waters, we approach those 
M. P., III. o 



lU classical landscape [part iv 

visible things with a theery that they are dead, 
governed by physical laws, and so forth. But coming 
to them, we find the theory fail; that they are not 
dead; that, say what we choose about them, the 
instinctive sense of their being alive is too strong 
for us; and in scorn of all physical law, the wilfdl 
iountain sings, and the kindly flowers rejoice. And 
then, puzzled, and yet happy; pleased, and yet 
ashamed of being so; accepting sympathy from 
nature, which we do not believe it gives, and giving 
sympathy to nature, which we do not believe it re- 
ceives — mixing, besides, all manner of purposeful 
play and conceit with these involuntary fellowships, 
— we fall necessarily into the curious web of hesitat- 
ing sentiment, pathetic fallacy, and wandering fancy, 
which form a great part of our modern view of nature. 
But the Greek never removed his god out of nature 
at all; never attempted for a moment to contradict 
his instinctive sense that God was everywhere. ‘ The 
tree is glad ’, said he, ‘ 1 know it is; I can cut it 
down; no matter, there was a nymph in it. The 
water does sing \ said he; ‘I can dry it up; but 
no matter, there was a naiad in it.’ But in thus 
clearly defining his belief, observe, he threw it en- 
tirely into a human form, and gave his faith to 
nothing but the image of his own humanity. What 
sympathy and fellowship he had, were always for the 
spirit in the stream, not for the stream; always 
for the dryad in the wood, not for the wood^ - Content 
with this human sympathy, he approached the actual 
waves and woody fibres with no sympathy at all. 
The spirit that rulei them, he received as a plain 
fact. Them, also, ruled and material, ho received 
as plain facts; they, without their spirit, were dead 
enough. A rose was good for scent, and a stream 
for sound and coolness; for the rest, one was no 
more than leaves, the other no more than water; he 
could not make anything else of them; and the 
divine power, which was involved in their existence, 
having been all distilled away by him into an inde- 
pendent Flora or Thetis, the poor leaves or waves 



CHAP, xiii] CLASSICAL LAIPSCAPE m 

were left, in mere cold corporealness, tp make the 
most of their being discernibly red and soft, clear 
and wet?,' and unacknowledged in any other power 
whatsoever. 

§ 14. Then, observe farther, the Greeks lived in 
the midst of the most beautiful nature, and were 
as familiar with blue sea, clear air, and sweet out- 
lines of mountain, as we are with brick walls, black 
smoke, and level fields. This perfect familiarity 
rendered all such scenes of natural beauty unex- 
citing, if not indifferent to them, by lulling and over- 
wearying the imagination as far as it was concerned 
with such things; but there was another kind of 
beauty which they found it required effort to obtain, 
and which, when thoroughly obtained, seemed more 
glorious than any of this wild loveliness — the beauty 
of the human countenance and form. This, they 
perceived, could only be reached by continual exercise 
of virtue; and it was in Heaven’s sight, and theirs, 
all the more beautiful because it needed this self- 
denial to obtain it. So they set themselves to reach 
this, and having gained it, gave it their principal 
thoughts, and set it off with beautiful dress as best 
they might. But making this their object, they were 
oblij^ed to pass their lives in simple exercise and dis- 
ciplined employments. Living wholesomely, giving 
themselves no fever fits, either by fasting or over- 
eating, constantly in the open air, and full of animal 
spirit and physical power, they became incapable 
of every morbid condition of mental emotion. Un- 
happy love, disappointed ambition, spirituEj despond- 
ency, or any other disturbing sensation, had little 
power over ihe well-braced nerves, and healthy flow 
of the blood; and what bitterness might yet fasten 
on them was soon boxed or raced out of a boy, and 
spun or woven out of a girl, or danced out of both. 
They had indeed their sorrows, true and deep, but 
still, more like children’s sorrows than ours, whether 
bursting into open cry of pain, or hid with shudder- 
ing under the veil, still passing over the soul as 
clouds do over heaven, not sullying it, not mingling 



196 CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE [part iv 

with it darkening it perhaps long or utterly, but 
still not becoming one with it, and for the most 
part passing away in dashing rain of tears, and 
leaving the man unchanged; in nowise affecting, as 
our sorrow does, the whole tone of his thought and 
im^ination thenceforward. 

« How far our melancholy may be deeper and wider 
than theirs, in its roots and view, and therefore 
nobler, we shall consider presently; but at all events, 
they had the advantage of us in being entirely free 
from all those dim and feverish sensations which 
result from unhealthy state of the body. I believe 
that a large amount of the dreamy and sentimental 
sadness, tendency to reverie, and general pathetical- 
ness of modern life results merely from derangement 
of stomach; holding to the Greek life the same 
relation that the feverish night of an adult does to 
a child’s sleep. 

§ 15. Farther. The human beauty, which, whether 
in its bodily being or in imagined divinity, had be- 
come, for the reasons we have seen, the principal 
object of culture and sympathy to these Greeks, 
was, in its perfection, eminently orderly, symmetrical, 
and tender, itence, contemplating it constantly in 
this state, they could not but feel a proportionate 
fear of all that was disorderly, unbalanced, and 
rugged. Having trained their stoutest soldiers into 
a strength so delicate and lovely, that their white 
flesh, with their blood upon it, should look like ivory 
stained with purple ^ ; and having always around 
them, in# the motion and majesty of this beauty, 
enough for the full employment of their imagination, 
they shrank with dread or hatred from all the rugged- 
ness of lower nature — from the wrinkled forest bark, 
the jagged hill-crest, and irregular, inorganic storm 
of sky; looking to these for the most part as adverse 
powers, and taking pleasure only in such portions of 
the lower wotld as were at once conducive to the 
rest and health of the human frame, and in harmony 
with the laws of its gentler beauty. 

1 lliad^ iv, 141. 



CHAP. XIII] CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE 197 

§ 16. Thus, as far as I recollect, without a single 
exception, every Homeric landscape, intended to be 
beautiful, is composed of a fountain, a meadow, 
and a shady grove. This ideal is very interestingly 
marked, as intended for a perfect one, in the fifth 
book of the Odyssey; when Mercury himself stops 
for a moment, though on a message, to look at a 
landscape ‘ which even an immortal might be glad- 
dened to behold This landscape consists of a cave 
covered with a running vine, all blooming into grapes, 
and surrounded by a grove of alder, poplar, and sweet- 
smelling cypress. Four fountains of white (foaming) 
water, springing in succession (mark the orderliness), 
and close to one another, flow away in different 
directions, through a meadow full of violets and 
parsley (parsley, to mark its moisture, being else- 
where called ‘ marsh -nourished ’, and associated with 
the lotus 1) ; the air is perfumed not only by these 
violets and by the sweet cypress, but by Calypso’s 
fire of finely chopped cedar wood, which sends a 
smoke, as of incense, through the island; Calypso 
herself is singing; and finally, upon the trees are 
resting, or roosting, owls, hawks, and ‘ long-tongued 
sea-crows Whether these last are considered as a 
part of the ideal landscape, as marine singing-birds, 

I know not; but the approval of Mercury appears 
to be elicited chiefly by the fountains and violet 
meadow. 

§ 17. Now the notable things in this description 
are, first, the evident subservience of the whole land- 
scape to human comfort, to the foot, tha taste, or 
the smell; and, secondly, that throughout the pas- 
sage there is not a single figurative word expressive 
of the things being in any wise other than plain 
grass, fruit, or flower. I have used the term ‘ spring ’ 
of the fountains, because, without doubt, Homer 
means that they sprang forth brightly, having their 
source at the foot of the rocks (as copious fountains 
nearly always have) ; but Homer does not say 
‘ spring ’, he says simply flow, and uses only one 
1 Iliad, ii, 776. 



198 CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE [part iv 

word for ‘ growing softly *, or ‘ richly of the tall 
trees, the vine, and the violets. There is, however, 
some expression of sympathy with the sea-birds; he 
Speaks of them in precisely the same terms, as in 
other places of naval nations, saying they ‘ have care 
of the works of the sea.’ 

^ § 18. If we glance through the references to plea- 
sant landscape which occur in other parts of the 
Odyssey, we shall always be struck by this quiet sub- 
jection of their every feature to human service, and 
by the excessive similarity in the scenes. Perhaps 
the spot intended, after this, to be most perfect, 
may be the garden of Alcinous, where the principal 
ideas are, still more definitely, order, symmetry, and 
fruitfulness; the beds being duly ranged between 
rows of vines, which, as well as the pear, apple, 
and fig-trees, bear fruit continually, some grapes 
being yet sour, while others are getting black; there 
are plenty of ‘ orderly square beds of herbs chiefly 
leeks, and two fountains, one running through the 
garden, and one under the pavement of the palace 
to a reservoir for the citizens. Ulysses, pausing to 
contemplate this scene, is described nearly in the 
same terms as Mercury pausing to contemplate the 
wilder meadow; and it is interesting to observe, 
that, in spite of all Homer’s love of symmetry, the 
god’s admiration is excited by the free fountains, 
wild violets, and wandering vine; but the mortal’s, 
by the vines in rows, the leeks in beds, and the 
fountains in pipes. 

Ulysses* has, however, one' touching reason for 
loving vines in rows. His father had given him fifty 
rows for himself, when he was a boy, with corn 
between them (just as it now grows in Italy). Prov- 
ing his identity afterwards to his father, whom he 
finds at work in his garden, ‘ with thick gloves on, 
to keep his hands from the thorns ’, he reminds him 
of these fifty rows of vines, and of the ‘ thirteen 
pear-trees and ten apple-trees * which he had given 
him; and Laertes faints upon his neck, 

§ 19. If Ulysses had not been so much of a 



CHAP, xin] CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE 199 

gardener^ it might have been received as a sign of 
considerable feeling for landscape beauty, that, in- 
tending to pay the very highest possible compliment 
to the Princess Nausicaa, (and having indeed- the 
moment before, gravely asked her whether she was 
a goddess or not), he says that he feels, at seeing 
her, exactly as he did when he saw the young palm- 
tree growing at Apollo’s shrine at Delos. But I 
think the taste for trim hedges and upright trunks 
has its usual influence over him here also, and that 
he merely means to tell the princess that she is 
delightfully tall and straight. 

§ 20. The princess is, however, pleased by his 
address, and tells him to wait outside the town, till 
she can speak to her father about him. The spot 
to which she directs him is another ideal piece of 
landscape, composed of a * beautiful grovo of aspen 
poplars, a fountain, and a meadow near the road- 
side; in fact, as nearly as possible such a scene as 
meets- the eye of the traveller every instant on the 
much-despised lines of road through lowland France; 
for instance, on the railway between Arras and 
Amiens; — scenes, to my mind, quite exquisite in 
the various grouping and grace of their innumerable 
po)f)lar avenues, casting sweet, tremulous shadows 
over their level meadows and labyrinthine streams. 
We know that the princess means aspen poplars, 
because soon afterwards we find her fifty maid- 
servants at the palace, all spinning, and in perpetual 
motion, compared to the ‘ leaves of the tall poplar ’ ; 
and it is with exquisite feeling that it is^made after- 
wards 1 the chief tree in the groves of Proserpine ; its 
light and quivering leafage having exactly the melan- 
choly expression of fragility, faintness, and incon- 
stancy which the ancients attributed to the disem- 
bodied spirit 2. The likeness to the poplars by the 
streams of Amiens is more marked still in the Iliad j 
where the young Simois, struck by Ajax, falls to 

1 Odyssey^ x, 510. 

2 Compare the passage in Dante referred to above Chap. 
XII, § 6. 



I i«) CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE [part iv 

the earth ‘ like an aspen that has grown in, an irri- 
gated meadow, smooth-trunked, the soft shoots 
springing from its top, which some coach-making 
man has cut down with his keen iron, that he may 
fit a wheel of it to a fair chariot, and it lies parching 
by the side of the stream.’ It is sufficiently notable 
that Homer, living in mountainous and rocky coun- 
tnes, dwells thus delightedly on all the flat bits; 
and so I think invariably the inhabitants of moun- 
tain countries do, but the inhabitants of the plains 
do not, in any similar way, dwell delightedly on 
mountains. The Dutch painters are perfectly con- 
tented with their flat fields and pollards : Rubens, 
though he had seen the Alps, usually composes his 
landscapes of a hayfield or two, plenty of pollards 
and willows, a distant spire, a Dutch house with a 
moat about it, a windmill, and a ditch. The Flemish 
sacred painters are the only ones who introduce 
mountains in the distance, as we shall see presently; 
but rather in a formal way than with any appear- 
ance of enjoyment. So Shakspeare never speaks of 
mountains with the slightest joy, but only of low- 
land flowers, flat fields, and Warwickshire streams. 
And if we talk to the mountaineer, he will usually 
characterize his own country to us as a ‘ pays 
afire ux or in some equivalent, perhaps even more 
violent, German term : but the lowland peasant does 
not think his country frightful; he either will have 
no ideas beyond it, or about it; or will think it 
a very perfect country, and be apt to regard any 
deviation frjm its general principle of flatness with 
extreme disfavour ; as the Lincolnshire farmer in 
Alton Loche : ‘ I’ll shaw ’ee some ’at like a field o’ 
beans, wool — ^none o’ this here darned ups and 

downs o’ hills, to shake a body’s victuals out of 
his inwards — all so vlat as a barn’s vloor, for vorty 
mile on end — there’s the country to live ini’ 

/ i? whether this be altogether right 

(though certainly not wholly wrong), but it seems 
to me that there must be in the simple freshness 
and fruitfulness of level land, in its pale upright 



201 


CHAP, xiri] CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE 

trees, and gentle lapse of silent streams, enough for 
the satisfaction of the human mind in general; and 
I so far agree with Homer, that, if I had to educate 
an artist to the full perception of the meaning of the 
word ‘ gracefulness ’ in landscape, I should send 
him neither to Italy nor to Greece, but simply to 
those poplar groves between Arras and Amiens. 

§ 21. But to return more definitely to our Homeric 
landscape. When it is perfect, we have, as in the 
above instances, the foliage and meadows together; 
when imperfect, it is always either the foliage or the 
meadow; pre-eminently the meadow, or arable field. 
Thus, meadows of asphodel are prepared for the 
happier dead; and even Orion, a hunter among the 
mountains in his lifetime, pursues the ghosts of 
beasts in these asphodel meadows after death i. So 
the sirens sing in a meadow; and throughout the 
Odyssey there is a general tendency to the deprecia- 
tion of poor Ithaca, because it is rocky, and only fit 
for goats, and has ‘ no meadows for which reason 
Telemaclius refuses Atrides’s present of horses, con- 
gratulating the Spartan king at the same time on 
ruling over a plain which has ‘ plenty of lotus in 
it, and rushes *, with corn and barley. Note this 
constant dwelling on the marsh plants, or, at least, 
those which grow in flat and well -irrigated land, or 
beside streams : when Scamander, for instance, is 
restrained by Vulcan, Homer says, very sorrow- 
fully, that ‘ all his lotus, and reeds, and rushes were 
burnt and thus Ulysses, after being shipwrecked 
and nearly drowned, and beaten about^the sea for 
many days and nights, on raft and mast, at last 
getting ashore at the mouth of a large river, casts 
himself down first upon its rushes, and then, in 
thankfulness, kisses the ‘ corn-giving land as most 
opposed, in his heart, to the fruitless and devouring 
sea 2. 

^ Odyssey, xi, 571. xxiv, 13. The couch of Ceres, with 
Homer’s usual faithfulness, is made of a plouyked field, v, 
127. 

2 Odyssey, v, 398. 



CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE [part tv 

§ 22. In 4;his same passage, also, we £nd some 
peculiar expressions of the delight which the Greeks 
had in trees; for, when Ulysses first comes in sight 
of land, which gladdens him, ‘ as the reviving of a 
father from his sickness gladdens his children ’, it is 
not merely the sight of the land itself which gives 
hj^ such pleasure, but of the ‘ land and wood 
Horner never throws away any words, at least in 
such a place as this ; and what in another poet would 
have been merely the filling up of the deficient line 
with an otherwise useless word, is in him the ex- 
pression of the general Greek sense, that land of any 
kind was in nowise grateful or acceptable till there 
was wood upon it (or corn; but the corn, in the flats, 
could pot be seen so far as the black masses of 
forest on the hill sides), and that, as in being rushy 
and corn-giving, the low land, so in being woody, 
the high land, was most grateful to the mind of 
the man who for days and nights had been wearied 
on the engulphing sea. And this general idea of wood 
and corn, as the types of the fatness of the whole 
earth, is beautifully marked in another place of the 
Odyssey i, where the sailors in a desert island, having 
no flour of corn to offer as a meat offering with their 
sacrifices, take the leaves of the trees, and scatter 
them over the burnt offering instead. 

§ 23. But still, every expression of the pleasure 
which Ulysses has in this landing and resting, con- 
tains uninterruptedly the reference to the utility and 
sensible pleasantness of all things, not to their 
beauty. Af^ier his first grateful^ kiss given to the 
corn-growing land, he considers immediately how he 
is to pass the night; for some minutes hesitating 
whether it will be best to expose himself to the 
misty chill from the river, or run the risk of wild 
beasts in the wood. He decides for the wood, and 
finds in it a bower formed by a sweet and a wild 
olive tree, interlacing their branches, or — ^perhaps 
more accurately translating Homer ’s intensely graphic 
expression — ‘ changing their branches with each 
^ Odyssey^ xii, 357. 



CHAP, xm] CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE ' 203 

other ’ (it is very curious how often, in an entangle- 
ment of wood, one supposes the branches to belong 
to the wrong trees), and forming a roof penetrated 
by neither rain, sun, nor wind. Under this bower 
Ulysses collects the ‘ vain (or frusirate) outpouring of 
the dead leaves ’ — another exquisite expression, used 
elsewhere of useless grief or shedding of tears; and, 
having got enough together, makes his bed of them, 
and goes to sleep, having covered himself up with 
them, ‘ as embers are covered up with ashes.’ 

Nothing can possibly be more intensely possessive 
of the facta than this whole passage; the sense of 
utter deadness and emptiness, and frustrate fall in 
the leaves; of dormant life in the human body, — 
the fire, and heroism, and strength of it, lulled under 
the dead brown heap, as embers under ashes, and 
the knitting of interchanged and close strength of 
living boughs above. But there is not the smallest 
apparent sense of there being beauty elsewhere than 
in the human being. The wreathed wood is admired 
simply as being a perfect roof for it ; the fallen leaves 
only as being a perfect bed for it ; and there is literally 
no more excitement of emotion in Homer, as he 
describes them, nor does he expect us to be more 
excited or touched by hearing about them, than if 
he had been telling us how the chambermaid at the 
Bull aired the four-poster, and put on two extra 
blankets. 

§ 24. Now, exactly this same contemplation of 
subservience to human use makes the Greek take 
some pleasure in rocks, when they asfyame one par- 
ticular form, but one only — ^that of a cave. They 
are evidently quite frightful things to him under any 
other condition, and most of all if they are rough 
and jagged; but if smooth, looking ‘ sculptured ’ like 
the sides of a ship, and forming a cave or shelter 
for him, he begins to think them endurable. Hence, 
associating the ideas of rich and sheltering wood, sea, 
becalmed and made useful as a port by projecting 
promontories of rock, and smoothed caves or grottoes 
in the rocks themselves, we get the pleasantest idea 



m CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE [part iv 

which the Greek could form of a landscape, next to 
a marsh with poplars in it; not, indeed, if possible, 
ever to be without these last : thus, in commending 
the Cyclops’ country as one possessed of every per- 
fection, Homer first says : ‘ They have soft marshy 
meadows near the sea, and good, rich, crumbling, 
plpughing-land, giving fine deep crops, and vines 
always giving fruit then, ‘ a port so quiet, that 
they have no need of cables in it; and at the head 
of the port, a beautiful clear spring just under a 
cave, and aspen poplars all round it ’ 

§ 25. This, it will be seen, is very nearly Homer’s 
usual ‘ ideal ’ ; but, going into the middle of the 
island, Ulysses comes on a rougher and less agree- 
able bit, though still fulfilling certain required con- 
ditions of endurableness; a ‘cave shaded with 
laurels ’, which, having no poplars about it, is, how- 
ever, meant to be somewhat frightful, and only fit 
to be inhabited by a Cyclops. So in the country of 
the Laestrygonsj Homer, preparing his reader grad- 
ually for something very disagreeable, represents the 
rocks as bare and ‘ exposed to the sun ’; only with 
some smooth and slippery roads over them, by which 
the trucks bring down wood from the higher hills. 
Any one familiar with Swiss slopes of hills must 
remember how often he has descended, sometimes 
faster than was altogether intentional, by these same 
slippery woodman’s truck roads. 

Amd thus, in general, whenever the landscape is 
intended to be lovely, it verges towards the ploughed 
land and poplars; or, at worst, ‘to woody rocks; 
but, if intended to be painful, the rocks are bare 
and ‘ sharp ’. This last epithet, constantly used by 
Homer for mountains, does not altogether corre- 
spond, in Greek, to the English term, nor is it in- 
tended merely to characterize the sharp mountain 
summits; for it never would be applied simply to 
the edge or point of a sword, but signifies rather 

1 Odyssey, ix, 132, &;c. Hence Milton’s 

From haunted spring, and dale, 

Edged with poplar pale. 



CHAP. XIII] CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE m 

‘ harsh ‘ bitter \ or * painful being applied habit- 
ually to fate, death, and in Od, ii, 333, to a halter; 
and, as expressive of general objectionableness and 
unpleasantness, to all high, dangerous, or peaked 
mountains, as the Maleian promontory (a much 
dreaded one), the crest of Parnassus, the Tereian 
mountain, and a grim or untoward, though, by keep- 
ing off the force of the sea, protective, rock at the 
mouth of the Jardanus; as well as habitually to 
inaccessible or impregnable fortresses built on 
heights. 

§ 26. In all this I cannot too strongly mark the 
utter absence of any trace of the feeling for what we 
call the picturesque, and the constant dwelling of 
the writer’s mind on what was available, pleasant, 
or useful; his ideas respecting all landscape being 
not uncharacteristically summed, finally, by Pallas 
herself; when, meeting Ulysses, who after his lon^ 
wandering does not recognize his own country, and 
meaning to describe it as politely and soothingly as 
possible, she says i : — ‘ This Ithaca of ours is, indeed, 
a rough country enough, and not good for driving in; 
but, still, things might be worse : it has plenty of 
c^rn, and good wine, and always rain^ and soft 
nourishing dew; and it has good feeding for goats 
and oxen, and all manner of wood, and springs fit 
to drink at all the year round.’ 

We shall see presently how the blundering, pseudo- 
picturesque, pseudo-classical minds of Claude and 
the Renaissance landscape-painters, wholly missing 
Homer’s practical common sense, and (Equally incap- 
able of feeling the quiet natural grace and sweetness 
of his asphodel meadows, tender aspen poplars, or 
running vines, fastened on his ports and caves j as 
the only available features of his scenery ; and 
appointed the type of ‘ classical landscape ’ thence- 
forward to consist in a bay of insipid sea, and a 
rock with a hole through it 2 . 

1 Odyssey, xiii, 236, &c. 

2 Educated, as we shall see hereafter, first in this school, 

Turner gave the hackneyed composition a strange power and 
freshness, in his Glaucus and Scylla. ^ 



CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE [part iv 

§ 27. It may indeed be thought that I am assum- 
ing too hastily that this was the general view of the 
Greeks respecting landscape, because it was Homer’s. 
But I believe the true mind of a nation, at any 
period, is always best ascertainable by examining 
that of its greatest men; and that simpler and truer 
results will be attainable for us by simply comparing 
Homer, Dante, and Walter Scott, than by attempt- 
ing (what my limits must have rendered absurdly 
inadequate, and in which, also, both my time and 
knowledge must have failed me) an analysis of the 
landscape in the range of contemporary literature. 
All that I can do, is to state the general impression 
which has been made upon me by my desultory 
reading, and to mark accurately the grounds for this 
impression, in the works of the greatest men. Now 
it is quite true that in others of the Greeks, especially 
in iEschylus and Aristophanes, there is infinitely 
more of modem feeling, of pathetic fallacy, love of 
picturesque or beautiful form, and other such ele- 
ments, than there is in Homer; but then these ap- 
pear to me just the parts of them which were not 
Greek, the elements of their minds by which (as one 
division of the human race always must be with 
subsequent ones) they are connected with the modiae- 
vals and moderns. And without doubt, in his in- 
fluence over future mankind, Homer is eminently the 
Greek of Greeks : if I were to associate any one 
with him it would be Herodotus, and I believe all 
I have said of the Homeric landscape will be found 
equally true ^of the Herodotean, a^ assuredly it will 
be of the Platonic; the contempt, which Plato some- 
times expresses by the mouth of Socrates, for the 
country in general, except so far as it is shady, and 
has cicadas and running streams to make pleasant 
noises in it, being almost ludicrous. But Homer is 
the great type, and the more notable one because 
of his influence on Virgil, and, through him, on 
Dante, and all the after ages : and, in like manner, 
if we can get the abstract of mediseval landscape 
out of Dante, it will serve us as well as if we had 
,read all the songs of the troubadours, and help us 



CHAP. XIII] CLASSICAL LAKDSCAPE ^ 20? 

to the farther changes in derivative temper, down to. 
all modern time. 

§ 28. I think, therefore, the reader may safely 
accept the conclusions about Greek landscape which 
I have got for him out of Homer; and in these he* 
will certainly perceive something very different from» 
the usual imaginations we form of Greek feelings.. 
We think of the Greeks as poetical, ideal, imagin- 
ative, in the way that a modern poet or novelist is;, 
supposing that their thoughts about their mythology 
and world were as visionary and artificial as our a 
are : but I think the passages I have quoted show 
that it was not so, although it may be difficult for 
us to apprehend the strange minglings in them of 
the elements of faith, which, in our days, have been 
blended with other parts of human nature in a totally 
different guise. Perhaps the Greek mind may be 
best imagined by taking, as its groundwork, that of 
a good, conscientious, but illiterate, Scotch Presby- 
terian Border farmer of a century or two back, 
having perfect faith in the bodily appearances of 
Satan and his imps; and in all kelpies, brownies,, 
and fairies. Substitute for the indignant terrors in 
this man’s mind, a general persuasion of the Divinity y 
more or less beneficent, yet faultful, of all these 
beings; that is to say, take away his belief in the 
demoniacal malignity of the fallen spiritual world, 
and lower, in the same degree, his conceptions of 
the angelical, retaining for him the same firm faith 
in both; keep his ideas about flowers and beautiful 
scenery much as they are — his delighjb in regular 
ploughed land and meadows, and a neat garden 
(only with rows of gooseberry bushes instead of 
vines), being, in all probability, about accurately 
representative of the feelings of Ulysses; then, let. 
the military spirit that is in him, glowing against the 
Border forager, or the foe of old Flodden and Chevy - 
Chase, be made more principal, with a higher sense- 
of nobleness in soldiership, not as a careless excite- 
ment, but a knightly duty; and increased by high 
cultivation of every personal quality, not of mere- 
shaggy strength, but graceful strength, aided by a.. 



W CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE [vajrt iv 

softer climate, and educated in all proper harmony 
of sight and sound : finally, instead of an informed 
Christian, suppose him to have only the patriarchal 
Jewish knowledge of the Deity, and even this ob- 
scured by tradition, but still thoroughly solemn Mid 
faithful, requiring his continual service as a priest 
of burnt sacrifice and meat offering; and I think 
we shall get a pretty close approximation to the vital 
being of a true old Greek; some slight difference still 
existing in a feeling which the Scotch farmer would 
have of a pleasantness in blue hills and running 
streams, wholly wanting in the Greek mind; and 
perhaps also some difference of views on the subjects 
of truth and honesty. But the main points, the easy, 
.athletic, strongly logical and argumentative, yet 
fanciful and credulous, characters of mind, would be 
very similar in both; and the most serious change 
in the substance of the stuff among the modifications 
above suggested as necessary to turn the Scot into the 
Greek, is that effect of softer climate and surrounding 
luxury, inducing the practice of various forms of 
polished art, the more polished, because the practical 
and realistic tendency of the Hellenic mind (if my 
interpretation of it be right) would quite prevent it 
from diking pleasure in any irregularities of form, or 
imitations of the ^eds and wildnesses of that moun- 
tain nature with which it thought itself born to con- 
tend! In its utmost refinement of work, it sought 
eminently for orderliness; carried the principle of 
the leeks in squares, and fountains in pipes, perfectly 
■out in its streets and temples; formalized whatever 
decoration it put into its minor architectural mould- 
ings, and reserved its whole heart and power to repre- 
sent the action of living men or gods, though not 
omconscious , meanwhile, of 

The sin^jple, the sincere deliglit ; 

The habitual scene of hill and dale ; 

The rural herds, the vernal gale ; 

The tangled vetches’ purple bloom ; 

The fragrance of the bean’s perfume, — .. 

Theirs, theirs alone, who cultivate the soil, 

And drink the cup of thirst, and eat the bread of toil. 



CHAP. XIV] OF MEDIEVAL LANDSCAPE 209 


CHAPTER XIV 

OP MEDIiEVAL LANDSCAPE *. FIRST, THE FIELDS 

§ 1. In our examination of the spirit of classical 
landscape, we were obliged to confine ourselves to 
what is left to us in written description. Some inter- 
esting results might indeed have been obtained by 
examining the Egyptian and Ninevite landscape 
sculpture, but in nowise conclusive enough to be 
worth the pains of the inquiry; for the landscape of 
sculpture is necessarily confined in range, and usually 
inexpressive of the complete feelings of the work- 
man, being introduced rather to explain the place and 
circumstances of events, than for its own sake. In 
the Middle Ages, however, the case is widely differ- 
ent. We have wTitten landscape, sculptured land- 
scape, and painted landscape, all bearing united 
testimony to the tone of the national mind in almost 
every remarkable locality of Europe. 

§ 2. That testimony, taken in its breadth, is very 
curiously conclusive. It marks the mediaeval mind 
as agreeing altogether with the ancients, in holding 
that flat land, brooks, and groves of aspens, compose 
the pleasant places of the earth, and that rooks and 
mountains are, for inhabitation, altogether to be 
reprobated and detested; but as disagreeing with 
the classical mind totally in this other m«>st import- 
ant respect, that the pleasant flat land is never a 
ploughed field, nor a rich lotus meadow good for 
pasture, but garden ground covered with flowers, and 
divided by fragrant hedges, with a castle in the 
middle of it. The aspens are delighied in, not be- 
cause they are good for ‘ coach-making men ’ to 
make cart-wheels of, but because they are shady 
and graceful; and the fruit-trees, covered with de- 
licious fruit, especially apple and orange, occupy 
still more important positions in the scenery. Sing- 
M. F., in. p 



210 OP MEDIEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

ing-birds — ^not ‘ sea-crows but nightingales ^ — perch 
on every bough ; and the ideal occupation of mankind 
is not to cultivate either the garden or the meadow, 
but to gather roses and eat oranges in the one, and 
ride out hawking over the other. 

Finally, mountain scenery, though considered as 
disagreeable for general inhabitation, is always intro- 
duced as being proper to meditate in, or to encourage 
communion with higher beings ; and in the ideal 
landscape of daily life, mountains are considered 
agreeable things enough, so that they be far enough 
away. 

§ 3. In this great change there are three vital points 
to be noticed. 

The first, the disdain of agricultural pursuits by 
the nobility; a fatal change, and one gradually 
bringing about the ruin of that nobility. It is ex- 
pressed in the medieeval landscape by the eminently 
pleasurable and horticultural character of everything; 
by the fences, hedges, castle walls, and masses of 
useless, but lovely flowers, especially roses. The 
knights and ladies are represented always as singing, 
or making love, in these pleasant places. The idea 
of setting an old knight, like Laertes (whatever his 
state of fallen fortune), ‘ with thick gloves on to keep 
his hands from the thorns *, to prune a row of vines, 
would have been regarded as the most monstrous 
violation of the decencies of life; and a senator, once 
detected in the home employments of Cincinnatus, 
could, I suppose, thenceforward hardly have appeared 
in society^ 

§ 4. The second vital point is the evidence of a 
more sentimental enjoyment of external nature. A 
Greek, wishing really to enjoy himself, shut himself 
into a beautiful atrium, with an excellent dinner, and 
a society of philosophical or musical friends. But a 
mediasval knight went into his pleasance, to gather 

1 The peculiar dislike felt by the medisevals for the sea^ is 
BO interesting a subject of inquiry, that I have reserved it for 
separate discussion in another work, in present preparation, 
H<trhour& df England (published in 1866). 



I. THE FIELDS 


211 


CHAP. XI V] 


roses and hear the birds sing; or rode out hunting 
or hawking. His evening feast, though riotous 
enough sometimes, was not the height of his day’s 
enjoyment'; and if the attractions of the world are 
to be shown typically to him, as opposed to the horrors 
of death, they are never represented by a full feast 
in a chamber, but by a delicate dessert in an orange 
grove, with musicians under the trees; or a ride 
on a May morning, hawk on fist. 

This change is evidently a healthy, and a very 
interesting one. 

§ 6. The third vital point is the^ marked sense that 
this hawking and apple-eating are not altogether 
right; that there is something else to be done in 
the world than that; and that the mountains, as 
opposed to the pleasant garden-ground, are places 
where that other something may best bo learned; 
which is evidently a piece of infinite and new respect 
for the mountains, and another healthy change in 
the tone of the human heart. 

Let us glance at the signs and various results of 
these changes, one by one. 

§ 6. The two first named, evil and good as they 
are, are very closely connected. The more poetical 
delight in external nature proceeds just from the 
fact that it is no longer looked upon with the eye 
of the farmer; and in proportion as the herbs and 
flowers cease to be regarded as useful, they are felt 
to be charming. Leeks are not now the most im- 
portant objects in the garden, but lilies and roses; 
the herbage which a Greek would have looked at 
only with a view to the number of horses it would 
feed, is regarded by the mediaeval knight as a green 
carpet for fair feet to dance upon, and the beauty 
of its softness and colour is proportionally felt by 
him; while the brook, which the Greek rejoiced to 
dismiss into a reservoir under the palace threshold, 
would be, by the mediaeval, distributed into pleasant 
pools, or forced into fountains; and regarded alter- 
nately as a mirror for fair faces, and a witchery to 
ensnare the sunbeams and the rainbow. 



212 OF MEDIEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

§ 7. And this change of feeling involves two others, 
very important. When the flowers and grass were 
regarded ,as means of life, and therefore (as the 
thoughtful labourer of the soil must always regard 
them) with the reverence due to those gifts of God 
which were most necessary to his existence ; although 
their own beauty was less felt, their proceeding from 
the Divine hand was more seriously acknowledged, 
and the herb yielding seed, and fruit-tree yielding 
fruit, though in themselves less admired, were yet 
solemnly connected in the heart with the reverence 
of Ceres, Pomona, or Pan. But when the sense of 
these necessary uses was more or less lost, among 
the upper classes, by the delegation of the art of 
husbandry to the hands of the peasant, the flower 
and fruit, whose bloom or richness thus became a 
mere source of pleasure, were regarded with less 
solemn sense of the Divine gift in them; and were 
converted rather into toys than treasures, chance 
gifts for gaiety, rather than promised rewards of 
labour; so that while the Greek could hardly have 
trodden the formal furrow, or plucked the clusters 
from the trellised vine, without reverent thoughts 
of the deities of field and leaf, who gave the seed 
to fructify, and the bloom to darken, the mediaeval 
knight plucked the violet to wreathe in his lady’s 
hair, or strewed the idle rose on the turf at her feet, 
with little sense of anything in the nature that 
gave them, but a frail, accidental, involuntary exu- 
berance ; while also the Jewish sacrificial system being 
now done .away, as well as the Pagan mythology, and, 
with it, tne whole conception of meat offering or 
firstfruits offering, the chiefest seriousnesses of all 
the thoughts connected with the gifts of nature 
faded from the minds of the classes of men concerned 
with art and literature; while the peasant, reduced 
to serf level, was incapable of imaginative thought, 
owing to his want of general cultivation. But on 
the other hand, exactly in proportion as the idea of 
definite spiritual presence in material nature was 
lost, the mysterious sense of unaccountable life in 



I. THE FIELDS 


213 


CHAP. XIV] 

the things themselves would be increased, and the 
mind would instantly be laid open to all those 
currents of fallacious, but pensive and pathetic 
sympathy, which we have seen to be characteristic 
of modern times. 

§ 8. Farther : a singular difference would neces- 
sarily result from the far greater loneliness of baronial 
life, deprived as it was of all interest in agricultural 
pursuits. The palace of a Greek leader in early 
times might have gardens, fields, and farms around 
it, but was sure to be near some busy city or sea- 
port : in later times, the city itself became the 
principal dwelling-place, and the country was visited 
only to see how the farm went on, or traversed in 
a line of march. Far other was the life of the 
mediaeval baron, nested on his solitary jut of crag; 
entering into cities only occasionally for some grave 
political or warrior’s purpose, and, for the most part, 
passing the years of his life in lion-like isolation; 
the village inhabited by his retainers straggling in- 
deed about the slopes of the rocks at his feet, but 
his own dwelling standing gloomily apart, between 
them and the uncompanionable clouds, commanding, 
from sunset to sunrise, the flowing flame of some 
calm unvoyaged river, and the ondless undulation 
of the untraversable Mils. How different must the 
thoughts about nature have been, of the noble who 
lived among the bright marble porticoes of the Greek 
groups of temple or palace — ^in the midst of a plain 
covered with corn and olives, and by the shore of a 
sparkling and freighted sea — ^from those ofHhe master 
of some mountain promontory in the green recesses 
of Northern Europe, watching night by night, from 
amongst his heaps of storm-broken stpne, rounded 
into towers, the lightning of the lonely sea flash 
round the sands of Harlech, or the mists changing 
their shapes for ever, among the changeless pines, 
that fringe the crests of Jura. 

§ 9. Nor was it without similar effect on the 
minds of men that their journeyings and pilgrimages 
became more frequent than those of the Greek, the 



214 OF MEDIAEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

extent of ground traversed in the course of them 
larger, and the mode of travel more oompanionless. 
To the Greek, a voyage to Egypt, or the Hellespont, 
was the subject of lasting fame and fable, and the 
forests of the Danube and the rocks of Sicily closed 
for him the gates of the intelligible world. What 
' parts of that norrow world he crossed were crossed 
with fleets or armies; the camp always populous 
on the plain, and the ships drawn in cautious sym- 
metry around the shore. But to the medieeval knight, 
from Scottish moor to Syrian sand, the world was 
one great exercise ground, or field of adventure; the 
staunch pacing of his charger penetrated the path- 
lessness of outmost forest, and sustained the sultri- 
ness of the most secret desert. Frequently alone— 
or, if accompanied, for the most part only by retainers 
of lower rank, incapable of entering into complete 
sympathy with any of his thoughts — ^lie must have 
been compelled often to enter into dim companion- 
ship with the silent nature around him, and must 
assuredly sometimes have talked to the wayside 
flowers of his love, and to the fading clouds of his 
ambition. 

§ 10. But, on the other hand, the idea of retire- 
ment from the world for the sake of self-mortifica- 
tion, of combat with demons, or communion with 
angels, and with their King — authoritatively com- 
mended as it was to all men by the continual practice 
of Christ Himself — gave to all mountain solitude at 
once a sanctity and a terror, in^the mediaeval mind, 
which werS altogether different from anything that 
it had possessed in the un-Christian periods. On the 
one side, there was an idea of sanctity attached to 
rocky wilderpiess, because it had always been among 
hills that the Deity _ had manifested Himself most 
intimately to men, and to the hills that His saints 
had nearly always retired for meditation, for especial 
communion with Him, and to prepare for death. 
Men acquainted with the history of Moses, alone at 
Horeb, or with Israel at Sinai — of Elijah by the 
brook Cherith, and in the Horeb cave; of the deaths 



CHAP. XIV] I. THE FIELDS 215 

of Moses and Aaron on Hor and Nebo; of the pre- 
paration of Jephthah’s daughter for her death among 
the Judea mountains; of the continual retirement 
of Christ Himself to the mountains for prayer, His 
temptation in the desert of the Dead Sea, His sermon 
on the hills of Capernaum, His transfiguration on 
the crest of Tabor, and His evening and morning 
walks over Olivet for the four or five days preceding 
His crucifixion — were not likely to look with irrever- 
ent or unloving eyes upon the blue hills that girded 
their golden horizon, or drew down upon them the 
mysterious clouds out of the height of the darker 
heaven. But with this impression of their greater 
sanctity was involved also that of a peculiar terror. 
In all this — their haunting by the memories of pro- 
phets, the presences of angels, and the everlasting 
thoughts and words of the Redeemer — the mountain 
ranges seemed separated from the active world, and 
only to be fitly approached by hearts which were 
condemnatory of it. Just in so much as it appeared 
necessary for the noblest men to retire to the hill- 
recesses before their missions could be accomplished, 
or their spirits perfected, in so far did the daily world 
seem by comparison to be pronounced profane and 
dangerous; and to those who loved that world, and 
its work, the mountains were thus voiceful with per- 
petual rebuke, and necessarily contemplated with a 
kind of pain and fear, such as a man engrossed by 
vanity feels at being by some accident forced to 
hear a startling sermon, or to assist at a funeral 
service. Every association of this kind was deepened 
by the practice and the precept of the •time; and 
thousands of hearts, which might otherwise have 
felt that there was loveliness in the wild landscape, 
shrank from it in dread, because they knew that the 
monk retired to it for penance, and the hermit for 
contemplation. The horror which the Greek had felt 
for hills only when they were uninhabited anjd 
barren, attached itself now to many of the sweetest 
spots of earth ; the feeling was conquered by political 
interests, but never by admiration; military ambition 



216 OF MEDIAEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

seized the frontier rock, or maintained itself in the 
uuftssailable pass; but it was only for their punish- 
ment, or in their despair, that men consented to 
tread the crocused slopes of the Chartreuse, or the 
soft glades and dewy pastures of Vailombrosa. 

§ 11. In all these modifications of temper and 
principle there appears much which tends to a pas- 
sionate, affectionate, or awe-struck observance of the 
features of natural scenery, closely resembling, in all 
but this superstitious dread of mountains, our feelings 
at the present day. But one character which the 
medisBvals had in common with the ancients, and 
that exactly the most eminent character in both, 
opposed itself steadily to all the feelings we have 
hitherto been examining, the admiration, namely, 
and constant watchfulness, of human beauty. Ex- 
ercised in nearly the same manner as the Greeks, 
from their youth upwards, their countenances were 
cast even in a higher mould ; for, although somewhat 
less regular in feature, and affected by minglings of 
Northern bluntness and stolidity of general expres- 
sion, together with greater thinness of lip and shaggy 
formlessness of brow, these less sculpturesque 
features were, nevertheless, touched with a serious- 
ness and refinement proceeding first from the modes 
of thought inculcated by the Christian religion, and 
secondly from their more romantic and various life. 
Hence a degree of personal beauty, both male and 
female, was attained in the Middle Ages, with which 
classical periods could show nothing for a moment 
comparable : and this beauty was set forth by the 
most perfect splendour, united with grace, in dress, 
which the human race have hitherto invented. The 
strength of their art-genius was directed in great 
part to this object; and their best workmen and 
most brilliant fanciers were employed in wreathing 
the mail or embroidering the robe. The exquisite 
arts of enamelling and chasing metal enabled them 
to make the armour as radiant and delicate as the 
plumage of a tropical bird; and the most various 
and vivid imaginations were displayed in the alter- 



I. THE FIELDS 


CHAP. XIV] 


217 


nations of colour, and fiery freaks of form, on shield 
and crest : so that of all the beautiful things whicH 
the eyes of men could fall upon, in the world about 
them, the most beautiful must have been a young 
knight riding out in morning sunshine, and in 
faithful hope : 


His broad, clear brow in sunlight glowed ; 
On burnished hooves his war-horse trode ; 
From underneath his helmet flowed 
His coal-black curls, as on he rode. 

All in the blue, unclouded weather, 

Thick jewelled shone the saddle leather ; 
The helmet and the helmet feather 
Burned like one burning flame together ; 
And the gemmy bridle glittered free, 

Like to some branch of stars we see 
Hung in the golden galaxy. 


§ 12. Now, the effect of this superb presence of 
human beauty on men in general was, exactly as 
it had been in Greek times, first, to turn their 
thoughts and glances in great part away from all 
other beauty but that, and to make the grass of the 
field take to them always more or less the aspect of 
a carpet to dance upon, a lawn to tilt upon, or a 
serviceable crop of hay; and, secondly, in what at- 
tention they paid to this lower nature, to make them 
dwell exclusively on what was graceful, symmetrical, 
and bright in colour. All that was rugged, rough, 
dark, wild, unterminated, they rejected at once, as 
the domain of ‘ salvage men ’ and monstrous giants : 
all that they admired was tender, brigljt, balanced, 
enclosed, symmetrical — only symmetrical in the 
noble aud free sense : for what we moderns call 
‘ symmetry or ‘ balance differs as much from 
mediseval symmetry as the poise of a grocer’s scales, 
or the balance of an Egyptian mummy with its hands 
tied to its sides, does from the balance of a knight 
on his horse, striking with the battle-axe, at the 
gallop; the mummy’s balance looking wonderfully 
perfect, and yet sure to be one-sided if you weigh 
the dust of it — the knight’s balance swaying and 



2|8 OF MEDIEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

changing like the wind, and yet as true and accurate 
as the laws of life. 

§ 18. And this love of symmetry was still farther 
enhanced by the peculiar duties required of art at 
the time; for, in order to fit a flower or leaf for 
inlaying in armour, or showing clearly in glass, it 
was absolutely necessary to take away its complexity, 
and reduce it to the condition of a disciplined and 
orderly pattern; and this the more, because, for all 
military purposes, the device, whatever it was, had 
to be distinctly intelligible at extreme distance. That 
it should be a good imitation of nature, when seen 
near, was of no moment; but it was of highest 
moment that when first the knight’s banner flashed 
in the sun at the turn of the mountain road, or rose, 
torn and bloody, through the drift of the battle dust, 
it should still be discernible what the bearing was ; 

At length, the freshening western blast 
Aside the shroud of battle cast ; 

And first the ridge of mingled spears 
Above the brightening cloud appears ; 

And in the smoke the pennons flew. 

As in the storm the white sea-mew ; 

Then marked they, dashing broad and far 
The broken billows of the war. 

Wide raged the battle on the plain ; 

Spears shook, and falchions flashed amain ; 

Fell England’s arrow-flight like rain ; 

Crests rose, and stooped, and rose again, 

Wild and disorderly. 

Amidst the scene of tumult, high, 

They saw Lord Marmionds falcpn fly, 

And stainless TunstalVs banner white ^ 

And Edmund Howard"^ s lion hriyht. 

It was needed, not merely that they should see 
it was a falcon, but Lord Marmion’s falcon; not only 
a lion, but the Howards’ lion. Hence, to the one 
imperative end of intelligihility , every minor resem- 
blance to nature was sacrificed, and above all, the 
curved^ which are chiefly the confusing lines; so 
that* the straight, elongated back, doubly elongated 
tail, projected and separate claws, and other recti- 



CHAP. XIV] I. THE FIELDS 21^ 

linear unnaturalnesses of form, became the means 
by which the leopard was, in midst of the mist and 
storm of battle, distinguished from the dog, or the 
lion from the wolf; the most admirable fierceness 
and vitality being, in spite of these necessary changes 
(so often shallowly sneered at by the modern work- 
man), obtained by the old designer. 

Farther, it was necessary to the brilliant harmony 
of colour, and clear setting forth of everything, that 
all confusing shadows^ all dim and doubtful lines 
should be rejected : hence at once an utter denial of 
natural appearances by the great body of workmen; 
and a calm rest in a practice of representation which 
would make either boar or lion blue, scarlet, or 
golden, according to the device of the knight, or the 
need of such and such a colour in that place of the 
pattern ; and which wholly denied that any substance 
ever cast a shadow, or was affected by any kind of 
obscurity. 

§ 14. All this was in its way, and for its end, 
absolutely right, admirable, and delightful; and those 
who despise it, laugh at it, or derive no pleasure from 
it, are utterly ignorant of the highest principles of 
art, and are mere tyros and beginners in the practice 
of colour. But, admirable though it might be, one 
necessary result of it was a farther withdrawal of 
the observation of men from the refined and subtle 
beauty of nature; so that the workman who first 
was led to think lightly of natural beauty, as 
being subservient to human, was next led to think 
inaccurately of natural beauty, because he had 
continually to alter and simplify it for nis practical 
purposes. 

§ 15. Now, asembling all these different sources of 
the peculiar mediaeval feeling towards nature in one 
view, we have : 

Ist. Love of the garden instead of love of the farm, 
leading to a sentimental contemplation of nature, 
instead of a practical and agricultural one (§§ 3, 
4, 6). 



m OF MEMtEVAL landscape [part IV 

2nd. Loss of sense of actual Divine presence, leading 
to fancies of fallacious animation, in herbs, 
flowers, clouds, &c. (§ 7). 

3rd. Perpetual, and more or less undisturbed, com- 
panionship with wild nature (§§ 8, 9). 

4th. Apprehension of demoniacal and angelic pre- 
sence among mountains, leading to a reverent 
dread of them (§ 10). 

5th. Priucipalness of delight in human beauty, lead- 
ing to comparative contempt of natural objects 
(§ 11 ). 

0th. Consequent love of order, light, intelligibility, 
and symmetry, leading to dislike of the wildness, 
darkness, and mystery of nature (§ 12). 

7th. Inaccuracy of observance of nature, induced by 
the habitual practice of change on its forms 

(§ 13 ). 

From these mingled elements, we should neces- 
sarily expect to find resulting, as the characteristic 
of mediaeval landscape art, compared with Greek, a 
far higher sentiment about it, and affection for it, 
more or less subdued by still greater respect for the 
loveliness of man, and therefore subordinated entirely 
to human interests; mingled with curious traces of 
terror, piety, or superstition, and cramped by various 
formalisms — some wise and necessary, some feeble, 
and some exhibiting needless ignorance and inac- 
curacy. 

Under these lights, let us examine the facts. 

§ 16. Thq, landscape of the Middle Ages is repre- 
sented in a central manner by the illuminations of 
the MSS of Romances, executed about the middle of 
the fifteenth century. On one side of these stands 
the earlier landscape work, more or less treated as 
simple decoration ; on the other, the later landscape 
work, becoming more or less affected with modern 
ideas and modes of imitation. 

These central fifteenth-century landscapes are 
almost invariably composed of a grove or two of tall 
trees, a winding river, and a castle, or a garden : 



I. THE FIELDS 


221 


CHAP. XIV] 

the peculiar feature of both these last being irimness ; 
the artist always dwelling especially on the fences; 
wreathing the espaliers indeed prettily with sweet- 
briar, and putting pots of orange-trees on the tops 
of the walls, but taking great care that there shall 
be no loose bricks in the one, nor broken stakes in 
the other — the trouble and ceaseless warfare of the 
times having rendered security one of the first ele- 
ments of pleasantness, and making it impossible for 
any artist to conceive Paradise but as surrounded by 
a moat, or to distinguish the road to it better than 
by its narrow wicket gate, and watchful porter. 

§ 17. One of these landscapes is thus described by 
Macaulay : ‘We have an exact square, enclosed by 
the rivers Pison, Gihon, Hiddekel, and Euphrates, 
each with a convenient bridge in the centre; rect- 
angular beds of flowers; a long canal neatly bricked 
and railed in; the tree of knowledge, clipped like 
one of the limes behind the Tuileries, standing in the 
centre of the grand alley; the snake turned round it, 
the man on the right hand, the woman on the left, 
and the beasts drawn up in an exact circle round 
them.’ 

All this is perfectly true: and seems in the de- 
scription very curiously foolish. The only curious 
folly, however, in the matter is the exquisite naivete 
of the historian, in supposing that the quaint land- 
scape indicates in the understanding of the painter 
so marvellous an inferiority to his own; whereas, it 
is altogether his own wit that is at fault, in not 
comprehending that nations, whose yovjfch had been 
decimated among the sands and serpents of Syria, 
knew probably nearly as much about Eastern scenery 
as youths trained in the schools of the modern Royal 
Academy; and that this curious symmetry was en- 
tirely symbolic, only more or less modified by the 
various instincts which I have traced above. Mr 
Macaulay is evidently quite unaware that the serpent 
with the human head, and body twisted round the 
tree, was the universally accepted symbol of the evil 
angel, from the dawn of art up to Michael Angelo; 



2^ OF MEDIiEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

that the greatest sacred artists invariably place the 
man on the one side of the tree, the woman on the 
other, in order to denote the enthroned and balanced 
dominion about to fall by temptation ; that the beasts 
are ranged (when they are so, though this is much 
more seldom the case) in a circle round them, ex- 
pressly to mark that they were then not wild, but 
obedient, intelligent, and orderly beasts; and that 
the four rivers are trenched and enclosed on the four 
sides, to mark that the waters which now wander in 
waste, and destroy in fury, had then for their prin- 
cipal office to ‘ water the garden ’ of God. The 
description is, however, sufficiently apposite and in- 
teresting, as bearing upon what I have noted respect- 
ing the eminent /cnce-loving spirit of the medicevals. 

§ 18. Together with this peculiar formality, we 
find ah infinite delight in drawing pleasant flowers, 
always articulating and outlining them completely; 
the sky is always blue, having only a few delicate 
white clouds in it, and in the distance are blue 
mountains, very far away, if the landscape is to be 
simply delightful; but brought near, and divided into 
quaint overhanging rocks, if it is intended to be 
meditative, or a place of saintly seclusion. But the 
whole of it always — flowers, castles, brooks, clouds, 
and rocks — subordinate to the human figures in the 
foreground, and painted for no other end than that 
of explaining their adventures and occupations. 

§ 19. Before the idea of landscape had been thus 
far developed, the representations of it had been 
purely typical; the objects which had to be sho’vvTi 
in order to ''explain the scene of the event, being 
firmly outlined, usually on a pure golden or chequered 
colour background, not on sky. The change from 
the golden background (characteristic of the finest 
thirteenth-century work) and the coloured chequer 
(which in like manner belongs to the finest four- 
teenth) to the blue sky, gradated to the horizon, 
takes place early in the fifteenth century, and is the 
crisis of change in the spirit of mediaeval art. Strictly 
speaking, we might divide the art of Christian times 



I. THE FIELDS 


CHAP. XIV] 


223 


into two great masses — Symbolic and Imitative; the 
symbolic, reaching from the earliest periods down 
to the close of the fourteenth century, and the imita- 
tive from that close, to the present time; and, then, 
the most important circumstance indicative of the 
culminating point, or turn of tide, would be this of 
the change from chequered background to sky back- 
ground. The uppermost figure in Plate VII, repre- 
senting the tree of knowledge, taken from a somewhat 
late thirteenth -century Hebrew manuscript (Addi^ 
tional 11,639) in the British Museum, will at once 
illustrate Mr Macaulay’s ‘ serpent turned round the 
tree ’, and the mode of introducing the chequer back- 
ground, and will enable the reader better to under- 
stand the peculiar feeling of the period, which no 
more intended the formal w’alls or streams for an 
imitative representation of the Garden of Eden, than 
these chequers for an imitation of sky. 

§ 20. The moment the sky is introduced (and it is 
curious how perfectly it is done at once, many manu- 
scripts presenting, in alternate pages, chequered back- 
grounds, and deep blue skies exquisitely gradated 
to the horizon) — the moment, I say, the sky is intro- 
duced, the spirit of art becomes for evermore changed, 
and thenceforward it gradually proposes imitation 
more and more as an end, until it reaches the 
Turnerian landscape. This broad division into two 
schools would therefore be the most true and accu- 
rate we could employ, but not the most convenient. 
For the great mediaeval art lies in a cluster about 
the culminating point, including symbolism on one 
side, and imitation on the other, and extending like 
a radiant cloud upon the mountain peak of ages, 
partly down both sides of it, from the year 1200 to 
1500; the brightest part of the cloud leaning a little 
backwards, and poising itself between 1250 and 1350. 
And therefore the most convenient arrangement is 
into Romanesque and barbaric art, up to 1200 — 
mediseval art, 1200 to 1500 — and modern art, from 
1500 downwards. But it is only in the earlier or 
symbolic mediaeval art, reaching up to the close of 



OF MEDIAEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

the fourteenth century, that the peculiar modification 
of natural forms for decorative purposes is seen 
in its perfection, with all its beauty, and all its neces- 
sary shortcomings; the minds of men being accu- 
rately balanced between that honour for the superior 
human form which they shared with the Greek ages, 
and the sentimental love of nature which was peculiar 
to their own. The expression of the two feelings will 
be found to vary according to the material and place 
of the art; in painting, the conventional forms are 
more adopted, in order to obtain definition, and 
brilliancy of colour, while in sculpture the life of 
nature is often rendered with a love and faithfulness 
which put modern art to shame. And in this earnest 
contemplation of the natural facts, united with an 
endeavour to simplify, for clear expression, the results 
of that contemplation, the ornamental artists arrived 
at two abstract conclusions about form, which are 
highly curious and interesting. 

§ 21. They saw, first, that a leaf might always be 
considered as a sudden expansion of the stem that 
bore it; an uncontrollable expression of delight, on 
the part of the twig, that spring had come, shown in 
a foimtain-like expatiation of its tender green heart 
into the air. They saw that in this violent proclama- 
tion of its delight and liberty, whereas the twig had, 
until that moment, a disposition only to grow quietly 
forwards, it expressed its satisfaction and extreme 
pleasure in sunshine by springing out to right 
and left. Let a 6, Fig. 1, Plate VIII, be the twig 
growing forward in the direction from a to b. It 
reaches the point b, and then — spring coming — not 
being able to contain itself, it bursts out in every 
direction, even springing backwards at first for joy; 
but as this backward direction is contrary to its own 
proper fate and nature, it cannot go on so long, and 
the length of each rib into which it separates is 
proportioned accurately to the degree in which the 
proceedings of that rib are in harmony with the 
natural destiny of the plant. Thus the rib c, entirely 
contradictory, by the direction of his life and energy. 



L THE FIELDS 


226 


CHAP. XIV] 

of the general intentions to the tree, is but a short- 
lived rib; d, not quite so opposite to his fate, lives 
longer; 6, accommodating himself still more to the 
spirit of progress, attains a greater length still; and 
the largest rib of all is the one who has not yielded 
at all to the erratic disposition of the others when 
spring came, but, feeling quite as happy about the 
spring as they did, nevertheless took no holiday, 
minded his business, and grew straightforward. 

§ 22. Fig. 6 in the same plate, which shows the 
disposition of the ribs in the leaf of an American 
Plane, exemplifies the principle very accurately : it 
is indeed more notably seen in this than in most 
leaves, because the ribs at the base have evidently 
had a little fraternal quarrel about their spring holi- 
day; and the more gaily -minded ones, getting to- 
gether into trios on each side, have rather pooh- 
poohed and laughed at the seventh brother in the 
middle, who wanted to go on regularly, and attend 
to his work. Nevertheless, though thus starting quite 
by himself in life, this seventh brother, quietly push- 
ing on in the right direction, lives longest, and makes 
the largest fortune, and the triple partnerships on 
the right and left meet with a very minor prosperity. 

§ 23. Now if we enclose Fig. ], in Plate VIII, witli 
two curves passing through the extremities of the 
ribs, we get Fig. 2, the central type of all leaves. 
Only this type is modified of course in a thousand 
ways by the life of the plant. If it be marsh or 
aquatic, instead of springing out in twigs, it is almost 
certain to expand in soft currents, as th^ liberated 
stream does at its mouth into the ocean. Fig. 3 
(Alisma Plantago) ; if it be meant for one of the 
crowned and lovely trees of the earth, it will separate 
into stars, and each ray of the leaf will form a ray 
of light in the crown. Fig. 5 (Horse-chestnut); and 
if it be a commonplace tree, rather prudent and 
practical than imaginative, it will not expand all 
at once, but throw out the ribs every now and then 
along the central rib, like a merchant taking his 
occasional and restricted holiday. Fig. 4 (Elm). 

M. P., III. Q 



m OF MEDIAEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

§ 24. Now in the bud, where all these proceed- 
ings on the leaf’s part are first imagined, the young 
leaf is generally (always?) doubled up in embryo, so 
as to present the profile of the half -leaves, as Fig. 7, 
only in exquisite complexity of arrangement; Fig. 9, 
for instance, is the profile of the leaf -bud of a rose. 
Hence the general arrangement of line represented 
by Fig. 8 (in which the lower line is slightly curved 
to express the bending life in the spine) is everlast- 
ingly typical of the expanding power of joyful vegeta- 
tive youth; and it is of all simple forms the most 
exquisitely delightful to the human mind. It pre- 
sents itself in a thousand different proportions and 
variations in the buds and profiles of leaves; those 
being always the loveliest in which, either by acci- 
dental perspetitive of position, or inherent character 
in the tree, it is most frequently presented to the 
eye. The branch of bramble, for instance, Fig. 10 
at the bottom of Plate VIII, owes its chief beauty 
to the perpetual recurrence of this typical form; and 
we shall find presently the enormous importance of 
it, even in mountain ranges, though, in these, falling 
force takes the place of vital force. 

§ 25. This abstract conclusion the great thirteenth 
century artists were the first to arrive at ; and 
whereas, before their time, ornament had been con- 
stantly refined into intricate and subdivided symme- 
tries, they were content with this simple form as 
the termination of its most important features. Fig. 3 
[Plate A] , which is a scroll out of a Psalter 
executed the latter half of the thirteenth century, 
is a sufficient example of a practice at that time 
absolutely universal. 

§ 26. The second great discovery of the Middle 
Ages in floral ornament, was that, in order completely 
to express the law of subordination among the leaf- 
ribs, two ribs were necessary, and no more^ on each 
side of the leaf, forming a series of three with the 
central one, because proportion is between three 
terms at least. 

That is to say, when they had only three ribs 




PLATE Vll. : Botany of 13th Century (Apple-tree and Cyclamen) 
M.P.,IIL] {face V. 226. 







M n/.\ 


Pla'jk VllJ : 'rnK (iKowrn of Leavks 


{face p. 'Z'2^ 



1. THE FIELDS 


227 


CHAP. XIV] 

altogether, as a, fig. 4 [Plate B] , no law of relation 
was discernible between the ribs, or the leaflets they 
bore ; but b}' the addition of a third on each side, as at 
b, proportion instantly was expressible, whether arith- 
metical or geometrical, or of any other kind. Hence 
the adoption of forms more or less approximating to 
that at c (young ivy), or d (wild geranium), as the 
favour! ce elements of their floral ornament, those 
leaves being, in their disposition of masses, the 
simplest which can express a perfect law of pro- 
portion, just as the outline Fig. 7, Plate VITI, is 
the simplest which can express a perfect law of 
growth. 

Plato IX gives, in rude outline, the arrangement of 
the border of one of the pages of a missal in my 
own possession, executed for tlie Countess Yolande 
of Flanders in the latter half of the fourteenth 
century, and furnishing, in exhaustless variety, the 
most graceful examples I have ever seen of the 
favourite decoration at the period, commonly now 
knowm as the ‘ Ivy -leaf ’ pattern. 

§ 27. In thus reducing these two everlasting laws 
of beauty to their simplest possible exponents, the 
mediaeval workmen were the first to discern and 
establish the principles of decorative art to the end 
of time, nor of decorative art merely, but of mass 
arrangement in general. For the members of any 
great composition, arranged about a centre, are 
always reducible to the law of the ivy-leaf, the best 
cathedral entrances having five porches correspond- 
ing in proportional purpose to its five l(^es (three 
being an imperfect, and seven a superfluous num- 
ber) ; while the loveliest groups of lines attainable in 
any pictorial composition are always based on the 
section of the leaf -bud. Fig. 7, Plate VIII, or on the 
relation of its ribs to the convex curve enclosing 
them. 

§ 28. These discoveries of ultimate truth are, I 
believe, never made philosophically, but instinctively; 

^ Married to Philip, younger son of the King of Navarre, in 
1352. She died in 139h 



228 OF MEDIAEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

so that wherever we find a high abstract result of 
the kind, we may be almost sure it has been the 
work of the penetrative imagination, acting under the 
influence of strong affection. Accordingly, when we 
enter on our botanical inquiries, I shall have occasion 
to show with what tender and loving fidelity to nature 
the masters of the thirteenth century always traced 
the leading lines of their decorations, either in missal- 
painting or sculpture, and how totally in this respect 
their methods of subduing, for the sake of distinct- 
ness, the natural forms they loved so dearly, differ 
from the iron formalisms to wdiich the Greeks, care- 
less of all that was not completely divine or com- 
pletely human, reduced the thorn of the acanthus, 
and softness of the lily. Nevertheless, in all this 
perfect and loving decorative art, we have hardly any 
careful references to other landscape features than 
herbs and flowers; mountains, water, and clouds 
are introduced so rudely, that the representations of 
them can never be received for anything else than 
letters or signs. Thus the sign of clouds, in the 
thirteenth century, is an undulating band, usually in 
painting, of blue edged with white, in sculpture, 
wrought so as to resemble very nearly the folds of a 
curtain closely tied, and understood for clouds only 
by its position, as surrounding angels or saints in 
heaven, opening to souls ascending at the Last Judg- 
ment, or forming canopies over the Saviour or the 
Virgin. Water is represented by zigzag lines, nearly 
resembling those employed for clouds, but distin- 
guished, i^ sculpture, by having fish in it; in paint- 
ing, both by fish and a more continuous blue or green 
colour. And when these unvaried symbols arc asso- 
ciated under the influence of that love of firm fence, 
moat, and every other means of definition which we 
have seen to be one of the prevailing characteristics 
of the mediaeval mind, it is not possible for us to 
conceive, through the rigidity of the signs employed, 
what were the real feelings of the workman or 
spectator about the natural landscape. We see that 
the thing carved or painted is not intended in any- 





CHAP. XIV] I. THE FIELDS 229 

wise to imitate the truth, or convey to us the feelines 
which the workman had in contemplating the truth. 
He has got a way of talking about it so definite and 
cold, and tells us with his chisel so calmly that the 
knight had a castle to attack, or the saint a river to 
cross dry-shod, without making the smallest effort 
to describe pictorially either castle or river, that we 
are left wholly at fault as to the nature of the 
emotion with which he contemplated the real objects. 
But that emotion, as the intermediate step between 
the feelings of the Grecian and the Modern, it must 
be our aim to ascertain as clearly as possible; and, 
therefore, finding it not at this period completely 
expressed in visible art, we must, as we did with 
the Greeks, take up the written landscape instead, 
and examine this mediaeval sentiment as we find it 
embodied in the poem of Dante. 

§ 29. The thing tnat must first strike us in this 
respect, as wo turn our thoughts to the poem, is, 
unquestionably, the formality of its landscape. 

Milton’s effort, in all that he tells us of his Inferno, 
is to make it indefinite; Dante’s, to make it definite. 
Both, indeed, describe it as entered through gates; 
but, within the gate, all is wild and fenceless with 
Milton, having indeed its four rivers — the last vestige 
of the mediaeval tradition — but rivers which flow 
through a waste of mountain and moorland, and 
by ‘ m^ny a frozen, many a fiery Alp ’. But Dante’s 
Inferno is accurately separated into circles drawn 
with well-pointed compasses; mapped and properly 
surveyed in every direction, trenched in a thoroughly 
good style of engineering from depth to depth, and 
divided in the ‘ accurate middle ’ (dritto mezzo) of 
its deepest abyss, into a concentric series of ten 
moats and embankments, like those about a castle, 
with bridges from each embankment to the next; 
precisely in the manner of those bridges over Hid- 
dekel and Euphrates, which Mr Macaulay thinks so 
innocently designed, apparently not aware that he is 
also laughing at Dante. These larger fosses are of 
rock, and the bridges also; but as he goes farther 



^0 OF MEDIAEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

into detail, Dante tells us of various minor fosses 
and embankments, in which he anxiously points out 
to us not only the formality, but the neatness and 
perfectness, of the stonework. For instance, in de- 
scribing the river Phlegethon, he tells us that it was 
‘paved with stone at the bottom, and at the sides, 
jind over the edges of the sides ’, just as the water is 
at the baths of Bulicame; and for fear we should 
think this embankment at all larger than it really 
was, Dante adds, carefully, that it was made just like 
the embankments of Ghent or Bruges against the 
sea, or those in Lombardy which bank the Brenta, 
only ‘ not so high, nor so wide ’, as any of these. 
And besides the trenches, we have two well-built 
castles; one, like Ecbatana, with seven circuits of 
wall (and surrounded by a fair stream), wherein the 
great poets and sages of antiquity live; and another, 
a great fortified city with walls of iron, red-hot, and 
a deep fosse round it, and full of ‘ grave citizens 
— the city of Dis. 

§ 30. Now, whether this be in what we moderns 
call ‘ good taste ’, or not, I do not mean just now 
to inquire — ^Dante having nothing to do with taste, 
but with the facts of what he had seen; only, so 
far as the imaginative faculty of the two poets is 
concerned, not that Milton’s vagueness is not the 
sign of imagination, but of its absence, so far as it 
is significative in the matter. For it does not follow, 
because Milton did not map out his Inferno as Dante 
did, that he could not have done so if he had chosen ; 
only, it was the easier and less imaginative process 
to leave it ^ague than to define it. Imagination is 
always the seeing and asserting faculty; that which 
obscures or conceals may be judgment, or feeling, 
but not invention. The invention, whether good or 
bad, is in the accurate' engineering, not in the fog 
and uncertainty. 

§ 31. When we pass with Dante from the Inferno 
to Purgatory, we have indeed more light and air, 
but no more liberty ; being now confined on various 
ledges cut into a mountain side, with a precipice on 



231 


CHAP, xiv] I. THE FIELDS 

one hand and a vertical wall on the other; and, 
lest here also we should make any mistake about, 
magnitudes, we are told that the ledges were* 
eighteen feet wide and that the ascent from one* 
to the other was by steps, made like those which go 
up from Florence to the church of San Miniato^. 

Lastly, though in the Paradise there is perfect 
freedom and infinity of space, though for trenches 
we have planets, and for cornices constellations, yet 
there is more cadence, procession, and order among 
the redeemed souls than any others; they fly, so as 
to describe letters and sentences in the air, and rest 
in circles, like rainbows, or determinate figures, as 
of a cross and an eagle ; in which certain of the more 
glorified natures are so arranged as to form the eye 
of the bird, while those most highly blessed are 
arranged with their white crowds in leaflets, so as 
to form the image of a white rose in the midst of 
heaven. 

§ 32. Thus, throughout the poem, I conceive that 
the first striking character of its scenery is intense 
definition ; precisely the reflection of that definiteness 
which we have already traced in pictorial art. But 
the second point which seems noteworthy is, that 
the flat ground and embanked trenches are reserved 
for the Inferno; and that the entire territory of the 
Purgatory is a mountain, thus marking the sense of 
that purifying and perfecting influence in mountains 
which we saw the mediseval mind was so ready to 
suggest. The same general idea is indicated at the 
very commencement of the poem, in which Dante is 
overwhelmed by fear and sorrow in pasting through 
a dark forest, but revives on seeing the sun touch 
the top of a hill, afterwards called by Virgil ‘ the 
pleasant mount — the cause and source of all delight.’ 

§ 33. While, however, we find this greater honour 
paid to mountains, I think we may perceive a much 
greater dread and dislike of woods. We saw that 
Homer seemed to attach a pleasant idea, for the 

^ ‘ Three times the length of the human body.’ — Purg. x, 24 

2 Fury, xii, 102. 



282 OF MEDIEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

most part, to forests; regarding them as sources of 
wealth and places of shelter; and we find constantly 
an idea of sacredness attached to them, as being 
haunted especially by the gods; so that even the 
wood which surrounds the house of Circe is spoken 
of as a sacred thicket, or rather, as a sacred glade, 
or labyrinth of glades (of the particular word used 
I shall have more to say presently); and so the 
wood is sought as a kindly shelter by Ulysses, in 
spite of its wild beasts; and evidently regarded with 
great affection by Sophocles, for, in a passage which 
is always regarded by readers of Greek tragedy with 
peculiar pleasure, the aged and blind OBidipus, 
brought to rest in ‘ the sweetest resting-place ’ in 
all the neighbourhood of Athens, has the spot de- 
scribed to him as haunted perpetually by nightin- 
gales, which sing ‘ in the green glades and in the 
dark ivy, and in the thousand-fruited, sunless, and 
windless thickets of the god ’ (Bacchus) ; the idea of 
the complete shelter from wind and sun being here, 
as with Ulysses, the uppermost one. After this come 
the usual staples of landscape, — narcissus, crocus, 
plenty of rain, olive trees; and last, and the greatest 
boast of all, — ‘ it is a good country for horses, and 
conveniently by the sea ’; but the prominence and 
pleasantness of the thick wood in the thoughts of 
the writer are very notable; whereas to Dante the 
idea of a forest is exceedingly repulsive, so that, as 
just noticed, in the opening of his poem, he cannot 
express a general despair about life more strongly 
than by saying he was lost in a wood so savage and 
terrible, tha^t ‘ even to think or speak of it is distress, 
— it was so bitter — it was something next door to 
death ’; and one of the saddest scenes in all the 
Inferno is in a forest, of which the trees are haunted 
by lost souls; while (with only one exception), when- 
ever the country is to be beautiful, we find ourselves 
coming out into open air and open meadows. 

It is quite true that this is partly a characteristic, 
not merely of Dante, or of medisBval writers, but of 
southern writers; for the simple reason that the 



I. THE FIELDS 


288 


CHAP. XIV] 

forest, being with them higher upon the hills, and 
more out of the way than in the north, was gener- 
ally a type of lonely and savage places; while in 
England, the ‘ greenwood coming up to the very 
walls of the towns, it was possible to be ‘ merry in 
the good greenwood in a sense which an Italian 
could not have understood. Hence Chaucer, Spenser, 
and Shakspeare send their favourites perpetually to 
the woods for pleasure or meditation; and trust their 
tender Canace, or Rosalind, or Helena, or Silvia, or 
Belphmbe, where Dante would have sent no one but 
a condemned spirit. Nevertheless, there is always 
traceable in the mediaeval mind a dread of thick 
foliage, which was not present to that of a Greek; 
so that, even in the north, we have our sorrowful 
" children in the wood ’, and black huntsmen of the 
Hartz forests, and such other wood terrors; the 
principal reason for the difference being that a Greek, 
being by no meaus given to travelling, regarded his 
woods as so much valuable property; and if he 
ever went into them for pleasure, expected to meet 
one or two gods in the course of his walk, but no 
banditti; while a mediaeval, much more of a solitary 
traveller, and expecting to meet with no gods in the 
thickets, but only with thieves, or a hostile ambush, 
or a bear, besides a great deal of troublesome ground 
for his horse, and a very serious chance, next to a 
certainty, of losing his way, naturally kept in the 
open ground as long as he could, and regarded the 
forests, in general, with anything but an eye of 
favour. 

§ 34. These, I think, are the principal points which 
must strike us, when we first broadly think of the 
poem as compared with classical work. Let us now 
go a little more into detail. 

As Homer gave us an ideal landscape, w^hich even 
a god might have been pleased to behold, so Dante 
gives us, fortunately, an ideal landscape, which is 
specially intended for the terrestrial paradise. And 
it will doubtless be with some surprise, after our 
reflections above on the general tone of Dante’s 



284 OF MEDIEVAL LANDSCAPE [paetiv 

feelings, that we find ourselves here first entering a 
forest, and that even a thick forest. But there is a 
peculiar meaning in this. With any other poet than 
Dante, it might have been regarded as a wanton in- 
consistency. Not so with him : by glancing back to 
the two lines which explain the nature of Paradise, 
we shall see what he means by it. Virgil tells him, 
as he enters it, ‘ Henceforward, take thine own plea- 
sure for guide; thou art beyond the steep ways, and 
beyond all Art — meaning, that the perfectly puri- 
fied and noble human creature, having no pleasure 
but in right, is past all effort, and past all rule. Art 
has no existence for such a being. Hence, the first 
aim of Dante, in his landscape imagery, is to show 
evidence of this perfect liberty, and of the purity and 
sinlessnesB of the new nature, converting pathless 
ways into happy ones. So that all those fences and 
formalisms which had been needed for him in imper- 
fection, are removed in this paradise; and even the 
pathlessness of the wood, the most dreadful thing 
possible to him in his days of sin and shortcoming, 
is now a joy to him in his days of purity. And as 
the fencelessness and thicket of sin led to the fet- 
tered and fearful order of eternal punishment, so the 
fencelessness and thicket of the free virtue lead to 
the loving and constellated order of eternal happi- 
ness. 

§ 35. This forest, then, is very like that of Colon os 
in several respects — in its peace and sweetness, and 
number of birds; it differs from it only in letting a 
light breeze through it, being therefore somewhat 
thinner than the Greek wood; the tender lines which 
tell of the voices of the birds mingling with the wind, 
and of the leaves all turning one way before it, have 
been more or less copied by every poet since Dante’s 
time. They are, so far as I know, the sweetest 
passage of wood description which exists in literature. 

Before, however, Dante has gone far in this wood 
— that is to say, only so far as to have lost sight 
of the place where he entered it, or rather, I sup- 
pose, of the light under the boughs of the outside 



235 


CHAP, xiv] I. THE FIELDS 

trees, and it must have been a very thin wood 
indeed if he did not do this in some quarter of a 
mile’s walk — he comes to a little river, three paces 
over, which bends the blades of grass to the left, 
with a meadow on the other side of it; and in this 
meadow 

A lady, graced with solitude, who went 
Singing, and setting flower by flower apart. 

By which the path she walked on was besprent 
‘ Ah, lady beautiful, that basking art 
In beams of love, if I may trust thy face, 

Which useth to bear witness of the heart. 

Let liking come on thee ', said I, ‘ to trace 
Thy path a little closer to the shore, 

AVhere I may reap the hearing of thy lays. 

Thou mindest me, how Proserpine of yore 

Appeared in such a place, what time her mother 
Lost her, and slie the spring, for evermore.’ 

As, pointing downwards and to one another 
Her feet, a ludy beudeth in the dance, 

And barely setteth one before the other, 

Thus, on the scarlet and the saffron glance 
Of flowers, with motion maid(in-like she bent 
(IL^r modest eyelids drooping and askance) ; 

And there she gave my wishes their content, 
Approaching, so that her sweet melodies 
Arrived upon mine ear with what tliey meant. 

When first she came amongst the blades, that rise, 
Already wetted, from the goodly river, 

She graced me by the lifting of her eyes. 

(Cayley.? 

§ 36. I have given this passage at length, because, 
for our purposes, it is by much the most important, 
not only in Dante, but in the whole circle^ of poetry. 
This lady, observe, stands on the opposite side of 
the little stream, which, presently, she explains to 
Dante is Lethe, having power to cause forgetfulness 
of all evil, and she stands just among the bent blades 
of grass at its edge. She is first seen gathering 
flower from flower, then ‘ passing continually the 
multitudinous flowers through her hands ’, smiling 
at the same time so brightly, that her first address 
to Dante is to prevent him from wondering at her, 



%m OF MEDIAEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

saying, ‘ if he will remember the verse of the ninety- 
second Psalm, beginning ‘ Delectastij he will know 
why she is so happy.* 

And turning to the verse of this Psalm we find it 
written, ‘ Thou, Lord, hast made me glad through 
Thy worhs, I will triumph in the works of Thy 
hands or, in the very words in which Dante would 
read it : 

Quia delectasti me, Domine, in factura tua, 

Et in operibua mauuuin Tuarum exultabo. 

§ 37. Now we could not for an instant have had 
any difficulty in understanding this, but that, some 
way farther on in the poem, this lady is called 
Matilda, and is with reason supposed by the com- 
mentators to be the great Countess Matilda of the 
eleventh century; not^able equally for her ceaseless 
activity, her brilliant political genius, her perfect 
piety, and her deep reverence for the see of Rome. 
This Countess Matilda is therefore Dante’s guide in 
the terrestrial paradise, as Beatrice is afterwards in 
the celestial; each of them having a spiritual and 
symbolic character in their glorified state, yet retain- 
ing their definite personality. 

The question is, then, what is the symbolic charac- 
ter of the Countess Matilda, as the guiding spirit of 
the terrestrial paradise? Before Dante had entered 
this paradise he had rested on a step of shelving rock, 
and as he watched the stars he slept, and dreamed, 
and thus tells us what he saw : 

A lady, young and beautiful, I dreamed. 

Was passing o’er a lea ; and, as i^he came, 

Methought I saw her ever and anon 
Bending to cull the flowers ; and thus she sang : 

‘ Know ye, whoever of my name would ask. 

That I am Leah ; for my brow to weave 
A garland, these fair hands unwearied ply ; 

To please me at the crystal mirror, here 
I deck me. But my sister Rachel, she 
Before her glass abides the livelong day, 

Her radiant eyes beholding, charmed no less 
Than I with this delightful task. Her joy 
In contemplation, as in labour mine.^ 



I. THE FIELDS 


237 


CHAP. XIV] 

This vision of Rachel and Leah has been always > 
and with unquestionable truth, received as a type 
of the Active and Contemplative life, and as an in- 
troduction to the two divisions of the paradise which 
Dante is about to enter. Therefore the unwearied 
spirit of the Countess Matilda is understood to 
represent the Active life, which forms the felicity of 
Earth; and the spirit of Beatrice the Contempla- 
tive life, which forms the felicity of Heaven. This 
interpretation appears at first straightforward and 
certain ; but it has missed count of exactly the most 
important fact in the two passages which we have to 
explain. Observe : Leah gathers the flowers to 
decorate herself, and delights in Her Own Labour. 
Rachel sits silent, contemplating herself, and delights 
in Her Own Image. Those are the types of the 
Unglorified Active and Contemplative powers of Man. 
But Beatrice and Matilda are the same powers, 
Glorified. And how are they Glorified? Leah took 
delight in her own labour; but Matilda — ' in operibus 
rnanuum Tuarum. ’ — in God's labour: Rachel in the 
sight of her own face; Beatrice in the sight of 
God's face. 

§ 38. And thus, when afterwards Dante sees 
Beatrice on her throne, and prays her that, when he 
himself shall die, she would receive him with kind- 
ness, Beatrice merely looks down for an instant, and 
answers with a single smile, then ‘ towards the 
eternal fountain turns.’ 

Therefore it is evident that Dante distinguishes in 
both cases, not between earth and heaven, but be- 
tween perfect and imperfect happiness, •whether in 
earth or heaven. The active life which has only the 
service of man for its end, and therefore gathers 
flowers, with Leah, for its own decoration, is indeed 
happy, but not perfectly so; it has only the happi- 
ness of the dream, belonging essentially to the dream 
of human life, and passing away with it. But the 
active life which labours for the more and more 
discovery of God’s work, is perfectly happy, and 
is the life of the terrestrial paradise, being a true 



m OF MEDI-EVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

foretaste of heaven, and beginning in earth, as 
heaven’s vestibule. So also the contemplative life 
which is concerned with human feeling and thought 
and beauty — the life which is in earthly poetry and 
imagery of noble earthly emotion — is happy, but it is 
the happiness of the dream; the contemplative life 
which has God’s person and love in Christ for its 
' object, has the happiness of eternity. But because 
this higher happiness is also begun here on earth, 
Beatrice descends to earth; and when revealed to 
Dante first, he sees the image of the twofold person- 
ality of Christ reflected in her eyes; as the flowers, 
which are, to the mediaeval heart, the chief work of 
God, are for ever passing through Matilda’s hands. 

§ 39. Now, therefore, we see that Dante, as the 
great prophetic exponent of the heart of the Middle 
Ages, has, by the lips of the spirit of Matilda, 
declared the mediasval faith, — that all perfect active 
life was * the expression of man’s delight in God's 
work' ; and that all their political and warlike energy, 
as fully shown in the mortal life of Matilda, was 
yet inferior and impure — ^the energy of the dream 
— compared with that which on the opposite bank of 
Lethe stood ‘ choosing flower from flower ’. And 
what joy and peace there were in this work is 
marked by Matilda’s being the person who draws 
Dante through the stream of Lethe, so as to make 
him forget all sin, and all sorrow: throwing her 
arms round him, she plunges his head under the 
waves of it; then draws him through, crying to 
him, ‘ hold me, hold me ’ (tiemmi, tiemmi), and so 
presents him, thus bathed, free' from all painful 
memory, at the feet of the spirit of the more heavenly 
contemplation. 

§ 40. The reader will, I think, now see, with 
sufficient distinctness, why I called this passage the 
most important, for our present purposes, in the 
whole circle of poetry. For it contains the first great 
confession of the discovery by the human race (I 
mean as a matter of experience, not of revelation), 
that their happiness was not in themselves, and that 



cflAP. xiv] I. THE FIELDS 239 

their labour was not to have their own service as 
its chief end. It embodies in a few syllables the 
sealing difference between the Greek and the me- 
diaeval, in that the former sought the flower and herb 
for his own uses, the latter for God’s honour; the 
former, primarily and on principle, contemplated his 
own beauty and the workings of his own mind, and 
the latter, primarily and on principle, contemplated 
Christ’s beauty and the workings of the mind of 
Christ. 

§ 41. I will not at present follow up this subject 
any farther; it being enough that we have thus got 
to the root of it, and have a great declaration of the 
central mediseval purpose, whereto we may return 
for solution of all future questions. I would only, 
therefore, dosire the reader now to compare The 
Stones of Venice ^ vol. i, chap, xx, §§ 15, 16; The 
Seven Lamps of Architecture, chap, iv, § 3; and 
the second volume of this work. Chap. II, §§ 9, 10, 
and Chap. Ill, § 10; that he may, in these several 
places, observe how gradually our conclusions are 
knitting themselves together as wo are able to deter- 
mine more and more, of the successive questions that 
come before us : and, finally, to compare the two 
interesting passages in Wordsworth, which, without 
any memory of Dante, nevertheless, as if by some 
special ordaining, describe in matters of modern life 
exactly the soothing or felicitous powers of the two 
active spirits of Dante — Leah and Matilda, Excur- 
sion, book V, line 608 to 625, and book vi, line 102 
to 214. 

§ 42. Having thus received from Dantd this great 
lesson, as to the spirit in which mediaeval landscape 
is to be understood, what else we have to note 
respecting it, as seen in his poem, will be com- 
paratively straightforward and easy. And first, we 
have to observe the place occupied in his mind by 
colour. It has already been shown, in the Stones of 
Venice, vol. ii, chap, v, §§ 30-34, that colour is the 
most sacred element of all visible things. Hence, 
as the mediaeval mind contemplated them first for 



S40 OF MEDIAEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

their sacredness, we should, beforehand, expect that 
the first thing it would seize would be the colour; 
and that w^e should find its expressions and render- 
ings of colour infinitely more loving and accurate 
than among the Greeks. 

§ 43. Accordingly, the Greek sense of colour seems 
to have been so comparatively dim and uncertain, 
that it is almost impossible to ascertain what the 
real idea was which they attached to any word allud- 
ing to hue : and above all, colour, though pleasant 
to their eyes, as to those of all human beings, seems 
never to have been impressive to their feelings. 
They liked purple, on the whole, the best; but there 
was no sense of cheerfulness or pleasantness in one 
colour, and gloom in another, such as the mediae vals 
had. 

For instance, when Achilles goes, in great anger 
and sorrow, to complain to Thetis of the scorn done 
him by Agamemnon, the sea appears to him ‘ wine- 
coloured ’. One might think this meant that the 
sea looked dark and reddish -purple to him, in a kind 
of sympathy with his anger. But we turn to the 
passage of Sophocles, which has been above quoted, 
— a passage peculiarly intended to express peace and 
rest-— and we find that the birds sing among ‘ wine- 
coloured ’ ivy. The uncertainty of conception of 
the hue itself, and entire absence of expressive 
character in the word, could hardly be more clearly 
manifested. 

§ 44. Again : I said the Greek liked purple, as a 
general source of enjoyment, better than any other 
colour. So he did; and so all healthy persons who 
have eye for colour, and are unprejudiced about it, 
do; and will to the end of time, for a reason presently 
to be noted. But so far was this instinctive prefer- 
ence for purple from giving, in the Greek mind, any 
consistently cheerful or sacred association to the 
colour, that Homer constantly calls death ‘ purple 
death ’. 

§ 45, Again : in the passage of Sophocles, so often 
spoken of, I said there was some difficulty respecting 



CHAP, xiv] I. THE FIELDS 241 

a word often translated * thickets I believe, my- 
self, it means glades; literally, ‘ going places ’ in tne 
woods — that is to say, places where, either naturally 
or by force, the trees separate, so as to give some 
accessible avenue. Now, Sophocles tells us the birds 
sang in these ‘ green going places ’ ; and we take up 
the expression gratefully, thinking the old Greek per- 
ceived and enjoyed, as wo do, the sweet fall of the 
eminently green light through the leaves when they 
are a little thinner- than in the heart of the wood. 
But we turn to the tragedy of Ajax, and are much 
sliaken in our conclusion about Ihe meaning of the 
word, when we are told that the body of Ajax is 
to lie unburied, and be eaten by sea-birds on the 
‘ green sand ’. The formation, geologically distin- 
guished by that title, was certainly not known to 
Sophocles; and the only conclusion which, it seems 
to me, we can come to under the circumstances, — 
assuming Ariel’s ^ authority as to the colour of pretty 
sand, and the ancient mariner’s (or, rather, his 
hearer’s 2) as to the colour of ugly sand, to be con- 
clusive — is that Sophocles really did not know green 
from yellow or brown. 

§ 46. Now, without going out of the terrestrial 
paradise, in which Dante last left us, we shall be 
able at once to compare with this Greek incertitude 
the precision of the mediseval eye for colour. Some 
three arrowfiights farther up into the wood we come 
to a tall tree, which is at first barren, but, after 
some little time, visibly opens into flowers, of a colour 
‘ less than that of roses, but more than that of 
violets ’. * 

It certainly would not be possible, in words, to 
come nearer to the definition of the exact hue which 
Dante meant — that of the apple-blossom. Had he 
employed any simple colour-phrase, as a ‘ pale pink ’, 
or ‘ violet-pink ’, or any other such combined ex- 

1 Come unto these yellow sands. 

2 And tbou art long, and lank, and brown^ 

As is the ribbed sea sand. 

M. p. , III. 


R 



U2 OF MEDIiEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

pression, he still could not have completely got at 
the delicacy of the hue ; he might perhaps have indi- 
cated its kind, but not its tenderness; but by taking 
the rose-leaf as the type of the delicate red, and 
then enfeebling this with the violet grey, he gets, as 
closely as language can carry him, to the complete 
rendering of the vision, though it is evidently felt 
by him to be in its perfect beauty ineffable; and 
rightly so felt, for of all lovely things which grace 
the spring time in our fair temperate zone, I am 
not sure but this blossoming of the apple-tree is the 
fairest. At all events, I find it associated in my 
mind with four other kinds of colour, certainly prin- 
cipal among the gifts of the northern earth, namely : 

1st. Bell gentians growing close together, mixed with 
lilies of the valley, on the Jura pastures. 

2nd. Alpine roses with dew upon them, under low 
rays of morning sunshine, touching the tops of 
the flowers. 

3rd, Bell heather in mass, in full light, at sunset. 
4th. White narcissus (red-contred) in mass, on the 
Vevay pastures, in sunshine after rain. 

And I know not where in the group to place the 
wreaths of apple-blossom, in the Vevay orchards, 
with the far-off blue of the lake of Geneva seen 
between the flow^ers. 

A Greek, however, would have regarded this 
blossom simply with the eyes of a Devonshire farmer, 
as bearing on the probable price of cider, and would 
have called it red, cerulean, purple, white, hyacin- 
thine, or generally ‘ aglaos agreeable, as happened 
to suit his verse. 

§ 47. Again ; we have seen how fond the Greek 
was of composing his paradises of rather damp grass; 
but that in this fondness for grass there was always 
an undercurrent of consideration for his horses; and 
the characters in it which pleased him most were its 
depth and freshness; not its colour. Now, if we 
remember carefully the general expressions, respect- 



I. THE FIELDS 


243 


CHA.P. XIV] 

ing grass, used in modern literature, I think nearly 
the commonest that occurs to us will be that of 
‘ enamelled ’ turf or sward. This phrase is usually 
employed by our pseudo-poets, like all their other 
phrases, without knowing what it means, because it 
has been used by other writers before them, and 
because they do not know what else to say of grass. 
If we were to ask them what enamel was, they could 
not ’tell us ; and if we asked why grass was like 
enamel, they could not tell us. . The expression has 
a meaning, however, and one peculiarly characteristic 
of mediteval and modern temper. 

§ 48. The first instance I know of its right use, 
though very probably it had been so employed be- 
fore, is in Dante. The righteous spirits of the pre- 
Christian ages are seen by him, though in the In- 
ferno, yet in a place open, luminous, and high, 
walking upon the ‘ green enamel '. 

I am very sure that Dante did not use this phrase 
as we use it. He knew well what enamel was; and 
his readers, in order to understand him thoroughly, 
must remember what it is — a vitreous paste, dis- 
solved in water, mixed with metallic oxides, to give 
it the opacity and the colour required, spread in a 
moist state on metal, and afterwards hardened by 
fire, so as never to change. And Dante means, in 
using this metaphor of the grass of the Inferno, to 
mark, that it is laid as a tempering and cooling sub- 
stance over the dark, metallic, gloomy ground; but 
yet so hardened by the fire, that it is not any more 
fresh or living grass, but a smooth, silent, lifeless 
bed of eternal green. And w^e know how hard 
Dante’s idea of it was; because afterwards, in what 
is perhaps the most awful passage of the whole In- 
ferno, when the three furies rise at the top of the 
burning tower, and catching sight of Dante, and not 
being able to get at him, shriek wildly for the Gorgon 
to come up too, that they may turn him into stone— 
the word stone is not hard enough for them. Stone 
might crumble away after it was made, or something 
with life might grow upon it; no, it shall not be 



iiU OF MEDIEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

stone; they will make enamel of him; nothing can 
grow out of that ; it is dead for ever 

Venga Medusa, si lo farem di Smalt o, 

§ 49. Now, almost in the opening of the Purgatory, 
as there at the entrance of the Inferno, we find a 
company of great ones resting in a grassy place. 
But the idea of the grass now is very different. The 
word now used is not ‘ enamel but ‘ herb and 
instead of being merely green, it is covered with 
flowers of many colours. With the usual mediasval 
accuracy, Dante insists on telling us precisely what 
these colours were, and how bright; which he does 
by naming the actual pigments used in illumination 
— ‘ Gold, and fine silver, and cochineal, and white 
lead, and Indian wood, serene and lucid, and fresh 
emerald, just broken, would have been excelled, as 
less is by greater, by the flowers and grass of the 
place. ’ It is evident that the ‘ emerald ’ here means 
the emerald green of the illuminators; for a fresh 
emerald is no brighter than one which is not fresh, 
and Dante w^as not one to throw away his words thus. 
Observe, then, we have here the idea of the growth, 
life, and variegation of the ‘ green herb as opposed 
to the smalto of the Inferno; but the colours of the 
variegation are illustrated and defined by the refer- 
ence to actual pigments : and, observe, because the 
other colours are rather bright, the blue ground 
(Indian wood, indigo?) is sober; lucid, but serene; 
and presently two angels enter, who are dressed in 
green drapery, but of a paler green than the grass, 
which Dante marks, by telling us that it was ‘ the 
green of leaves just budded.’ 

§ 60. In all this, I wish the reader to observe two 
things : first, the general carefulness of the poet in 
defining colour, distinguishing it precisely as a painter 
would (opposed to the Greek carelessness about it); 
and, secondly, his regarding the grass for its green- 
ness and variegation, rather than, as a Greek would 

1 Compare parallel passage, making Dante hard or change- 
less in good, rury. viii, 114. 



CHAP, xiv] I. THE FIELDS , 245 

have done, for its depth and freshness. This green- 
ness or brightness, and variegation, are taken up by 
later and modern poets, as the things intended to 
be chiefly expressed by the word ‘ enamelled and, 
gradually, the term is taken to indicate any kind of 
bright and interchangeable colouring ; there being 
always this much of propriety about it, when used 
of gieensward, that such sward is indeed, like enamel, 
a coat of bright colour on a comparatively dark 
ground; and is thus a sort of natural jewellery and 
painter’s work, different from loose and large veget- 
ation. The word is often awkwardly and falsely 
used, by the later poets, of all kinds of growth and 
colour ; as by Milton of the bowers of Paradise show- 
ing themselves over its wall; but it retains, never- 
theless, through all its jaded inanity, some half-un- 
conscious vestige of the old sense, even to the 
present day. 

§ 51. There arc, it seems to me, several important 
deductions to be made from these facts. The Greek, 
we have seen, delighted in the grass for its useful- 
ness; the mediaBval, as also we moderns, for its 
colour and beauty. But both dwell on it as the first 
element of the lovely landscape; we saw its use in 
Homer, wo see also that Dante thinks the righteous 
spirits of the heathen enough comforted in Hades 
by having even the iwage of green grass put beneath 
their feet; the happy resting-place in Purgatory has 
no other delight than its grass and flowers; and, 
finally, in the terrestrial paradise, the feet of Matilda 
pause where the Lethe stream first bends the blades 
of grass. Consider a little what a depth* there is in 
this groat instinct of the human race. Gather a 
single blade of grass, and examine for a minute, 
quietly, its narrow sword-shaped strip of fluted green. 
Nothing, as it seems there, of notable goodness or 
beauty. A very little strength, and a very little 
tallness, and a few delicate long lines meeting in a 
point — ^not a perfect point neither, but blunt and 
unfinished, by no means a creditable or apparently 
much cared for example of Nature’s workmanship; 



246 OF MEDIAEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

made, as it seems, only to be trodden on to-day, 
and to-morrow to be cast into the oven ; and a little 
pale and hollow stalk, feeble and flaccid, leading 
down to the dull brown fibres of roots. And yet, 
think of it well, and judge whether of all the gorgeous 
flowers that beam in summer air, and of all strong 
, and goodly trees, pleasant to the eyes or good for 
food — stately palm and pine, strong ash and oak, 
scented citron, burdened vine — there be any by man 
so deeply loved, by God so highly graced, as that 
narrow point of feeble green. It seems to me not to 
have been without a peculiar significance, that our 
Lord, when about to work the miracle which, of all 
that He showed, appears to have been felt by the 
multitude as the most impressive — the miracle of 
the loaves — commanded the people to sit down by 
companies * upon the green grass He was about 
to feed them with the principal produce of earth and 
the sea, the simplest representations of the food of 
mankind. He gave them the seed of the herb; He 
bade them sit down upon the herb itself, which was 
as great a gift, in its fitness for their joy and rest, 
as its perfect fruit, for their sustenance; thus, in 
this single order and act, when rightly understood, 
indicating for evermore how the Creator had en- 
trusted the comfort, consolation, and sustenance of 
man, to the simplest and most despised of all the 
leafy families of the earth. And well docs it fulfil 
its mission. Consider what we owe merely to the 
meadow grass, to the covering of the dark ground 
by that glorious enamel, by the companies of those 
soft, and co'Untless, and peaceful spears. The fields I 
Follow but forth for a little time the thoughts of 
all that we ought to recognize in those words. All 
spring and summer is in them, — ^the walks by silent, 
scented paths, — the rests in noonday heat, — the joy 
of herds and flocks, — the power of all shepherd life 
and meditation, — the life of sunlight upon the world, 
falling in emerald streaks, and failing in soft blue 
shadows, where else it would have struck upon the 
dark mould, or scorching dust, — ^pastures beside the 



I. THE FIELDS 


247 


CHAP. XI V] 

pacing brooks, — ^soft banks and knolls of lowly hills, 
— thymy slopes of down overlooked by the blue line 
of lifted sea, -—crisp lawns all dim with early dew, 
or smooth in evening warmth of barred sunshine, 
dinted by happy feet, and softening in their fall the 
sound of losing voices : all these are summed in 
those simple words; and these are not all. We may 
not measure to the full the depth of this heavenly 
gift, in our own land; though still, as we think of 
it longer, the infinite of that meadow sweetness, 
Shakspeare’s peculiar joy, would open on us more 
and more, yet we have it but iu part. Go out, in 
the spring time, among the meadows that slope from 
the shores of the Swiss lakes to the roots of their 
lower mountains. There, mingled with the taller 
gentians and the white narcissus, the grass grows 
deep and free; and as you follow the winding moun- 
tain paths, beneath arching boughs all veiled and 
dim with blossom — paths that for ever droop and 
rise over the green banks and mounds sweeping down 
in scented undulation, steep to the blue water, 
studded here and there with new-mown heaps, filling 
all the air with fainter sweetness, — look up towards 
the higher hills, where the waves of everlasting green 
roll silently into their long inlets among the shadows 
of the pines; and we may, perhaps, at last know the 
meaning of those quiet words of the 147th Psalm, 

‘ He maketh grass to grow upon the mountains.’ 

§ 52. There are also several lessons symbolically 
connected with this subject, which we must not allow 
to escape us. Observe, the peculiar characters of the 
grass, which adapt it especially for the •service of 
man, are its apparent humility^ and cheerfulness. 
Its humility, in that it seems created only for 
lowest service — appointed to be trodden on, and fed 
upon. Its cheerfulness, in that it seems to exult 
under all kinds of violence and sufiering. You roll 
it. and it is stronger the next day; you mow it, and 
it multiplies its shoots, as if it were grateful; you 
tread upon it, and it only sends up richer perfume. 
Spring comes, and it rejoices with all the earth — 



248 OF MEDIAEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

glowing with variegated flame of flowers — waving 
in soft depth of fruitful strength. Winter comes, 
and though it will not mock its fellow plants by 
growing then, it will not pine and mourn, and turn 
colourless or leafless as they. It is always green; 
and is only the brighter and gayer for the hoar-frost. 

§ 63. Now, these two characters — of humility, and 
joy under trial — are exactly those which most defin- 
itely distinguish the Christian from the Pagan 
spirit. Whatever virtue the pagan possessed was 
rooted in pride, and fruited with sorrow. It began 
in the elevation of his own nature; it ended but in 
the ‘ verde smalto ’ — the hopeless green — of the 
Elysian fields. But the Christian virtue is rooted in 
self -debasement, and strengthened under suffering by 
gladness of hope. And remembering this, it is 
curious to observe how utterly without gladness the 
Greek heart appears to be in watching the flowering 
grass, and what strange discords of expression arise 
sometimes in consequence. There is one, recurring 
once or twice in Homer, which has always pained 
me. He says, ‘ The Greek army was on the fields, 
as thick as flowers in the spring It might be so; 
but flowers in spring time are not the image by which 
Dante would have numbered soldiers on their path 
of battle. Dante could not have thought of the 
flowering of the grass but as associated with happi- 
ness. There is a still deeper significance in the 
passage quoted, a little while ago, from Homer, de- 
scribing Ulysses casting himself down on the rushes 
and the corn -giving land at the river shore — the 
rushes an& corn being to him only good for rest 
and sustenance — when we compare it with that in 
which Dante tells us he was ordered to descend to 
the shore of the lake as he entered Purgatory, to 
gather a rush, and gird himself with it, it being to 
him the emblem not only of rest, but of humility 
under chastisement, the rush (or reed) being the 
only plant which can grow there ; ‘ no plant which 
bears leaves, or hardens its bark, can live on that 
shore, because it does not yield to the chastisement 



I. THE FIELDS 


249 


CHAP. XIV] 

of its waves.’ It cannot but strike the reader sin- 
gularly how deep and harmonious a significance runs 
through all these words of Dante — how every syllable 
of them, the more we penetrate it, becomes a seed 
of farther uhoughtl For, follow up this image of 
the girding with the reed, under trial, and see to 
whose feet it will lead us. As the grass of the 
earth, thought of as the herb yielding seed, leads us 
to the place where our Lord commanded the multi- 
tude to sit down by companies upon the green grass; 
so the grass of the waters, thought of as sustaining 
itself among the waters of affliction, leads us to the 
place where a stem of it was put into our Lord’s 
hand for His sceptre; and in the crown of thorns, 
and the rod of reed, was foreshown the everlasting 
truth of the Christian ages — ^that all glory was to be 
begun in suffering, and all power in humility. 

Assembling the images we have traced, and adding 
the simplest of all, from Isaiah^ xl, 6, we find, the 
grass and flowers are types, in their passing, of the 
passing of human life, and, in their excellence, of the 
excellence of human life; and this in twofold way; 
first, by their Beneficence, and then, by their endur- 
ance : — the grass of the earth, in giving the seed of 
corn, and in its beauty under tread of foot and stroke 
of scythe; and the grass of the waters, in giving its 
freshness for our rest, and in its bending before the 
wave But understood in the broad human and 
Divine sense, the ‘ herb yielding seed ’ (as opposed 
to the fruit-tree yielding fruit) includes a third family 
of plants, and fulfils a third office to the human race. 
It includes the great family of the lintif and flaxes, 
and fulfils thus the three offices of giving food, 
raiment, and rest. Follow out this fulfilment; con- 
sider the association of the linen garment and the 
linen embroidery, with the priestly office, and the 
furniture of the tabernacle; and consider how the 
rush has been, in all time, the first natural carpet 

1 So also in Isa., xxxv, 7, the prevalence of righteousness 
and peace over all evil is thus foretold : * In the habitation of 
dragons, where each lay, shall be grass, with reeds and rushes.* 



260 OF MEDIJEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

thrown under the human foot. Then next observe the 
three virtues definitely set forth by the three families 
of plants ; not arbitrarily or fancifully associated 
with them, but in all the three cases marked for us 
by Scriptural words : ♦ 

1st. Cheerfulness, or joyful serenity; in the grass 
for food and beauty. ‘ Consider the lilies of the field, 
'how they grow; they toil not, neither do they spin.’ 

2nd. Humility ; in the grass for rest. ‘ A bruised 
reed shall He not break.’ 

3rd. Love; in the grass for clothing (because of 
its swift kindling). ‘ The smoking flax shall He not 
quench.’ 

And then, finally, observe the confirmation of these 
last two images in, I suppose, the most important 
prophecy, relating to the future state of the Christian 
Church, which occurs in the Old Testament, namely, 
that contained in the closing chapters of Ezekiel. 
The measures of the Temple of God are to be taken; 
and because it is only by charity and humility that 
those measures ever can be taken, the angel has ‘ a 
line of flax in his hand, and a measuring reed ’. The 
use of the line was to measure the land, and of the 
reed to take the dimensions of the buildings; so the 
buildings of the church, or its labours, are to be 
measured by humility, and its territory or land, by 
love. 

The limits of the Church have, indeed, in later 
days, been measured, to the world’s sorrow, by 
another kind of flaxen line, burning with the fire of 
unholy zeal, not with that of Christian charity; and 
perhaps the hest lesson which we can finally take to 
ourselves, in leaving these sweet fields of the mediae- 
val landscape, is the memory that, in spite of all 
the fettered habits of thought of his age, this great 
Dante, this inspired exponent of what lay deepest 
at the heart of the early Church, placed his terrestrial 
paradise where there had ceased to be fence or 
division, and where the grass of the earth was bowed 
down, in unity of direction, only by the soft waves 
that bore with them the forgetfulness of evil. 



CHAP. XV] 


II. THE BOOKS 


261 


CHAPTER XV 

OF MEDIAEVAL LANDSCAPE : SECONDLY, THE ROCKS 

§ 1. I CLOSED the last chapter, not because our 
subject was exhausted, but to give the reader breath- 
ing time, and because I supposed he would hardly 
care to turn back suddenly from the subjects of 
thought last suggested, to the less pregnant matters 
of inquiry connected with medijeval landscape. Nor 
was the pause mistimed even as respects the order 
of our subjects; for hitherto we have been arrested 
chiefly by the beauty of the pastures and fields, and 
have followed the mediaeval mind in its fond regard 
of leaf and flower. But now we have some hard 
hill-climbing to do; and the remainder of our in- 
vestigation must be carried on for the most part, on 
hands and knees, so that it is not ill done of us first 
to take breath. 

§ 2. It will be remembered that in the last chapter, 
§ 14, we supposed it probable that there would be 
considerable inaccuracies in the mediaeval mode of 
regarding nature. Hitherto, however, we have found 
none; but, on the contrary, intense accuracy, pre- 
cision, and affection. The reason of this is, that all 
floral and foliaged beauty might be perfectly repre- 
sented, as far as its form went, in the sculpture and 
ornamental painting of the period; hence the atten- 
tion of men was thoroughly awakened to that beauty. 
But as mountains and clouds and large ^features of 
natural scenery could not be accurately represented, 
we must be prepared to find them not so carefully 
contemplated — more carefully, indeed, than by the 
Greeks, but still in no wise as the things themselves 
deserve. 

§ 3. It was besides noticed that mountains, though 
regarded with reverence by the mediaeval, were also 
the subjects of a certain dislike and dread. And we 
have seen already that in fact the place of the soul’s 



OF MEDIAEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiV 

purification, though a mountain, is yet by Dante sub- 
dued, whenever there is any pleasantness to be found 
upon it, from all mountainous character into grassy 
recesses, or slopes to rushy shore; and, in his general 
conception of it, resembles much more a castle 
mound, surrounded by terraced walks, — in the 
-manner, for instance, of one of Turner’s favourite 
scenes, the bank under Richmond Castle (Yorkshire); 
or, still more, one of the hill slopes divided by 
terraces, above the Rhine, in which the pictures que- 
ness of the ground has been reduced to the form best 
calculated for the growing of costly wine, than any 
scene to which we moderns should naturally attach 
the term ‘ Mountaiuous On the other hand, al- 
though the Inferno is just as accurately measured 
and divided as the Purgatory, it is nevertheless cleft 
into rocky chasms which possess something of true 
mountain nature — nature which we modems of the 
north should most of us seek with delight, but which, 
to the great Florentine, appeared adapted only for the 
punishment of lost spirits, and which, on the mind 
of nearly all his countrymen, would to this day pro- 
duce a very closely correspondent effect; so that 
their graceful language, dying away on the north side 
of the Alps, gives its departing accents to proclaim 
its detestation of hardness and ruggedness; and is 
heard for the last time, as it bestows on the noblest 
defile in all the Grisons, if not in all the Alpine chain, 
the name of the ‘ evil way ’ — ‘ la Via Mala 

§ 4, This * evil way though much deeper and 
more sublime, corresponds closely in general character 
to Dante’s '•Evilpits just as the banks of Richmond 
do to his mountain of Purgatory; and it is notable 
that Turner has been led to illustrate, with his whole 
strength, the character of both; having founded, as 
it seems to me, his early dreams of mountain form 
altogether on the sweet banks of the Yorkshire 
streams, and rooted his hardier thoughts of it in the 
rugged clefts of the Via Mala. 

§ 5. Nor of the Via Mala only : a correspondent 
defile on the St Gothard — so terrible in one part of 



11. THE BOCKS 


2B3 


CHAP. XV] 

it, that it car), indeed, suggest no ideas but those of 
horror to minds either of northern or southern 
temper, and whose wild bridge, cast from rock to 
rock over a chasm as utterly hopeless and escapeless 
as any into which Dante gazed from the arches of 
Malebolge, has been, therefore, ascribed both by 
northern and southern lips to the master-building of 
the great spirit of evil — supplied to Turner the ele- 
ments of his most terrible thoughts in mountain 
vision, even to the close of his life. The noblest 
plate in the series of the Liber Studiorum one en- 
graved by his own hand, is of that bridge; the last 
mountain journey he ever took was up the defile; 
and a rocky bank and arch, in the last mountain 
drawing which he ever executed with his perfect 
power, are remembrances of the path by which he 
had travel sed in his youth this Malebolge of the St 
Gothard. 

§ 6. It is therefore with peculiar interest, as bear- 
ing on our own proper subject, that we must examine 
Dante’s conception of the rocks of the eighth circle. 
And first, as to general tone of colour : from what 
we have seen of the love of the mediseval for bright 
and variegated colour, we might guess that his chief 
cause of dislike to rocks would be, in Italy, their 
comparative colourlessness. With hardly an excep- 
tion, the range of the Apennines is composed of a 
stone of which some special account is given here- 
after in the chapters on Materials of Mountains, and 
of which one peculiarity, there noticed, is its mono- 
tony of hue. Our slates and granites are often of 
very lovely colours; but the Apennine*limestone is 
so grey and toneless, that I know not any mountain 
districts so utterly melancholy as those which are 
composed of this rock, when un wooded. Now, as 
far as I can discover from the internal evidence in 
his poem, nearly all Dante’s mountain wanderings 
had been upon this ground. He had journeyed once or 
twice among the Alps, indeed, but seems to have been 

1 It is an unpublished plate. I know only two impressions 
of it. 



1S4 OF MEDIAEVAL LANDSCAPE [partiv 

" - impressed chiefly by the road from Garda to Trent, 
and that along the Comiche, both of which are either 
upon these limestones, or a dark serpentine, which 
shows hardly any colour till it is polished. It is not 
ascertainable that he had ever seen rock scenery of 
the finely coloured kind, aided by the Alpine mosses : 

^ I do not know the fall at Forli (Inferno ^ xvi, 99), but 
every other scene to which he alludes is among these 
Apennine limestones; and when he wishes to give 
the idea of enormous mountain size, he names Taber- 
nicch and Pietra-pana — the one clearly chosen only 
for the sake of the last syllable of its name, in order 
to make a sound as of cracking ice, with the two 
sequent rhymes of the stanza — and the other is an 
Apennine neat- Lucca. 

§ 7. His idea, therefore, of rock colour, founded 
on these experiences, is that of a dull or ashen grey, 
more or less stained by the brown of iron ochre, pre- 
cisely as the Apennine limestones nearly always are; 
the, grey being peculiarly cold and disagreeable. As 
we go down the very hill which stretches out from 
Pictra-pana towards Lucca, the stones laid by the 
road side' to mend it arc of this ashen grey, with 
efflorescences of manganese and iron in the fissures. 
The whole of Malebolge is made of this rock, ‘ All 
wrought in stone of iron-coloured grain. 

Perhaps the iron colour may bq meant to predomin- 
ate in Evilpits; but the definite gr^ limestone colour 
is stated higher up, the river Styx flowing at the base 
of ‘ malignant grey clifls (the Word malignant be- 
ing given to the iron-coloured, Malebolge also) ; and 
the same whitish grey idea is given again definitely 
in describing the robe of the purgatorial or penance 
angel which is ‘ of the colour of ashes, or earth, dug 
dry Ashes necessarily mean r^ood-ashes in an 
Italian mind, so that we get the tone very pale; 
and there can be no doubt whatever about the hue 
meant, because it is constantly seen on the sunny 

1 (Cayley.) ‘Tutto di pietra, e di color ferrigno.* Inf. 
xviii, 2. 

2 ‘ Maligno piagge grige.* Ivf. vii, 108. 



CHAP. XV] IL THE ROCKS 255 

sides of the Italian hills, produced by the scorching 
of the ground, a dusty and lifeless Whitish grey, 
utterly painful and oppressive; and I have no doubt 
that this colour, assumed eminently also by lime- 
stone crags in the sun, is the quality wl^ch Homer 
means to express by a term he applies often to bare 
rooks, and which is usually translated * craggy or 
* rocky Now Homer is indeed quite capable of 
talking of ‘ rocky rocks just as he talks sometimes 
of ‘ wet water ’ ; but I think he means more by this 
word : it. sounds as if it were derived from another, 
meaning ‘ meal ’, or ‘ flour and I have little doubt 
it means ‘ mealy white ’ ; the Greek limestones being 
for the most part brighter in effect than the Apennine 
ones. 

§ 8. And the fact is, that the great and pre-eminent 
fault of southern, as compared with northern scenery, 
is this rock-whiteness, which gives to distant moun- 
tain ranges, lighted by the sun, sometimes a faint 
and monotonous glow, hardly detaching itself from 
the whiter parts of the sky, and sometimes a speckled 
confusion of white light with blue shadow, breaking 
up the whole mass of the hills, and making them look 
near and small; the whiteness being still distinct 
at the distance of twenty or twenty-five miles. The 
inferiority and meagreness of such effects of hill, com- 
pared with the massive purple and blue of our own 
heaps of crags and morass, or the solemn grass- 
greens and pine-purples of the Alps, have always 
struck me most painfully; and they have rendered 
it impossible for any poet or painter studying in the 
south, to enter with joy into hill scenerj?. Imagine 
the difference to Walter Scott, if instead of the single 
lovely colour which, named by itself alone, was 
enough to describe his hills. 

Their southern rapine to renew, 

Far in the distant Cheviot's hlne^ 

a dusty whiteness had been the image that first asso- 
ciated itself with a hill range, and he had been 
obliged, instead of ‘ blue * Cheviots, to say ‘ barley- 
meal-coloured * Cheviots. 



#6 OF MEDIAEVAL LAOTSCAPE [partiv 

§ 9. But although this ^ would cAlise a somewhat 
painful shock even to a modern minds it would be 
as nothing when compared with the pain occasioned 
by absence of colour to a mediaeval one. We have 
been trained, by our ingenious principles of Renais- 
sance architecture, to think that meal-colour and ash- 
colour are the properest colours of all;' and that the 
most aristocratic harmonies are to be deduced out 
of grey mortar and creamy stucco. Any of our 
modern classical architects would delightedly ‘ face ’ 
a heathery hill with Roman cement ; and any Italian 
sacristan would, but for the cost of it, at once white- 
wash the Cheviots. But the mediae vals had not 
arrived at these abstract principles of taste. They 
liked fresco better than whitewash; and, on the 
whole, thought that Nature was in the right in paint- 
ing her flowers yellow, pink, and blue; — not grey. 
Accordingly, this absence of colour from rocks, as 
compared with meadows and trees, was in their eyes 
an unredeemable defect; nor did it matter to them 
•whether its place was supplied by the grey neutral 
tint, or the iron-coloured stain; for both colours, 
grey and brown, were, to them, hues of distress, 
despair, and mortification, hence adopted always for 
the dresses of monks; only the word ‘ brown ’ bore, 
in their colour vocabulary, a still gloomier sense than 
with us. I was for some time embarrassed by 
Dante’s use of it with respect to dark skies and 
water. Thus, in describing a simple twilight — ^not a 
Hades twilight, but an ordinarily fair evening — 
(Inf, ii, 1) he says, the ‘ brown ’ air took the animals 
of earth a\ray from their fatigues; the waves under 
Charon’s boat are ‘ brown ’ (In/, hi, 117); and Lethe, 
which is perfectly clear and yet dark, as with oblivion, 
is ‘ bruna-bruna ‘ brown, exceedingly brown ’. Now, 
clearly in all these cases no warmth is meant to be 
mingled in the colour. Dante had never seen one 
of our bog-streams, with its porter-coloured foam; 
and there can be no doubt that, in calling Lethe 
brown, he means it was dark slate grey, inclining to 
black; as, for instance, our clear Cumberland lakes. 



CHAP. XV] ir. f HE BOCKS 867 

which, looked strai^t down upon where they are 
deep, seem to be lakes of ink. i am sure ihis is the 
colour he means; because no clear stream or lake 
on the Continent ever looks brown, but blue or green; 
and Dante, by merely taking away the pleasant 
colour, would §et at once to this idea of grave clear 
grey. So, when he was talking of twilight, his eye 
for colour was far too good to let him call it brown 
in our sense. Twilight is not brown, but purple, 
golden, or dark grey; and this last was what Dante 
meant. Farther, I find that this negation of colour 
is always the means by which Dante subdues his 
tones. Thus the fatal inscription on the Hades gate 
is written in ‘ obscure colour and the air which 
torments the passionate spirits is ‘ aer nero ’ black 
air (Inf. v, 61), called presently afterwards (line 81) 
malignant air, just as the grey cliffs are called malig- 
nant cliffs. 

§ 10. I was not, therefore, at a loss to find out what 
Dante meant by the word; but I was at a loss to 
account for his not, as it seemed, acknowledging the 
existence of the colour of brown at all; for if he 
called dark neutral tint * brown ’, it remained a 
question what term he would use for things of the 
colour of burnt umber. But, one day, just when I 
was puzzling myself about this, I happened to be* 
sitting by one of our best living modern colourists,, 
watching him at his work, when he said, suddenly,, 
and by mere accident, after we had been talking of 
other things, ‘ Do you know I have found that there 
is no brown in Nature? What we call brown is 
always a variety either of orange or purpl^. It never 
can be represented by umber, unless altered by 
contrast. ’ 

§ 11. It is curious how far the significance of this 
remark extends, how exquisitely it illustrates and 
confirms the mediesval sense of hue; how far, on 
the other hand, it cuts into the heart of the old 
umber idolatries of Sir George Beaumont and his 
colleagues, the ‘ where do you put your brown tree * 
system; the code of Cremona-violin-coloured fore- 



OF MEDIAEVAL LANDSCAPE [paeTiv 

grounds, of brown varnish and aSphaltum; and aU 
the old night-owl science, which, like Young’s pencil 
of sorrow, . 

In melancholy dipped, embrowns the whole. 

Nay, I do Young an injustice by associating his 
words with the asphalt schools ; for his eye for 
colour was true, and like Dante Js; and I doubt not 
that he means dark grey, as Byron purple- grey in 
that night piece of the Siege of Corinth, beginning 

’Tifi midnight ; on the mountains brown 

The cold, round moon looks deeply down ; 

and, by the way, Byron’s best piece of evening colour 
farther certifies the hues of Dante’s twilight, — ^it 

Dies like the dolphin, when it gasps away — 

The last still loveliest; till ’tis gone, and all is grep. 

§ 12. Let not, however, the reader confuse the 
use of brown, as an expression of a natural tint, with 
its use as a means of getting other tints. Brown is 
often an admirable ground, just because it is the only 
tint which is not to be in the finished picture, and 
because it is the best basis of many silver greys and 
purples, utterly opposite to it in their nature. But 
there is infinite difference between laying a brown 
ground as a representation of shadow — and as a base 
for light : and also an infinite difference between 
using brown shadows, associated with coloured lights 
— always the characteristic of false schools of colour, 
— and using brown as a warm neutral tint for general 
study. I shall have to pursue this subject farther 
hereafter, in noticing how brown is used by great 
colourists in their studies, not as colour, but as the 
pleasantest negation of colour, possessing more trans- 
parency than black, and having more pleasant and 
sunlike warmth. Hence Turner, in his early studies, 
used blue for distant neutral tint, and brown for fore- 
ground neutral tint; while, as he advanced in colour 
science, he gradually introduced, in the place of 
brown, strange purples, altogether peculiar to himself, 



259 


CHAP, xv] ” II. THE BOCKS 

founded, apparently, on Indian red and vermilion, 
and passing into various tones of russet and orange 
But, in the meantime, we must go back to Dante 
and his mountains. 

§ 13. We find, then, that his general type of rook 
colour was meant, whether pale or dark, to be a 
colourless grey — the most melancholy hue which he 
supposed to exist i» Nature (hence the synonym for 
it, subsisting even till late times, in medisBval appel- 
latives of dress, ‘ sad-coloured ’) — with some rusty 
stain from iron ; or perhaps the ‘ color ferrigno * of 
the Inferno does not involve even so much of orange, 
but ought to be translated ‘ iron grey 

This being his idea of the colour of rocks, we have 
next to observe his conception of their substance. 
And I believe it will be found that the character on 
which he fixes first in them is frangihility — breakable- 
ness to bits, as opposed to wood, which can be sawn 
or rent, but not shattered with a hammer, and to 
metal, which is tough and malleable. 

Thus, at the top of the abyss of the seventh circle, 
appointed for the ‘ violent \ or souls who had done 
evil by force, w’e are told, first, that the edge of it 
was composed of ‘ great broken stones in a circle 
then, that the place was ‘ Alpine and, becoming 
hereupon attentive, in order to hear what an Alpine 
place is like, we find that it was * like the place 
beyond Trent, where the rock, either by earthquake, 
or failure of support, has broken down to the plain, 
so that it gives any one at the top some means of 
getting down to the bottom.’ This is pot a very 
elevated or enthusiastic description of an Alpine 
scene; and it is far from mended by the following 
verses, in which we are told that Dante ‘ began to 
go down by this great unloading of stones ’, and that 

1 It is in these subtle purples that even the more elaborate 
passages of the earlier drawings are worked ; as, for instance, 
the Highland streams, spoken of in Pre-Raphaelitism. Also, 
Turner could, by opposition, get what colour he liked out of a 
brown. I have seen cases in which he had made it stand for 
the purest rose light. 



im OF MEDI^VAIi LANDSCAPE [partiv 

they moved often under his feet by reason of the new 
weight. The fact is that Dante, by many expres- 
sions throughout the poem, shows himself to have 
been a notably bad climber ; and being fond of sitting 
in the sun, looking at his fair Baptistery, or walking 
in a dignified manner on flat pavement in a long 
robe, it puts him seriously out of his way when he 
has to take to his hands and knees, or look to his feet ; 
so that the first strong impression made upon him 
by any Alpine scene whatever, is, clearly, that it is 
bad walking. When he is in a fright and hurry, and 
has a very steep place to go down, Virgil has to 
carry him altogether, and is obliged to encourage 
him, again and again, when they have a steep slope 
to go up — ^the first ascent of the purgatorial moun- 
tain. The similes by which he illustrates the steep- 
ness of that ascent are all taken from the Riviera of 
Genoa, now traversed by a good carriage road under 
the name of the Corniche; but as this road did not 
exist in Dante’s time, and the steep precipices and 
promontories were then probably traversed by foot- 
paths which, as they necessarily passed in many 
places over crumbling and slippery limestone, were 
doubtless not a little dangerous, and as in the 
manner they commanded the bays of sea below, and 
lay exposed to the full blaze of the south-eastern 
sun, they corresponded precisely to the situation of 
the path by which he ascends above the purgatorial 
sea, the image could not possibly have been taken 
from a better source for the fully conveying his idea 
to the reader ; nor, by the way, is there reason 
to discredit, in this place, his powers of climbing; 
for, with his usual accuracy, he has taken the angle 
of the path for us, saying it was considerably more 
than forty -five. Now a continuous mountain slope of 
forty -five degrees is already quite unsafe either for 
ascent or descent, except by zigzag paths; and a 
greater slope than this could not be climbed, straight- 
forward, but by help of crevices or jags in the rock, 
and great physical exertion besides. 

§ 14. Throughout these passages, however, Dante’s 



261 


CHAP. XV] II. THE BOCKS 

thoughts are clearly fixed altogether on the question 
of mere accessibility or inaccessibility. He does not 
show the smallest interest in the rocks, except as 
things to be conquered; and his description of their 
appearance is utterly meagre, involving no other 
epithets than * erto ’ (steep or upright), Inf. xix, 
131, Purg, iii, 48, &c.; ‘ sconcio * (monstrous), Inf. 
xix, 131; ‘ stagliata * (cut). Inf. xvii, 134; ‘ maligno ’ 
(malignant). Inf. vii, 108; ‘ duro ’ (hard), xx, 25; 
with ‘ large ’ and ‘ broken.’ (rotto) in various places. 
No idea of roundness, massiveness, or pleasant form 
of any kind appears for a moment to enter his mind ; 
and the different names which are given to the rocks 
in various places seem merely to refer to variations 
in size : thus a ‘ rocco ’ is part of a ‘ scoglio Inf. 
XX, 25 and xxvi, 27; a ‘ scheggio ’ (xxi, 60 and xxvi, 
17) is a less fragment yet; a ‘ petrone ’, or * sasso 
is a large stone or boulder (Purg. iv, 101, 104), and 
‘ pietra ’, a less stone — both of these last terms, espe- 
cially ‘ sasso being used for any largo mountainous 
mass, as in Purg. xxi, 106; and the vagueness of the 
word ‘ monte ’ itself, like that of the French ‘ mon- 
tagne applicable either to a hill on a post-road 
requiring the drag to be put on — or to the Mont 
Blanc, marks a peculiar carelessness in both nations, 
at the time of the formation of their languages, as to 
the sublimity of the higher hills; so that the effect 
produced on an English ear by the word ‘ mountain *, 
signifying always a mass of a certain large size, 
cannot be conveyed either in French or Italian. 

§ 15. In all these modes of regarding rocks we find 
(rocks being in themselves, as we shall 8ee presently, 
by no means monstrous or frightful things) exactly 
that inaccuracy in the mediteval mind which we had 
been led to expect, in its bearings on things contrary 
to the spirit of that symmetrical and perfect human- 
ity which had formed its ideal ; and it is very curious 
to observe how closely in the terms he uses, and the 
feelings they indicate, Dante here agrees with 
Homer. For the word stagliata (cut) corresponds 
very nearly to a favourite term of Homer’s respecting 



m OF MEDIEVAL LANDSCAPE [paetiv 

rocks * sculptured used by him also of ships* sides; 
and the frescoes and illuminations of the Middle Ages 
enable us to ascertain exactly what this idea of ‘ cut ’ 
rock was. 

§ 16. In Plate X I have assembled some ex- 
amples, which will give the reader a suflBcient know- 
* ledge of medieeval rock-drawing, by men whose names 
are known. They are chiefly taken from engravings, 
with which the reader has it in his power to compare 
them 1, and if, therefore,* any injustice is done to 
the original paintings the fault is not mine; but the 
general impression conveyed is quite accurate, and 
it would not have been worth while, where work is 
so deficient in first conception, to lose time in insuring 
accuracy of facsimile. Some of the crap may be 
taller here, or broader there, than in the original 
paintings; but the character of the work is perfectly 
preserved, and that is all .with which we are at 
present concerned. 

Fip. 1 and 6 are by Ghirlandajo; 2 by Filippo 
Pesellino ; 4 by Leonardo da Vinci ; and 6 by Andrea 
del Castagno. All these are indeed workmen of a 
much later period than Dante, but the system of 
rock-drawing remains entirely unchanged from 
Giotto’s time to Ghirlandajo ’s; is then altered only 
by an introduction of stratification indicative of a 
little closer observance of nature, and so remains 
until Titian’s time. Fig. 1 is exactly representative of 
one of Giotto’s rocks, though actually by Ghirlandajo-, 
and Fig. 2 is rather less skilful than Giotto’s ordinary 
work. Both these figures indicate precisely what 
Homer and Dante meant by ‘ cut ’ rocks. They had 
observed the concave smoothness of certain rock 
fractures as eminently distinctive of rook from earth, 
and use the term ‘ cut * or ‘ sculptured ’ to distinguish 
the smooth surface from the knotty or sandy one, 
having observed nothing more respecting its real 
contours than is represented in Figs, 1 and 2, which 
look as if they had been hewn out with an adze. 


^ The references are in Appendix I. 





CHAP. XV] II. THE ROCKS 263 

u 

Lorenao Ghiberti preserves the same type, even in 
his finest work. 

Fig. 3, from an interesting sixteenth century MS 
in the British Museum (Cotton, Augustus, a, 6j, is 
characteristic of the best later illuminators’ work; 
and Fig. 6, from Ghirlandajo, is pretty illustrative of 
Dante’s idea of terraces on the purgatorial mountain. 
It is the road by which the Magi descend in his 
picture of their Adoration, in the Academy of Flor- 
ence. Of the other examples I shall have more to 
say in the chapter on Precipices ; meanwhile we have 
to return to the landscape of the poem. 

§ 17. Inaccurate as this conception of rock was, 
it seems to have been the only one which, in mediae- 
val art, had place as representative of mountain 
scenery. To Dante, mountains are inconceivable ex- 
cept as great broken stones or crags; all their broad 
contours and undulations seem to have escaped his 
eye. It is, indeed, with his usual undertone of 
symbolic meaning that he describes the great broken 
stones, and the fall of the shattered mountain, as 
the entrance to the circle appointed for the punish- 
ment of the violent; meaning that the violent and 
cruel, notwithstanding all their iron hardness of heart, 
have no true strength, but, either by earthquake, or 
want of support, fall at last into desolate ruin, naked, 
loose, apd shaking under the tread. But in no part 
of the poem do we find allusion to mountains in 
any other than a stern light; nor the slightest evi- 
dence that Dante cared to look at them. From that 
hill of San Miniato, whose steps he knew so well, the 
eye commands, at the farther extremitj^ of the Val 
d'Arno, the whole purple range of the mountains of 
Carrara, peaked and mighty, seen always against the 
sunset light in silent outline, the chief forms that 
rule the scene as twilight fades away. By this vision 
Dante seems to have been wholly unmoved, and, 
but for Lucan’s mention of Aruns at Luna, would 
seemingly not have spoken of the Cfj,rrara hills in 
the whole course of his poem : when he does allude 
to them, he speaks of their white marble, and their 



264 OF MEDIiEVAL LANDSCAPE [part iv 

command of stars and sea, but has evidently no regard 
for the hills themselves. There is not a single phrase 
or syllable throughout the poem which indicates such 
a regard. Ugolino, in his dream, seemed to himself 
to be in the mountains, ‘ by cause of which the 
Pisan cannot see Lucca ’ ; and it is impossible to look 
up from Pisa to that hoary slope without remember- 
ing the awe that there is in the passage; neverthe- 
less, it was as a hunting-ground only that he remem- 
bered those hills. Adam of Brescia, tormented with 
eternal thirst, remembers the hills of Romena, but 
only for the sake of their sweet waters : 

The rills that glitter down the grassy slopes 
Of Oasentino, making fresh and soft 
The banks whereby they glide to Arno’s stream, 
Stand ever in my view. 

And, whenever hills are spoken of as having any 
influence on character, the repugnance to them is 
still manifest; they are always causes of rudeness 
or cruelty : 

But that ungrateful and malignant race, 

AYho in old times came down from Fesole, 

At/y and still smack of their rough mountain Jlintf 
Will, for thy good deeds, show thee enmity. 

Take heed thou cleanse thee of their ways. 

So again : 

As one mount ain-bred^ 

Rugged, and clownish, if some city’s walls 
He chance to enter, round him stares agape. 

§ 18. Finally, although the Carrara mountains are 
named as having command of the stars and sea, the 
Alps are never specially mentioned but in bad 
weather, or snow. On the sand of the circle of the 
blasphemers : 

Fell slowly wafting down 
Dilated flakes of fire, as flakes of snow 
On Alpine summit, when the wind is hushed. 

So the Paduans have to defend their town and castles 
against inundation, 

Ere the genial warmth be felt. 

On Chiarentana’s top. 



II. THE BOCKS 


CHAP. XV] 


265 


The clouds of anger, in Purgatory, can only be figured 
to the reader who has 

On an Alpine height been ta’en by cloud, 

Through which thou sawest no better than the mole 
Doth through opacous membrane. 

And in approaching the second branch of Lethe, the 
seven ladies pause. 

Arriving at the verge 
Of a dim umbrage hoar, such as is seen 
Beneath green leaves and gloomy branches oft 
To overbrow a bleak and Alpine cliff. 

§ 19. Truly, it is unfair of Dante, that when he is 
going to use snow for a lovely image, and speak of 
it as melting away under heavenly sunshine, he 
must needs put it on the Apennines, not on the 
Alps : 

As snow that lies . 

Amidst the living rafters, on the back 
Of Italy, congealed, when drifted high 
And closely piled by rough Sclavonian blasts, 

Breathe but the land whereon no shadow falls, 

And straightway, melting, it distils away, 
liike a fire- wasted taper ; thus was I, 

Without a sigh, or tear, consumed in heart. 

The reader will thank me for reminding him, 
though out of its proper order, of the exquisite passage 
of Scott which we have to compare with this : 

As snow upon the mountain’s hreast 
Slides from the rock that gave it rest, 

Sweet Ellen glided from her stay, 

And at the monarch’s feet she lay. 

Examine fihe context of this last passage, and its' 
beauty is quite beyond praise; but note the northern 
love of rocks in the very first words I have to quote 
from Scott, ‘ The rocks that gave it rest ’. Dante could 
not have thought of his ‘ cut rocks ’ as giving rest 
even to snow. He must put it on the pine branches, 
if it is to be at peace. 

§ 20. There is only one more point to be noticed 
in the Dantesque landscape; namely, the feeling 
entertained by the poet towards the sky. And the 



266 OF MEDIiEVAL LANDSCAPE [eartiv 

love of mountains is so closely connected with the 
love of clouds, the sublimity of both depending much 
on their association, that, having found Dante regard- 
less of the Carrara mountains as seen from San 
Miniato, we may well expect to find him equally re- 
gardless of the clouds in which the sun sank behind 
them. Accordingly, we find that his only pleasure 
in the sky depends on its ‘ white clearness ’, — that 
turning into ‘ bianca aspetto di cilestro ’ which is so 
peculiarly characteristic of fine days in Italy. His 
pieces of pure pale light are always exquisite. In 
the dawn on the purgatorial mountain, first, in its 
pale white, he sees the ‘ tremola della marina ’ — 
trembling of the sea; then it becomes vermilion; and 
at last, nearaunrise, orange. These are precisely the 
changes of a calm and perfect dawn. The scenery of 
Paradise begins with ‘ Day added to day the light 
of the sun so flooding the heavens, that ‘ never rain 
nor river made lake so wide ’ ; and throughout the 
Paradise all the beauty depends on spheres of light, 
or stars, never on clouds. But the pit of the Inferno 
is at first sight obscure, deep, and so cloudy that at 
its bottom nothing could be seen. When Dante and 
Virgil reach the marsh in which the souls of those 
who have been angry and sad in their lives are for 
ever plunged, they find it covered with thick fog; 
and the condemned souls say to them. 

We ouce were sad, 

lu the sweet air, made gladsome hy the sun. 

Now in these murky settlings are we sad. 

Even the angel crossing the marsh to help them is 
‘^annoyed by this bitter marsh smoke, ‘ fummo 
acerbo and continually sweeps it with his hand 
from before his face. 

Anger on the purgatorial mountain, is in like 
manner imaged, because of its blindness and wild- 
ness, by the Alpine clouds. As they emerge from 
its mist they see the white light radiated through the 
fading folds of it; and, except this appointed cloud, 
no other can touch the mountain of purification : 



CHAP. XV] 


II. THE ROCfilS 


267 


Tempest none, shower, hail, or snow. 
Hoar-frost, or dewy moistness, higher falls, 

Than that byief scale of threefold steps. Thick clouds, 
Nor scudding rack, are ever seen, swift glance 
Ne’er lightens, nor Thaumantian iris gleams. 

Dwell for a little while on this intense love of 
Dante for light — taught, as he is at last by Beatrice, 
to gaze on the sun itself like an eagle — and endeav- 
our to enter into his equally intense detestation of 
all mist, rack of cloud, or dimness of rain; and 
then consider with what kind of temper he would 
have regarded a landscape of Copley Fielding’s, or 
passed a day in the Highlands. He has, in fact, 
assigned to the souls of the gluttonous no other 
punishment in the Inferno than perpetuity of High- 
land weather : 

Show ers 

Ceaseless, accursed, heavy and cold, unchanged 
For ever, both in kind and in degree. 

Large hail, discoloured water, sleety flaw, 

Through the dim midnight air streamed down amain. 

§ 21, However, in this immitigable dislike of 
clouds, Dante goes somewhat beyond the general 
temper of his age. For although the calm sky was 
alone loved, and storm and rain were dreaded by all 
men, yet the white horizontal clouds of serene 
summer were regarded with great affection by all 
early painters, and considered as one of the accom- 
paniments of the manifestation of spiritual power; 
sometimes, for theological reasons which we shall 
soon have to examine, being received, evefi without 
any other sign, as the types of blessing or Divine 
acceptance; and in almost every representation of 
the heavenly paradise, these level clouds are set by 
the early painters for its floor, or for thrones of its 
angels; whereas Dante retains steadily, through 
circle after circle, his cloudless thought, and con- 
cludes his painting of heaven, as he began it, upon 
the purgatorial rhountain, with the image of shadow- 
less morning ; 



268 OF MEDIEVAL LANDSCAPE [part iv 

I raised my eyes, and as at morn is seen 
The horizon’s eastern quarter to excel, 

So likewise, that pacific Oriflamb 

Glowed in the midmost, and toward every part, 

With like gradation paled away its flame. 

But the best way of regarding this feeling of 
Dante’s is as the ultimate and most intense expres- 
sion of the love of light, colour, and clearness, which, 
as we saw above, distinguished the mediaeval from 
the Greek on one side, and, as we shall presently 
see, distinguished him from the modern on the other. 
For it is evident that precisely in the degree in which 
the Greek was agriculturally inclined, in that de- 
gree the sight of clouds would become to him more 
acceptable than to the mediaeval knight, who only 
looked for the fine afternoons in which he might 
gather the flowers in his garden, and in no wise 
shared or imagined the previous anxieties of his 
gardener. Thus, when we find Ulysses comforted 
about Ithaca, by being told it had ‘ plenty of rain 
and the maids of Colonos boasting of their country 
for the same reason, wo may be sure that they had 
same regard for clouds; and accordingly, except 
Aristophanes, of whom more presently, all the Greek 
poets speak fondly of the clouds, and consider them 
the fitting resting-places of the gods; including in 
their idea of clouds not merely the thin clear cirrus, 
but the rolling and changing volume of the thunder- 
cloud ; nor even these only, but also the dusty whirl- 
wind cloud of the earth, as in that noble chapter of 
Herodotus which tells us of the cloud, full of mystic 
voices, that rose out of the dust of Eleusis, and went 
down to Salamis. Clouds and rain were of course 
regarded with a like gratitude by the eastern and 
southern nations — Jews and Egyptians; and it is 
only among the northern medieevals, with whom fine 
weather was rarely so prolonged as to occasion pain- 
ful drought, or dangerous famine, and over whom 
the clouds broke coldly and fiercely when they came, 
that the love of serene light assumes its intense 
character, and the fear of tempest its gloomiest; so 



II. THE ROCKS 


269 


CHAP. XV] 


that the powers of the clouds which to the Greek 
foretold his conquest at, Salamis, and with whom 
he fought in alliance, side by side with their light- 
nings, under the crest of Parnassus, seemed, in the 
heart of the Middle Ages, to be only under the 
dominion of the spirit of evil. I have reserved, for 
our last example of the landscape of Dante, the 
passage in which this conviction ' is expressed; a 
passage not less notable for its close description of 
what the writer feared and disliked, than for the 
ineffable tenderness, in which Dante is always raised 
as much above all other poets, as in softness the 
rose above all other flowers. It is the spirit of 
Buonconte da Montefeltro who speaks : 


Then said another; ‘ Ah, so may thy wish, 

That takes thee o’er the mountain, be fulfilled, 

As thou shalt graciously give aid to mine ! 

Of Montefeltro I ; Buonconte I ; 

Giovanna, nor none else, have care for me ; 

Sorrowing with these I therefore go.’ I thus ; 

‘ From Campaldino’s field what force or chance 
Drew thee, that ne’er thy sepulture was known ? ’ 

‘ Oh ! ’ answered he, ‘ at Oasentino’s foot 
A stream there courseth, named Archiano, sprung 
In Apeunine, above the hermit’s seat. 

E’en where its i\amo is cancelled, there came I, 

Pierced in the throat, fleeing away on foot, 

And bloodying the plain. Here sight and speech 
Failed me ; and finishing with Mary’s name, 

I fell, and tenantless my flesh remained. . . . 

That evil will, which in his intellect 
Still follows evil, came ; . . . 

the valley, soon 

As day was spent, he covered o^er with cloudy 
From Pratomagno to the mountain range, 

And stretched tiie sky above ; so that the air. 

Impregnate, changed to water. Fell the rain ; 

And to the fosses came all that the land 
Contained not ; and, as mightiest streams are wont, 

To the great river, with such headlong sweep, 

Rushed, that nought stayed its course. My stiffened frame, 
Laid at his mouth, the fell Archiano found, 

And dashed it into Arno ; from my breast 
Ijoosening the cross, that of myself I made 



270 : OF MEDIEVAL LANDSCAPE [part iv 

"When overcome with pain. He hurled me on, 

Along the banks and bottom of his course ; 

Then in his muddy spoils encircling wrapt.’ 

Observe, Buonconte, as he dies, crosses his arms 
over his breast, pressing them together, partly in his 
pain, partly in prayer. His body thus lies by. the 
river shore, as on a sepulchral monument, the arms 
folded into a cross. The rage of the river, under 
the influence of the evil demon, unlooses this cross ^ 
dashing the body supinely away, and rolling it over 
and over by bank and bottom. Nothing can be truer 
to the action of a stream in fury than these lines. 
And how desolate is it all I The lonely flight — ^the 
grisly wound, ‘ pierced in the throat * — the death, 
without help or pity — only the name of Ma^ on the 
lips — and the cross folded over the heart. Then the 
rage of the demon and the river — the noseless grave, 
— and, at last, even she who had been most trusted 
forgetting him, 

Giovanna, nor none else, have care for me. 

There is, I feel assured, nothing else like it in all 
the range of poetry; a faint and harsh echo of it, 
only, exists in one Scottish ballad, * The Twa 
Corbies 

Here, then, I think, we may close our inquiry into 
the nature of the mediaeval landscape; not but that 
many details yet require to be worked out; but 
these will be best observed by recurrence to them, 
for comparison with similar details in modern land- 
scape — our principal purpose, the getting at the 
governing tones and temper of conception, being, I 
believe, now sufficiently accomplished. And I think 
that our subject may be best pursued by immediately 
turning from the mediseval to the perfectly modern 
landscape ; for although I have much to say respect- 
ing the transitional state of mind exhibited in the 
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, I believe the 
transitions may be more easily explained after we 
have got clear sight of the extremes; and that by 
getting perfect and separate hold of the three great 



cHAP.xvi] OF MODERN LANDSCAPE 271 

phases of art, — Greek, mediaeval, and modern — we 
shall be enabled to trace, with least chance of error, 
those curioue vacillations which brought us to the 
modern temper while vainly endeavouring to resus- 
citate the Greek. I propose, therefore, in the next 
chapter, to examine the spirit of modern landscape, 
as seen generally in modern painting, and especially 
in the poetry of Scott. 


CHAPTER XVI 

OF MODERN LANDSCAPE 

§ 1. We turn our eyes, therefore, as boldly and as 
quickly as may be, from these serene fields and 
skies of mediaeval art, to the most characteristic ex- 
amples of rhodern landscape. And, I believe, the 
first thing that will strike us, or that ought to strike 
us, is their cloudiness. 

Out of perfect light and motionless air, we find 
ourselves on a sudden brought under sombre skies, 
and into drifting wind; and, with fickle sunbeams 
flashing in our face, or utterly drenched with sweep 
of rain, we are reduced to track the changes of the 
shadows on the grass, or watch the rents of twilight 
through angry cloud. And we find that whereas all 
the pleasure of the mediaeval was in stability, de- 
finiteness, and luminousness, we are expected to 
rejoice in darkness, and triumph in mutability; to 
lay the foundation of happiness in things which mo- 
mentarily change or fade; and to expect Uie utmost 
satisfaction and instruction from what it is imposs- 
ible to arrest, and difficult to comprehend. 

§ 2. We find, however, together with this general 
delight in breeze and darkness, much attention to 
the real form of clouds, and careful drawing of 
effects of mist; so that the appearance of objects, 
as seen through it, becomes a subject of science with 
us; and the faithful representation of that appear- 
ance is made of primal importance, under the name 



172 OF MODERN LANDSCAPE [paetiv 

of a§rial perspective* The aspects of sunset and 
sunrise, with all their attendant phenomena of cloud 
and mist, are watchfully delineated; and in ordinary 
daylight landscape, the sky is considered of so much 
importance, that a principal mass of foliage, or a 
whole foreground, is unhesitatingly thrown into shade 
merely to bring out the form of a white cloud. So 
that, if a general and characteristic name were needed 
for modern landscape art, none better could be in- 
vented than ‘ the service of clouds.’ 

§ 3. And this name would, unfortunately, be 
characteristic of our art in more ways than one. 
In the last chapter, I said that all the Greeks spoke 
kindly about the clouds, except Aristophanes; and 
he, I am sorry to say (since his report is so un- 
favourable) is the only Greek who had studied them 
attentively. He tells us, first, that they are ‘ great 
goddesses to idle men ’; then, that they are ‘ mis- 
tresses of disputings, and logic, and monstrosities, 
and noisy chattering ’; declares that whoso believes 
in their divinity must first disbelieve in Jupiter, and 
place supreme power in the hands of an unknown 
p[od ‘ Whirlwind ’ ; and, finally, he displays their 
influence over the mind of one of their disciples, in 
his sudden desire ‘ to speak ingeniously concerning 
smoke 

There is, I fear, an infinite truth in this Aristo- 
phanic judgment applied to our. modern cloud - 
worship. Assuredly, much of the love of mystery in 
our romances, our poetry, our art, and, above all, 
in our metaphysics, must come under that definition 
so long ergo given by the great Greek, ‘ speaking 
ingeniously concerning smoke And much of the in- 
stinct, which, partially developed in painting, may 
be now seen throughout every mode of exertion of 
mind, -—the’ easily encouraged doubt, easily excited 
curiosity, habitual agitation, and delight in the 
changing and the marvellous, as opposed to the old 
quiet serenity of social custom and religious faith, — is 
again deeply defined in those few words, the ‘ dethron- 
ing of Jupiter ’, the ‘ coronation of the whirlwind.’ 



278 


CHAP. XVI] OF MOf)EfiN LANDSCAPE 

§ 4. Nor of whirlwind merely, but also of dark- 
ness or ignorance respecting all stable facts. That 
darkening of the foreground to bring out the white 
clouds, is, in one aspect of it, a type of the subjec- 
tion of all plain and positive fact, to what is uncer- 
tain and unintelligible. And as we examine farther 
into the matter, we shall be struck by another great 
difference between the old and modern landscape, 
narhely, that in the old no one ever thought of draw- 
ing anything but as well as he could. That might 
not be well, as we have seen in the case of rocks; but 
is was as well as he could, and always distinctly. 
Leaf, or stone, or animal, or man, it was equally drawn 
with care and clearness, and its essential characters 
shown. If it was an oak tree, the acorns were 
drawn; if a flint pebble, its veins wore drawn; if 
an arm of the sea, its fish were drawn; if a group 
of figures, their faces and dresses were drawn — to 
the very last subtlety of expression and end of thread 
that could be got into the space, far off or near. 
But now our ingenuity is all ‘ concerning smoke ’. 
Nothing is truly drawn but that; all else is vague, 
slight, imperfect; got with as little pains as possible. 
You examine your closest foreground, and find no 
leaves; your largest oak, and find no acorns; your 
human figure, and find a spot of red paint instead 
of a face; and in all this, again and again, the 
Aristophanic words come true, and the clouds seem 
to be ‘ great goddesses to idle men.’ 

§ 5. The next thing that will strike us, after this 
love of clouds, is the love of liberty. "V^hereas the 
mediaeval was always shutting himself into castles, 
and behind fosses, and drawing brickwork neatly, 
and beds of flowers primly, our painters delight in 
getting to the open fields and moors ; abhor all hedges 
and moats ; never paint anything but free-growing 
trees, and rivers gliding ‘ at their own sweet will ’; 
eschew formality down to the smallest detail; break 
and displace the brickwork which the mediaeval would 
have carefully cemented ; leave unpruned the thickets 
he would have delicately trimmed; and, carrying the 

M. P.,111. T 



)^:04t OF MODERN LANDBCAFE [paetiv 

love of liberty even to license, and the love of wild- 
ness even to ruin, take pleasure at last in every aspect 
of age and desolation which emancipates the objects of 
nature from the got-emment of men; — on the castle 
wall displacing its tapestry with ivy, and spreading, 
^ through the garden, the bramble for the rose. 

§ 6. Connected with this love of liberty we find 
a singular manifestation of love of mountains, and 
see our painters traversing the wildest places of the 
globe in order to obtain subjects with craggy fore- 
grounds and purple distances. Some few of them 
remain content with pollards and flat land ; but these 
are always men of third-rate order; and the leading 
masters, while they do not reject the beauty of the 
low grounds, reserve their highest powers to paint 
Alpine peaks or Italian promontories. And it is 
eminently noticeable, also, that this pleasure in the 
mountains is never mingled with fear, or tempered 
by a spirit of meditation, as with the mediaeval; but 
is always free and fearless, brightly exhilarating, 
and wholly unreflectivo : so that the painter feels 
that his mountain foreground may be more consist- 
ently animated by a sportsman than a hermit; and 
our modern society in general goes to the mountains, 
not to fast, but to feast, and leaves their glaciers 
covered with chicken-bones and egg-shells. 

§ 7. Connected with this want of any sense of 
solemnity in mountain scenery, is a general profanity 
of temper in regarding all the rest of nature; that 
is to say, a total absence of faith in the presence 
of any deity therein. Whereas the mediaeval never 
painted a cloud, but with the purpose of placing an 
angel in it; and a Greek never entered a wood with- 
out expecting to meet a god in it; we should think 
the appearance of an angel in the cloud wholly un- 
natural, and should be seriously surprised by meet- 
ing a god anywhere. Our chief ideas about the wood 
are connected with poaching. We have no belief that 
the clouds contain more than so many inches of rain 
or hail, and from our ponds and ditches expect no- 
thing more divine than ducks and watercresses. 



275 


osAP.xvi] 6F modern LANDSCAPE 

§ 8. Finally : connected with this profanity of 
temper is a strong tendency to deny the sacred 
element of colour, and make our boast in blackness. 
For though occasionally glaring, or violent, modern 
colour is on the whole eminently sombre, tending 
continually to grey or brown, and by many of our 
best painters consistently falsified, with a confessed 
pride in what they call chaste or subdued tints; so 
that, whereas a mediaeval paints his sky bright blue, 
and his foreground bright green, gilds the towers of 
his castles, and clothes his figures with purple and 
white, we paint our sky grey, our foreground black, 
and our foliage brown, and think that enough is 
sacrificed to the sun in admitting the dangerous 
brightness of a scarlet cloak or a blue jacket. 

§ 9. These, I believe, are the principal points 
which would strike us instantly, if we were to be 
brought suddenly into an exhibition of modem land- 
scapes out of a room filled with mediaeval work. It 
is evident that there are both evil and good in this 
change; but how much evil, or how much good, we 
can only estimate by considering, as in the former 
divisions of our inquiry, what are the real roots of 
the habits of mind which have caused them. 

And first, it is evident that the title ‘ Dark Ages ’, 
given to the mediaeval centuries, is, respecting art, 
wholly inapplicable. They were, on the contrary, 
the bright ages; ours are the dark ones. I do not 
mean metaphysically, but literally. They were the 
ages of gold; ours are the ages of umber. 

This is partly mere mistake in us; we build 
brown brick walls, and wear brown coats, because we 
have been blunderingly taught to do so, and go on 
doing so mechanically. There is, however, also some 
cause for the change in our own tempers. On the 
whole, these are much sadder ages than the early 
ones; not sadder in a noble and deep way, but 
in a dim, wearied way — the way of ennui, and jaded 
intellect, and uncomfortableness of soul and body. 
The Middle Ages had their wars and agonies, but also 
intense delights. Their gold was dashed with blood; 



2?i« OF MODERN LANDSCAPE [paetiv 

but ours is sprinkled with dust. Their life was in- 
woven with white and purple ; ours is one seamless 
stuff of brown. Not that we are without apparent 
festivity, but festivity more or less forced, mistaken, 
embittered, incomplete — ^not of the heart. How 
wonderfully, since Shakspeare’s time, have we lost 
the power of laughing at bad jests I The very finish 
of our wit belies our gaiety. 

§ 10. The profoundest reason of this darkness of 
heart is, I believe, our want of faith. There never 
yet was a generation of men (savage or civilized) 
who, taken as a body, so wofully fulfilled the words, 

‘ having no hope, and without God in the world ’, 
as the present civilized European race. A Red 
Indian or Otaheitan savage has more sense of a 
Divine existence round him, or government over 
him, than the plurality of refined Londoners and 
Parisians; and those among us who may in some 
sense be said to believe, are divided almost without 
exception into two broad classes, Romanist and Puri- 
tan; who, but for the interference of the unbelieving 
portions of society, would, either of them, reduce the 
other sect as speedily as possible to ashes; the 
Romanist having always done so whenever he could, 
from the beginning of their separation, and the 
Puritan at this time holding himself in complacent 
expectation of the destruction of Rome by volcanic 
fire. Such division as this between persons nomin- 
ally of one religion, that is to say, believing in the 
same God, and the same Revelation, cannot but be- 
come a stumbling-block of the gravest kind to all 
thoughtful* and far-sighted men — a stumbling-block 
which they can only surmount under the most favour- 
able circumstances of early education. Hence, nearly 
all our powerful men in this age of the world are 
unbelievers; the best of them in doubt and misery; 
the worst in reckless defiance; the plurality, in plod- 
ding hesitation, doing, as well as they can, what 
practical work lies ready to their hands. Most of 
our scientific men are in this last class; our popular 
authors either set themselves definitely against all 



277 


cHAP.xvi] OF MODERN LANDSCAPE 

religious form, pleading for simple truth and benevo- 
lence, (Thackeray, Dickens), or give themselves up to 
bitter and fruitless statement of facts, (De Balzac), 
or surface-painting, (Scott), or careless blasphemy, 
sad or smiling, (Byron, Beranger). Our earnest 
poets, and deepest thinkers, are doubtful and indig- 
nant, (Tennyson, Carlyle); one or two, anchored, 
indeed, but anxious, or weeping, (Wordsworth, Mrs. 
Browning) ; and of these two, the first is not so sure 
of his anchor, but that now and then It drags with 
him, even to make him cry out, 

Great God, I had rather be 
A Pagan suckled in some creed outworn ; 

So might I, standing on this pleasant lOa, 

Have glimpses that would make me less forlorn. 

In politics, religion is now a name; in art, a 
hypocrisy or affectation. Over German religious pic- 
tures the inscription, ‘ See how Pious I am can be 
read at a glance by any clear-sighted person. Over 
French and English religious pictures, the inscrip- 
tion, ‘ See how Impious I am ’, is equally legible. 
All sincere and modest art is, among us, profane 

§ 11. This faithlessness operates among us accord- 
ing to our tempers, producing either sadness or levity, 
and being the ultimate root alike of our discontents 
and of our wantonnesses. It is marvellous how full of 
contradiction it makes us : we are first dull, and 
seek for wild and lonely places because we have no 
heart for the garden; presently we recover our 
spirits, and build an assembly room among the moun- 
tains, because we have no reverence for the desert. 
I do not know if there be game on Sin a?, but I am 
always expecting' to hear of some one’s shooting 
over it. 

§ 12. There is, however, another, and a more inno- 
cent root of our delight in wild scenery. 

All the Renaissance principles of art tended, as I 

1 Pre-Raphaelitism, of course, excepted, which is a new phase 
of art, in no wise considered in this chapter. Blake was 
sincere, but full of wild creeds, and somewhat diseased in 
brain. 



OF MODERN LANDSCAPE [i»A»Tiv 

have before often explained, to the setting Beauty 
above Truth, and seeking for it always at the ex- 
pense of truth. And the proper punishment of such 
pursuit — ^the punishment which all the laws of the 
universe rendered inevitable — ^was, that those who 
thus pursued beauty should wholly lose sight of 
beauty. All the thinkers of the age, as we saw 
previously, declared that it did not exist. The age 
seconded their efiorts, and banished beauty, so far 
as human effort could succeed in doing so, from the 
face of the earth, and the form of man. To powder 
the hair, to patch the cheek, to hoop the body, to 
buckle the foot, were all part and parcel of the same 
system which reduced streets to brick walls, and 
pictures to brown stains. One desert of Ugliness was 
extended before the eyes of mankind ; and their 
pursuit of the beautiful, so recklessly continued, 
received unexpected consummation in high-heeled 
shoes and periwigs — Gower Street, and Gaspar 
Poussin. 

§ 13. Reaction from this state was inevitable, if 
any true life was left in the races of mankind; and, 
accordingly, though still forced, by rule and fashion, 
to the producing and wearing all that is ugly, men 
steal out, half-ashamed of themselves for doing so, 
to the fields and mountains; and, finding among 
these the colour, and liberty, and variety, and 
power, which are for ever grateful to them, delight 
in these to an extent never before known; rejoice 
in all the wildest shattering of the mountain side, 
as an opposition to Gower Street; gaze in a rapt 
manner att sunsets and sunrises, to see there the 
blue, and gold, and purple, whicji glow for them 
no longer on knight’s armour or temple porch; and 
gather with care out of the fields, into their blotted 
herbaria, the flowers which the five orders of archi- 
tecture have bsmished from their doors and case- 
ments. 

§ 14. The absence of care for personal beauty, 
which is another great characteristic of the age, adds 
to this feeling in a twofold way : first, by turning all 



279 


OHAP. xvi] OF MODERN LANDSCAPE 

reverent thoughts away from human nature; and 
making us think of men as ridiculous or ugly crea- 
tures, getting through the world as well as they can, 
and spoiling it in doing so; not ruling it in a kingly 
way and crowning all its loveliness. In the Middle 
Ages hardly anything but vice could be caricatured, 
because virtue was always visibly and personally 
noble ; now virtue itself is apt to inhabit such poor 
human bodies, that no aspect of it is invulnerable, 
to jest; and for all fairness we have to seek to the 
flowers, for all sublimity, to the hills. 

The same want of care operates, in another way, 
by lowering the standard of health, increasing the 
susceptibility to nervous or sentimental impressions, 
and thus adding to the other powers of nature over 
us whatever charm may be felt in her fostering the 
melancholy fancies of brooding idleness. 

§ 15. It is not, however, only to existing inani- 
mate nature that our want of beauty in person and 
dress has driven us. The imagination of it, as it 
was seen in our ancestors, haunts us continually; 
and while we yield to the present fashions, or act in 
accordance with the dullest modern principles of 
economy and utility, we look fondly back to the 
manners of the ages of chivalry, and delight in paint- 
ing, to the fancy, the fashions we pretend to despise, 
and the splendours we think it wise to abandon. 
The furniture and personages of our romance are 
sought, when the writer desires to please most easily, 
in the centuries which we profess to have surpassed 
in everything ; the art which takes us into the 
present times is considered as both daiiing and de- 
graded ; and while the weakest words please us, and 
are regarded as poetry, which recall the manners 
of our forefathers, or of strangers, it is only as 
familiar and vulgar that we accept the description 
of our own. 

In this we are wholly different from all the races 
that preceded us. All other nations have regarded 
their ancestors with reverence as saints or heroes; 
but have nevertheless thought their own deeds and 



280 OF MODERN LANDSCAPE [partiv 

ways ot life the fitting subjects for their arts of paint- 
ing or of verse. We, on the contrary, regard our an- 
cestors as foolish and wicked, but yet find our chief 
artistic pleasure in descriptions of their ways of life. 

The Greeks and mediaevals honoured, but did not 
imitate, their forefathers; we imitate, but do not 
honour. 

§ 16. With this romantic love of beauty, forced 
to seek in history, and in external nature, the satis- 
faction it cannot find in ordinary life, we mingle 
a more rational passion, the due and just result of 
newly awakened powers of attention. Whatever may 
first lead us to the scrutiny of natural objects, that 
scrutiny never fails of its reward. Unquestionably 
they are intended to be regarded by us with both 
reverence and delight; and every hour we give to 
them renders their beauty more apparent, and their 
interest more engrossing. Natural science — which 
can hardly be considered to have existed before 
modern times — rendering our knowledge fruitful in 
accumulation, and exquisite in accuracy, has acted 
for good or evil, according to the temper of the mind 
which received it; and though it has hardened the 
faithlessness of the dull and proud, has shown new 
grounds for reverence to hearts which were thought- 
ful and humble. The neglect of the art of war, 
while it has somewhat weakened and deformed the 
body 1, has given us leisure and opportunity for 
studies to which, before, time and space were equally 
wanting; lives which once were early wasted on 
the battle field are now passed usefully in the study; 
nations whjeh exhausted themselves in annual war- 
fare now dispute with each other the discovery of 
new planets ; and the serene philosopher dissects the 
plants, and analyzes the dust, of lands which were 

Of course this is meant only of the modern citizen or 
country-gentleman, as compared with a citizen of Sparta or 
old Florence. I leave it to others to say whether the ‘ neglect 
of the art of war ’ may or may not, in a yet more fatal sfense, 
be predicated of the English nation. War, without art, we 
seem, with God’s help, able Atill to wage nobly. 



CHAP. XVI] OF MODERN LANDSCAPE 281 

of old only traversed by the knight in hasty march, 
or by the borderer in heedless rapine. 

§ 17. The elements of progress and decline being 
thus strangely mingled in the modern mind, we 
might beforehand anticipate that one of the notable 
characters of our art would bo its inconsistency; that 
efforts would be made in every direction, and arrested 
by every conceivable cause and manner of failure; 
that in all we did, it would become next to impos- 
sible to distinguish accurately the grounds for praise 
or for regret; that all previous canons of practice 
and methods of thought would be gradually over- 
thrown, and criticism continually defied by successes 
which no one had expected, and sentiments w^hich 
no one could define. 

§ 18. Accordingly, while, in our inquiries into 
Greek and mediaeval art, I was able to describe, in 
general terms, what all men did or felt, I find now 
many characters in many men; some, it seems to 
me, founded on the inferior and evanescent principles 
of modernism, on its recklessness, impatience, or 
faithlessness; others founded on its science, its new 
affection for nature, its love of openness and liberty. 
And among all these characters, good or evil, I see 
that some, remaining to us from old or transitional 
periods, do not properly belong to us, and will soon 
fade away; and others, though not yet distinctly 
developed, are yet properly our own, and likely to 
grow forward into greater strength. 

For instance : our reprobation of bright colour is, 
I think, for the most part, mere affectation, and 
must soon be done away with. Vulgarity, dulness, 
or impiety, will indeed always express themselves 
through art in brown and grey, as in Rembrandt, 
Caravaggio, and Salvator; but we are not wholly 
vulgar, dull, oj impious; nor, as moderns, are we 
necessarily obliged to continue so in any wise. Our 
greatest men, whether sad or gay, still delight, like 
the great men of all ages, in brilliant hues. The 
colouring of Scott and Byron is full and pure; tliat 
of Keats and Tennyson rich even to excess. Our 



!282 


OF MODERN DANDSOARE [partiv 

practical failures in colouring are merely the neces- 
sary consequences of our prolonged want of practice 
during the periods of Renaissance aiSectation and 
ignorance; and the only durable difEerence between 
old and modern colouring, is the acceptance of cer- 
tain hues, by the modern, which please him by ex- 
pressing that ’ melancholy peculiar to his more 
reflective or sentimental character, and the greater 
variety of them necessary to express his greater 
science. 

§ 19. A^ain : if we ever become wise enough to 
dress consistently and gracefully, to make health a 
principal object in education, and to render our streets 
beautiful with art, the external charm of past history 
will in great measure disappear. There is no essen- 
tial reason, because we live after the fatal seven- 
teenth century, that we should never again be able 
to confess interest in sculpture, or see brightness in 
embroidery; nor, because now we choose to make 
the night deadly with our pleasures, and the day 
with our labours, prolonging the dance till dawn, 
and the toil to twilight, that we should never again 
learn how rightly to employ the sacred trusts of 
strength, beauty, and time. Whatever external 
charm attaches itself to the past, would then be 
seen in proper subordination to the brightness of 
present life; and the elements of romance would 
exist, in the earlier ages, only in the attraction which 
must generally belong to whatever is unfamiliar; in 
the reverence which a noble nation always pays to 
its ancestors; and in the enchanted light which 
races, like^individuals, must perceive in looking back 
to the days of their childhood. 

§ 20. Again : the peculiar levity with which natural 
scenery is regarded bv a large number of modern 
minds cannot be consiSered as entirely characteristic 
of the age, inasmuch as it never can belong to its 
greatest intellects. Men of any high mental power 
must be serious, whether in ancient or modern days : 
a certain degree of reverence for fair scenery is found 
in all our great writers without exception, — even the 



CHAP, xvi] OF MODERN LANDSCAPE m 

one who has made us laugh oftenest, taking Us to the 
valley of Chamouni, and to the sea beach, there to 
give peace after suffering, and change revenge into 
pityi. It is only the dull, the uneducated, or the 
worldly, whom it is painful to meet on the hill-sides; 
and levity, as a ruling character, cannot be ascribed 
to the whole nation, but only to its holiday-making 
apprentices, and its House of Commons. 

§ 21. We need not, therefore, expect to find any 
single poet or painter representing the entire group 
of powers, weaknesses, and inconsistent instincts 
which govern or confuse our modern life. But we 
may expect that in the man who seems to be given 
by Providence as the type of the age (as Homer 
and Dante were given, as the types of classical and 
mediaaval mind), we shall find whatever is fruitful 
and substantial to be completely present, together 
with those of our weaknesses, which are indeed 
nationally characteristic, and compatible with general 
greatness of mind; just as the weak love of fences, 
and dislike of mountains, were found compatible with 
Dante’s greatness in other respects. 

§ 22. Farther : as the admiration of mankind is 
found, in our times, to have in great part passed 
from men to mountains, and from human emotion 
to natural phenomena, we may anticipate that the 
great strength of art will also be warped in this 
direction; with this notable result for us, that where- 
as the greatest painters or painter of classical and 
mediceval periods, being wholly devoted to the repre- 
sentation of humanity, furnished us with but little 
to examine in landscape, the greatest painters or 
painter of modern times will in all probability be 
devoted to landscape principally; and farther, be- 
cause in representing human emotion words surpass 
painting, but in representing natural scenery paint- 
ing surpasses words, we may anticipate also that the 
painter and poet (for convenience’ sake I here use 
the words in opposition) will somewhat change their 
relations of rank in illustrating the mind of the age; 

1 See David Copperjield^ chap. Iv, and Iviii. 



284 OF MODERN LANDSCAPE [partiv 

tliat the painter will become of more importance, the 
poet of less ; and that the relations between the men 
who are the types and firstfruits of the age in word 
and work — namely, Scott and Turner — will be, in 
many curious respects, different from those between 
Homer and Phidias, or Dante and Giotto, 

It is this relation which we have now to examine. 

§ 23. And, first, I think it probable that many 
readers may be surprised at my calling Scott the 
great representative of the mind of the age of litera- 
ture. Those who can perceive the intense penetra- 
tive depth of Wordsworth, and the exquisite finish 
and melodious power of Tennyson, may be offended 
at my placing in higher rank that poetry of care- 
less glance, and 'reckless rhyme, in which Scott 
poured out the fancies of his youth; and those who 
are familiar with the subtle analysis of the French 
novelists, or who have in any wise submitted them- 
selves to the influence of German philosophy, may 
be equally indignant at my ascribing a principality 
to Scott among the literary men of Europe, in an 
age which has produced De Balzac and Goethe. 

So also in painting, those who are acquainted with 
the sentimental efforts made at present by the Ger- 
man religious and historical schools, and with the 
disciplined power ajid learning of the French, will 
think it beyond all explanation absurd to call a 
painter of light water-colour landscapes, eighteen 
inches by twelve, the first representative of the arts 
of the age. I can onl 3 ^ crave the reader’s patience, 
and his due consideration of the following reasons 
for my drting so, together with those advanced in 
the farther course of the work. 

§ 24. I believe the first test of a truly great man 
is his humility. I do not mean, by humility, doubt 
of his own power, or hesitation in speaking his 
opinions; but a right understanding of the relation 
between what he can do and say, and the rest of 
the world’s sayings and doings. All great men not 
only know their business, but usually know that they 
know it ; and are not only right in their main 



2B5 


CHAP, XVI] OF MODERN LANDSCAPE 

opinions, but they usually know that they are right 
in them; only, they do not think much of them- 
selves on that account. Arnolfo knows he can build 
a good dome at Florence; Albert Diirer writes calmly 
to one who had found fault with his work, ‘ It can- 
not be better done Sir Isaac Newton knows that 
he has worked out a problem or two that would have 
puzzled anybody else; — only they do not expect theii* 
fellow-men therefore to fall down and worship them; 
they have a curious under-sense of powerlessness, 
feeling that the greatness is not in them, but through 
them; that they could not do or be anything else 
than God made them. And they see something 
divine and God-made in every other man they meet, 
and are endlessly, foolishly, incredibly merciful. 

§ 26. Now, I find among the men of the present 
age, as far as I know them, this character in Scott 
and Turner pre-eminently ; I am not sure if it is 
not in them alone. I do not find Scott talking about 
the dignity of literature, nor Turner about the dignity 
of painting. They do their work, feeling that they 
cannot well help it; the story must be told, and 
the effect put down; and if people like it, well and 
good; and if not, the world will not be much the 
worse. 

I believe a very different impression of their esti- 
mate of themselves and their doings will be received 
by any one who reads the conservations of Words- 
worth or Goethe. The slightest manifestation of 
jealousy or self-complacency is enough to mark a 
second-rate character of the intellect; and I fear 
that, especially in Goethe, such manifestations are 
neither few nor slight. 

§ 26. Connected with this general humility, is the 
total absence of affectation in these men — that is to 
say, of any assumption of manner or behaviour in 
their work, in order to attract attention. Not but 
that they are mannerists both. Scott’s verse is 
strongly mannered, and Turner’s oil painting; but 
the manner of it necessitated by the feelings of the 
men, entirely natural to both, never exaggerated for 



286 OF MODEEN LANDSCAPE [pmiv 

the sake of show. I hardly know any other literary 
or pictorial work of the day . which is not in some 
degree affected. I am afraid Wordsworth was often 
affected in his simplicity, and Be Balzac in his finish. 
Many fine French writers are affected in their 
reserve, and full of stage tricks in placing of sen- 
tences. It is lucky if in German writers we ever 
find so much as a sentence without affectation. I 
know no painters without it, except one or two Pre- 
Raphaelites (chiefly Holman Hunt), and some simple 
water-colour painters, as William Hunt, William 
Turner of Oxford, and the late George Robson; but 
these last have no invention, and therefore by our 
fourth canon, Chap. Ill, § 21, are excluded from 
the first rank of artists; and of the Pre-Raphaelites 
there is here no question, as they in no wise represent 
the modem school. 

§ 27. Again : another very important, though not 
infallible, test of greatness is, as wo have often said, 
the appearance of Ease with which the thing is done. 
It may be that, as with Bante and Leonardo, the 
finish given to the work effaces the evidence of ease ; 
but where the ease is manifest, as in Scott, Turner, 
and Tintoret ; and the thing done is very noble, it is 
a strong reason for placing the men above those who 
confessedly w^rk with great pains. Scott writing his 
chapter or two before breakfast — ^not retouching, 
Turner finishing a whole drawing in a forenoon be- 
fore he goes out to shoot (providing always the chap- 
ter and drawing be good), are instantly to be set 
above men who confessedly have spent the day over 
the work, and think the hours well spent if it has 
been a little mended between sunrise and sunset. 
Indeed, it is no use for men to think to appear great 
by working fast, dashing, and scrawling; the thing 
they do must be good and great, cost what time it 
may; but if it he so, and they have honestly and 
unaffectedly done it with no effort ^ it is probably a 
greater and better thing than the result of the 
hardest efforts of others. 

§ 28. Then, as touching the kind of work done by 



CHAP. XVI] OP MODERN LANDSCAPE m 

these two men, the more I ihink of it I find this 
conclusion more impressed upon me, — ^that the great- 
est thing a human soul ever does in this world is 
to see something, and tell what it saw in a plain 
way. Hundreds of people can talk for one who 
can think, but thousands can think for one who can 
see. To see clearly is poetry, prophecy, and reli- 
gion — all in one. 

Therefore, finding the world of Literature more or 
less divided into Thinkers and Seers, I believe we 
shall find also that the Seers are wholly the greater 
race of the two. A true Thinker, who has practical 
purpose in his thinking, and is sincere, as Plato, or 
Carlyle, or Helps, becomes in some sort a seer, and 
must be always of infinite use in his generation ; but 
an affected Thinker, who supposes his thinking of 
any other importance than as it tends to work, is 
about the vainest kind of person that can be found 
in the occupied classes. Nay, I believe that meta- 
physicians and philosophers are, on the whole, the 
greatest troubles the world has got to deal with; 
and that while a tyrant or bad man is of some use 
in teaching people submission or indignation, and a 
thoroughly idle man is only harmful in setting an 
idle example, and communicating to other lazy people 
his own lazy misunderstandings, busy metaphysi- 
cians are always entangling good and active people, 
and weaving cobwebs among the finest wheels of 
the world’s business; and are as much as possible, 
by all prudent persons, to be brushed out of their 
way, like spiders, and the meshed weed that has 
got into the Cambridgeshire canals, and dther such 
impediments to barges and business. And if we 
thus clear the metaphysical element out of modern 
literature, we shall find its bulk amazingly dimin- 
ished, and the claims of the remaining writers, or 
of those whom we have thinned by this abstraction 
of their straw stuffing, much more easily adjusted 

1 Observe, I do not speak thns of metaphysics because I have 
no pleasure in them. Wlien I speak contemptuously of philo- 
logy, it may be answ'ered me, that I am a bad scholar ; but I 



288 OF MODERN LANDSCAPE [partiv 

§ 29. Again : the mass of sentimental literature, 
concerned with the analysis and description of 
emotion, headed by the poetry of Byron, is alto- 
gether of lower rank than the literature which merely 
describes what it saw. The true Seer always feels 
as intensely as any one else; but he does not much 
describe his feelings. He tells you whom he met, 
and what they said; leaves you to make out, from 
that, what they feel, and what he feels, but goes 
into little detail. And, generally speaking, pathetic 
writing and careful explanation of passion are quite 
easy, compared with this plain recording of what 
people said and did, or with the right invention of 
what they are likely to say and do; for this reason, 
that to invent a story, or admirably and thoroughly 
tell any part of a story, it is necessary to grasp the 
entire mind of every personage concerned in it, and 
know precisely how they would bo affected by what 
happens; which to do requires a colossal intellect; 
but to describe a separate emotion delicately, it is 
only needed that one should feel it oneself; and 
thousands of people are capable of feeling this or 
that noble emotion, for one who is able to enter 
into all the feelings of somebody sitting on the 
other side of the table. Even, therefore, where this 
sentimental literature is first rate, as in passages of 
Byron, Tennyson, and Keats, it ought not to be 
ranked so high as the Creative; and though perfec- 
tion, even in narrow fields, is perhaps as rare as 
in the wider, and it may be as long before we have 
another In Memoriam as another Guy Mannering, 
I unhesit^itingly receive as a greater manifestation 
of power the right invention of a few sentences 
spoken by Pleydell and Mannering across their 
supper-table, than the most tender and passionate 
melodies of the self -examining verse. 

cannot be so answered touching metaphysics, for every one 
conversant with such subjects may see that I have strong 
inclination that way. which would, indeed, have led me far 
astray long ago, if I had not learned also some use of my 
handLs, eyes, and feet. 



cHAP.xvi] OP MODERN LANDSCAPE 289 

§ 80. Having, therefore, cast metaphysical vh-iters 
out of our way, and sentimental writers into the 
second rank, I do not think Scott’s supremacy 
among those who remain will any more be doubtful; 
nor would it, perhaps, have been doubtful before, 
had it not been encumbered by innumerable faults 
and weaknesses. But it is pre-eminently in these 
faults and weaknesses that Scott is representative of 
the mind of his age : and because he is the greatest 
man born amongst us, and intended for the endur- 
ing type of us, all our principal faults must be laid 
on his shoulders, and he must bear down the dark 
marks to the latest ages; while the smaller men, 
who have some special work to do, perhaps not so 
much belonging to this age as leading out of it to 
the next, are often kept providentially quit of the 
encumbrances which they had not strength to sus- 
tain, and are much smoother and pleasanter to look 
at, in their way : only that is a smaller way. 

§ 31. Thus, the most startling fault of the age 
being its faithlessness, it is necessary that its greatest 
man should be faithless. Nothing is more notable or 
sorrowful in Scott’s mind than its incapacity of 
steady belief in anything. He cannot even resolve 
hardily to believe in a ghost, or a water-spirit; always 
explains them away in an apologetic manner, not 
believing, all the while, even in his own explanation. 
He never can clearly ascertain whether there is any- 
thing behind the arras but rats; never draws sword, 
and thrusts at it for life or death; but goes on look- 
ing at it timidly, and saying, ‘ it must be the wind ’. 
He is educated a Presbyterian, and remains one, 
because it is the most sensible thing he can do if 
he is to live in Edinburgh; but he thinks Romanism 
more picturesque, and profaneness more gentle- 
manly : does not see that anything affects human 
life but love, courage, and destiny; 'which are, in- 
deed, not matters of faith at ail, but of sight. Any 
gods but those are very misty in outline to him; 
and when the love is laid ghastly in poor Charlotte’s 
coffin ; and the courage is no more of use — ^the 
M. p.,m. u 



^90 OF MODEBN LANDSCAPE [paetiv 

pen having fallen from between the fingers; and 
destiny is sealing the serbll — tke God-li^t is dim 
in the tears that fall on it. 

He is in all. this the epitome of his epoch. 

§, 82. Again : as another notable weakness of the 
age is its habit of Idoking back, in a romantic and 
passionate idleness, to the past ages, not under- 
standing them all the while, nor really desiring to 
understand them, so Scott gives up nearly the half of 
his int^y^ctual power to a fond, yet purposeless, 
dreamin^'pter the past, and spends half his literary 
labourism endeavours to revive it, not in reality, but 
on the stage of fiction; endeavours which were the 
best of thetkind that modernism made, but still suc- 
cessful only so far as Scott put, under the old armour, 
the everlasting human nature which he knew; and 
totally unsuccessful, so far as concerned the painting 
of the armour itself, which he knew not. The excel- 
lence of Scott’s work is precisely in proportion to the 
degree in which it is sketched from present nature. 
His familiar life is inimitable ; his quiet scenes of in- 
troductory conversation, as the beginning of Rob Roy 
and Redgauntlet, and all his living Scotch charac- 
ters, mean or noble, from Andrew Fairservice to 
Jeanie Deans, are simply right, and can never be 
bettered. But his romance and antiquarianism, his 
knighthood and monkery, are all false, and he knows 
them to be false; does not care to make them 
earnest; enjoys them for their strangeness, but 
laughs at his own antiquarianism, all through his 
own third novel — with exquisite modesty indeed, 
but with total misunderstanding of the function of 
an Antiquary. He does not see how anything is to 
be got out of the past but confusion, old iron on 
drawingroom chairs, and serious inconvenience to 
Dr Heavysterne. 

§ 33. Again : more than any age that had preceded 
it, ours had been ignorant of the meaning of the 
word ‘ Art It had not a single fixed principle, and 
what unfixed principles it worked upon were aJl 
wrong. It was necessary that Scott should know 



OHAP.XVI] OF MODERN LANDSCAPE m 

Nothing of art. He neither cared for painting nor 
sculpture, and wa| totally incapable of formu^g a 
judgment about them. He had some contused li?ve 
of Gothic architecture, because it was dark, pictur- 
esque, old, and like nature; but could not til the 
worst from the best, and built for himself perhaps 
the most incongruous and ugly pile that gentlemanly 
modernism ever designed; marking, in the mx>st 
curious and subtle way, that mingling of reverence 
with irreverence which is so striking in the age ; he 
reverences Melrose, yet casts one of itt piscinas, 
puts a modern steel grate into it, and makes it his 
fireplace. Like all pure moderns, he supposes the 
Gothic barbarous, notwithstanding his love of it; 
admires, in an equally ignorant way, totally opposite 
styles ; is delighted with the new town of Edinburgh ; 
mistakes its dulness for purity of taste, and actually 
compares it, in its deathful formality of street, as 
contrasted with the rudeness of the old town, to 
Britornart taking off her armour. 

§ 84. Again : as in reverence and irreverence, so 
in levity and melancholy, we saw that the spirit of 
the age was strangely interwoven. Therefore, also, 
it is necessary that Scott should bo light, careless, 
unearnest, and yet eminently sorrowful. Through- 
out all his work there is no evidence of any purpose 
but to while away the hour. His life had no other 
object than the pleasure of the instant, and the 
establishing of a family name. All his thoughts 
were, in their outcome and end, less than nothing, 
and vanity. And yet, of all poetry that I know, 
none is so sorrowful as Scott’s. Other gr®at masters 
are pathetic in a resolute and predetermined way, 
when they choose; but, in their own minds, are 
evidently stern, or hopeful, or serene; never really 
melancholy. Even Byron is rather sulky and des- 
perate than melancholy; Keats is sad because he is 
sickly; Shelley because he is impious; but Scott 
is inherently and consistently sad. Around all his 
power, and brightness, and enjoyment of eye and 
heart, the far-away JEolian knell is for ever sound- 



OF MODEBN LANDSCAPE [partiv 

lxi|;; there is not one of those loving or laughing*' 
glances of his but it is brighter fgr the film of tears; 
his mind is like one of his own hill rivers, — ^it is 
white, and flashes in the sun fairly, careless, as it 
seems, and hasty in its going, but 

Far beneath, where slow they creep 
From pool to eddy, dark and deep, 

Where alders moist, and willows weep, 

You hear her streams repine. 

Life begins to pass from him very early; and 
while Homer sings cheerfully in his blindness, and 
Dante retains his courage, and rejoices in hope of 
Paradise, through all his exile, Scott, yet hardly 
past his J^th, lies pensive in the sweet sunshine 
and among the harvests of his native hills. 

Blackford, on whose uncultured breast, 

Among the broom, and thorn, and whin, 

A truant boy, I sought the nest. 

Or listed as I lay at rest, 

While rose on breezes thin 
The murmur of the city crowd, 

And, from his steeple jangling loud, 

St. Giles’s mingling din ! 

Now, from the summit to the plain, 

Waves all the hill with yellow grain ; 

And on the landscape as I look, 

Nought do 1 see unchanged remain, 

Save the rude cliffs and chiming brook ; 

To me they make a heavy moan 
Of early friendships past and gone. 

§ 35. Such, then, being the weaknesses which it 
was necessary that Scott should share with his age, 
in order that he might sufficiently represent it, and 
such the grounds for supposing him, in spite of all 
these weaknesses, the greatest literary man whom 
that age produced, let us glance at the principal 
points in which his view of landscape difiers from 
that of the mediae vals. 

I shall not endeavour now, as I did with Homer 
and Dante, to give a complete analysis of all the 
feelings which appear to be traceable in Scott’s allu- 



CHAP. XVI] OF MOBERlSr' LANDSCAPE 298 

sions to landscape scenery — ^for this would require 
a volume — ^but ordy to indicate the main points of 
differing character oetween his temper and Dante’s. 
Then we will examine in detail, not the landscape 
of literature, but that of painting, which must, of 
course, be equally, or even in a higher degree, 
characteristic of the age. 

§ 86. And, first, observe Scott’s habit of looking 
at nature neither as dead, or merely material, in 
the way that Homer regards it, nor as altered by his 
own feelings, in the way that Keats and Tennyson 
regard it, but as having an animation and pathos of 
its own, wholly irrespective of human presence or 
passion — an animation which Scott loves and sym- 
pathizes with, as he would with a fellow-creature, 
forgetting himself altogether, and subduing his own 
humanity before what seems to him the power of 
the landscape : 

Yon lonely thorn,— would he could tell 
The changes of his parent dell, 

Since he, so grey and stubborn now, 

Waved in each breeze a sapling bough ! 

Would he could tell, how deep the shade 
A thousand mingled branches made, 

How broad the shadows of the oak, 

How clung the rowan to the rock, 

And through the foliage showed his head, 

With narrow leaves and berries red ! 

Scott does not dwell on the grey stubbornness of the 
thorn, because he himself is at that moment disposed 
to be dull, or stubborn; neither on the cheerful 
peeping forth of the rowan, because he*himself is 
at that moment cheerful or curious ; but he perceives 
them both with the kind of interest that he would 
take in an old man, or a climbing boy; forgetting 
himself, in sympathy with either age or youth. 

And from the grassy slope he sees 
The Greta flow to meet the Tees. 

Where issuing from her darksome bed, 

She caught the morning’s eastern red, 

And through the softening vale below 
Roiled her bright waves in rosy glow, 



114 * OF MODERN LANDSCAPE [partiv 

All blushing to her bridal bed, 

Like some shy maid, in convent bred ; 

While linnet, lark, and blackbird gay 

Sing forth her nuptial roundelay. 

Is Scott, or are the persons of his story, gay at this 
moment? Far from it. Neither Scott nor Rising- 
ham are happy, but the Greta is; and all Scott’s 
sympathy is ready for the Greta, on the instant. 

§ 87. Observe, therefore, this is not pathetic 
fallacy; for there is no passion in Scott \^hich alters 
nature. It is not the lover’s passion, making him 
think the larkspurs are listening for his lady’s foot; 
it is not the miser’s passion, making him think that 
dead leaves are falling coins; but it is an inherent 
and continual habit of thought, which Scott shares 
with the moderns in general, being, in fact, nothing 
else than the instinctive sense which men must 
have of the Divine presence, not formed into distinct 
belief. In the Greek it created, as we saw, the faith- 
fully believed gods of the elements; in Dante and 
the mediesvals, it formed the faithfully believed 
angelic presence : in the modern, it creates no perfect 
form, does not apprehend distinctly any Divine 
being or operation; but only a dim, slightly credited 
animation in the natural object, accompanied with 
great interest and affection for it. This feeling is 
quite universal with us, only varying in depth accord- 
ing to the greatness of the heart that holds it; and 
in Scott, being more than usually intense, and accom- 
panied with infinite affection and quickness of sym- 
pathy, it enables him to conquer all tendencies to 
the pathetic fallacy, and, instead of making Nature 
anywise subordinate to himself, he mak^' himself 
subordinate to her — follows her lead simply— does not 
venture to bring his own cares and thoughts into her 
pure and quiet presence — ^paints her in her simple 
and universal truth, adding no result of momentary 
passion or fancy, and appears, therefore, at first 
shallower than other poets, being in reality wider 
and healthier. ‘ What am I?’ he says continually, 
‘that I should trouble this sincere nature with my 



CHAP. XVI] OF MODERN LANDSCAPE 295 

thoughts. I happen to be feverish and depressed, and 
I could see a great naany sad and strange things 
in those waves and flowers; but I have no business 
to see such things. Gay Greta I sweet harebells! 
you are not sad nor strange to most people; you are 
but bright water and blue blossoms; you shall not 
be anything else to me, except that I cannot help 
thinking you are a little alive — ^no one can help 
thinking that.’ And thus, as Nature is bright, 
serene, or gloomy, Scott takes her temper, and 
paints her as she is; nothing of himself being ever 
intruded, except that far-away Eolian tone, of which 
he is unconscious; and sometimes a stray syllable 
or two, like that about Blackford Hill, distinctly stat- 
ing personal feeling, but all the more modestly for 
that distinctness, and for the clear consciousness that 
it is not the chiming brook, nor the cornfields, that 
are sad, but only the boy that rests by thepi; so 
returning on the instant to reflect, in all honesty, 
the image of Nature as she is meant by all men to 
be received; nor that in fine words, but in the first 
that come ; nor with comment of far-fetched 
thoughts, but with easy thoughts, such as all sensible 
men ought to have in such places, only spoken 
sweetly ; and evidently also with an undercurrent 
of more profound reflection, which here and there 
murmurs for a moment, and which I think, if we 
choose, we may continually pierce down to, and 
drink deeply from, but which Scott leaves us to 
seek, or shun, at our pleasure. 

§ 38, And in consequence of this unselfishness and 
humility, Scott’s enjoyment of Nature ii incompar- 
ably greater than that of any other poet I know. 
All the rest carry their cares to her, and begin 
maundering in her ears about their own affairs. 
Tennyson goes out on a furzy common, and sees it 
is calm autumn sunshine, but it gives him no 
pleasure. He only remembers that it is 


Dead calm in that noble bre ast 
Which heaves but with the heaving deep. 



296 OF MODERN LANDSCAPE [partiv 

He sees a tbunder-olqud in the evening, and would 
have ‘ doted and pored ’ on it, but cannot, for fear 
it should bring the ship bad weather. Keats drinks 
the beauty of Nature violently; but has no naore 
real sympathy with her than he has with a bottle 
of claret. His palate is fine; but he ‘ bursts joy’s 
grape against it gets nothing but misery, and a 
bitter taste of dregs, out of his desperate draught. 

Byron and Shelley are nearly the same, only with 
less truth of perception, and even more troublesome 
selfi&hness. Wordsworth is more like Scott, and 
understands how to be happy, but yet cannot alto- 
gether rid himself of the sense that he is a philoso- 
$her, and ought always to be saying something wise. 
He has also a vague notion that Nature would not 
be able to get on well without Wordsworth; and 
finds a considerable part of his pleasure in looking 
at himself as well as at her. But with Scott the 
love is entirely humble and unselfish. ‘ I, Scott, am 
nothing, and less than nothing; but these crags, and 
heaths, and clouds, how great they are, how lovely, 
how for ever to be beloved, only for their own silent, 
thoughtless sake 1 ’ 

§ 30. This pure passion for nature in its abstract 
being, is still increased in its intensity by the two 
elements above taken notice of, — the love of anti- 
quity, and the love of colour and beautiful form, 
mortified in our streets, and seeking for food in the 
wilderness and the ruin : both feelings, observe, in- 
stinctive in Scott from his childhood, as everything 
that makes a man great is always. 

A®d well the lonely infant knew 
Recesses where the wallflower grew, 

And honeysuckle loved to crawl 
Up the lone crag and ruined wall. 

I deemed such nooks the sweetest shade 
The sun in all its round surveyed. 

Not that these could have been instinctive in a 
child in the Middle Ages. The sentiments of a 
people increase or diminish in intensity from gener- 
ation to generation — every disposition of the parents 



297 


cHAP.xvi] OF MOrJERN LAKBSCAPE 

affecting the Irame of the mind in their offspring : 
the soldier’s child is born to be yet more a soldier, 
and the politician’s to be still more a politician; 
even the slightest colours of sentiment and affection 
are transmitted to the heirs of life; and the crown- 
ing expression of the mind of a people is given when 
some infant of highest capacity, and sealed with 
the impress of this national character, is born where 
providential circumstances permit the full develop- 
ment of the powers it has received straight from 
Heaven, and the passions which it has inherited from 
its fathers. 

§ 40. This love of ancientness, and that of natural 
beauty, associate themselves also in Scott with the 
love of liberty, which was indeed at the root even of 
all his Jacobite tendencies in politics. For, putting 
aside certain predilections about landed property, and 
family name, and ‘ gentlemanliness ’ in the club 
sense of the word — ^respecting which I do not now 
inquire whether they were weak or wise, — the main 
element which makes Scott like Cavaliers better than 
Puritans is, that he thinks the former free and 
masterful as well as loyal; and the latter formal and 
slavish. He is loyal, not so much in respect for law, 
as in unselfish love for the king; and his sympathy 
is quite as ready for any active borderer who breaks 
the law, or fights the king, in what Scott thinks a 
generous way, as for the king himself. Rebellion of 
a rough, free, and bold kind he is always delighted 
by; he only objects to rebellion on principle and in 
form : bare-headed and open-throated treason he will 
abet to any extent, but shrinks from it ifi a peaked 
hat and starched collar : nay, politically, he only 
delights in kingship itself, because he looks upon it 
as the head and centre of liberty; and thinks that, 
keeping hold of a king’s hand, one may get rid of 
the cramps and fences of law; and that the people 
may be governed by the whistle, as a Highland clan 
on the open hill-side, instead of being shut up into 
hurdled folds or hedged fields, as sheep or cattle left 
masterless. 



298 OF MODERN LANDSCAPE [partiv 

§ 41, And thus Nature becomes dear to Scott in 
a threefold way : dear to him, first, as containing 
those remains or memories of the past, which he 
cannot find in cities, and giving hope of PrsBtorian 
mound or knight’s grave, in every green slope and 
sh^de of its desolate places; — dear, secondly, in its 
moorland liberty, which has for him just as high 
a charm as the fenced garden had for the mediaeval; 

For I was wayward, bold, and wild, 

A self-willed imp— a grandame’s child ; 

But, half a plague, and half a jest, 

Was still endured, beloved, caressed : 

For me, thus nurtured, dost thou ask 
The classic poet’s well-conned task ? 

Nay, Erskine, nay. On the wild hill 
Let the wild heathbell flourish still ; 

Cherish the tulip, prune the vine ; 

But freely let the woodbine twine. 

And leave untrimmed the eglantine ; 

— and dear to him, finally, in that perfect beauty, 
denied alike in cities and in men, for which every 
modem heart had begun at last to thirst, and Scott’s, 
in its freshness and power, of all men’s, most 
earnestly. 

§ 42. And in this love of beauty, observe, that 
(as I said we might except) the love of colour is a 
leading element, his healthy mind being incapable 
of losing, under any modem false teaching, its joy 
in brilliancy of hue. Though not so subtle a colour- 
ist as Dante, which, under the circumstances of the 
age, he could not be, he depends quite as much upon 
colour for his power or pleasure. And, in general, 
if he does not mean to say much aboni things, the 
one character which he wUl give is colour^ using it 
with the most perfect mastery and faithfulness, up 
to the point of possible modem perception. For in- 
stance, if he has a sea-storm fco paint in a single 
line, he does not, as a feebler poet would probably 
have done, use any expression about the temper or 
form of the waves ; does not call them angry or moun- 



CHAP.xvi] OF MODEBN LANDSCAPE 299 

tainouB. He is content to strike tkem out with two 
dashes of Tintoret's favourite colours ; 

The blackening wave tar edged with white ; 

To inch and rock the aeamews fly. 

There is no form in this. Nay, the main virtu| of 
it is, that it gets rid of all form. The dark raging 
of the sea — what form has that? But out of the 
cloud of its darkness those lightning flashes of the 
foam, coming at their terrible intervals — you need 
no more. 

Again : where he has to describe tents mingled 
among oaks, he says nothing about the form of either 
tent or tree, but only gives the two strokes of colour : 

Thousand paviliona, white as snov). 

Chequered the borough moor below, 

Oft giving way, where still there stood 
Some relics of the old oak wood, 

That darkly huge did intervene, 

And tamed the glaring white with green. 

Again : of tents at Flodden : 

Next morn the Baron climbed the tower. 

To view, afar, the Scottish power, 

Encamped on Flodden edge. 

The white pavilions made a show, 

Like remnants of the winter snow. 

Along the dusky ridge. 

Again : of trees mingled with dark rocks : 

Until, where Teith’s young waters roll 
Betwixt him and a wooded knoll, 

That graced the sahU strath with greijjn,., 

The chapel of St Bride was seen. 

Again ^ there is hardly any form, only smoke and 
colour, in his celebrated description of Edinburgh : 

The wandering eye could o^er it go, 

And mark the distant city glow 
With gloomy splendour red ; 

For on the smoke-wreaths, huge and slow. 

That round her sable turrets flow, 

The morning beams were shed, 



‘ |i# OF MODERN LANDSCAPE [partiv 

And tinged them with a lustre proud. 

Like that which streaks a thunder-cloud. 

Such dusky grandeur clothed the height, 

Where the huge Castle holds its state, 

And all the steep slope down, 

Whose ridgy back heaves to the sky, 

Piled deep and massy, close and high. 

Mine own romantic town ! 

But northward far, with purer blaze, 

On Ochil mountains fell the rays. 

And as each heathy top they kissed, 

It gleamed a purple amethyst. 

Yonder the shores of Fife you saw ; 

Here Preston Bay and Berwick Law : 

And, broad between them rolled 
The gallant Frith the eye might note, 

Whose islands on its bosom float, 

Like emeralds chased in gold. 

I do not like to spoil a fine passage by italicizing 
it; but observe, the only hints at form, given 
throughout, are in the somewhat vague words, 

‘ ridgy ‘ massy * close and * high the whole 
being still more obscured by modern mystery, in its 
most tangible form of smoke. But the colours are 
all definite; note the rainbow band of them — gloomy 
or dusky red, sable (pure black), amethyst (pure 
purple), green, and gold — a noble chord throughout; 
and then, moved doubtless less by the smoky than the 
amethystine part of the group, 

Fitz Eustace’ heart felt closely pent, 

The spur he to his charger lent, 

And raised his bridle band, 

Add, making demi volte in air, 

Cried, ‘ Where ’s the coward would, not dare 
To fight for such a land ? ’ 

I need not multiply examples : the reader can 
easily trace for himself, through verse familiar to 
us all, the force of these colour instincts. I will 
therefore add only two passages, not so completely 
known by heart as most of the poems in which they 
occur. 



CHAP.XVI] OF MODESN - LANDSCAPE 801 

’Twas sileDice all. He laid him down 
Where purple heath profusely strown, 

And throatwort, with its azure hell, 

And moss and thyme his cushion swell. 

There, spent with toil, he listless eyed 
The course of Greta’s playful tide ; 

Beneath her banks, now eddying dun, 

Now brightly gleaming to the sun, 

As, dancing over rock and stone, 

In yellow light her currents shone, 

Matching in hue the favourite gem 
Of Albin’s mountain diadem. 

Then tired to watch the current play, 

He turned his weary eyes away 

To where the bank opposing showed 

Its huge S(^uare cliffs through shaggy wood. 

One, prominent above the rest, 

Beared to the sun its pale grey breast ; 

Around its broken summit grew 
The hazel rude, and sable yew ; 

A thousand varied lichens dyed 
Its waste and weather- beaten side ; 

And round its rugged basis lay, 

By time or thunder rent away. 

Fragments, that, from its frontlet torn. 

Were mantled now by verdant thorn. 

§ 43. Note, first, what an exquisite chord of colour 
is given in the succession of this passage. It begins 
with purple and blue; then passes to gold, or cairn- 
gorm colour (topaz colour); then to 'pale grey^ 
through which the yellow passes into black; and 
the black, through broken dyes of lichen, into green. 
Note, secondly, — what is indeed so manifest through- 
out Scott’s landscape as hardly to need pointing out, 
— the love of rocks, and true understandiiig of their 
colours and characters, opposed as it is in every 
conceivable way to Dante’s hatred and misunder- 
standing of them. 

I have already traced, in various places, most of 
the causes of this great difference; namely, first, 
the ruggedness of northern temper (compare § 8 
of the chapter* on the Nature of Gothic in The Stones 
of Venice); then the really greater beauty of the 
northern rocks, as noted when we were speaking of 



OF MODERN LANDSCAPE [pARtiv 

’the Apennine limestone ; then the lieeii of finding 
beauty among them, if it were to be found anywhere, 
— ^no well-arranged colours being any more to be 
seen in dress* but only in rock lichens; and, finally, 
the love of irregularity, liberty, and power springing 
up in glorious opposition to laws of prosody, fasmon, 
and the five orders. , 

§ 44. The other passage I have to quote is still 
more interesting; because it has no form in it at all 
except in one word (chalice), but wholly composes 
its imagery either of colour, or of that delicate half- 
believed life which we have seen to be so important 
an element in modern landscape : 

The summer dawn’s reflected hue 
'l ” ' To purple chaiiyed Loch Katrine blue ; 

Mildly and soft the western breeze 
Just kissed the lake, just stirred the trees ; 

And the pleased lakcy like maiden coy^ 

Trembled^ but dimpled not , for joy ; 

The mountain-shadows on her breast 
Were neither broken nor at rest ; 

In bright uncertainty they lie, 

Like future joys to Fancy’s eye. 

The wateri-lily to the light 

Her chalice reared of silver bright ; 

The doe awoke, and to the lawn, 

Begemmed with dew-drOi)s, led her fawn ; 

The grey mist left the mountain-side ; 

The torrent showed its glistening pride ; 

Invisible in flecked sky. 

The lark sent down her revelry ; 

The blackbird and the speckled'^thrush 
Good-morrow gave from brake and bush ; 

< In answer cooed the cushat dove 

Ker notes of peace, and rest, and love. 

Two more coasiderations Arb,, hc^-wever, suggested 
by the above passage. The first,, that the love of 
natural history, excited by the continual attention 
now given to all vdid landscape, heightens recipro- 
cally the interest of that landscape, and becomes an 
iinportant element in Scott’s description, leading him 
to finish, down to the minutest speckling of breast, 
and slightest shade of attributed emotion, the por- 



OHAP.xVi] OF MOETERN LANDSCAPE 1S08 

traiture of birds and animals; in strange op|>ositioii 
to Homer % sligiitly named ‘ sea-crows, who have 
care of the works of the sea and Dante’s singing- 
birds, of undefined Species. Compare carefully a 
passage, too long to be quoted — the 2nd and 8rd 
stanzas of canto vi of Rokehy, 

§ 45. The second, and the last point I have to 
note, is Scott’s habit of drawing a slight moral from 
every scene, just enough to excuse to his conscience 
hi^ want of definite religious feeling; and that this 
slight moral is almost always melancholy. Here 
he has stopped short without entirely expressing it 

The mountain shadows . 

. lie 

Like future jcys to Fancy^s eye. 

His completed thought would be that those future 
joys, like the mountain shadows, were never to be 
attained. It occurs fully uttered in many other 
places He seems to have been constantly rebuking 
his own worldly pride and vanity, but never purpose- 
fully : 

The foam*^lobes on her eddies ride, 

Thick as the schemes of huma® pride 
That down life’s current drive amain, 

As frail, as frothy, and as vain. 

Foxglove, and nightshade, side by side. 

Emblems of punishment and pride. 

Her dark eye flashed ; she paused, and sighed 
‘ Ah, what have I to do with pride ! ’ 

And hear the thought he gathers from the sunset 
(noting first the Tumerian colour — as usual, its 
principal element) : 

The sultry summer day is done, 

The western hills have hid the sun, 

But moutitain peak and village spire 
Retain reflection of hip fire. 

Old Barnarjd’s towers are purple still, 

To those that gaze from Toller Hill ; 



604 OF MODERN LANDSCAPE [partiv 

Distant and high the tower of Bowes, 

Like steel upon the anvil glows ; 

And Stanmore’s ridge, behind that lay, 

Rich with the spoils of parting day, 

In crimson and in gold arrayed, 

Streaks yet awhile the closing shade ; 

Then slow resigns to darkening heaven 
The tints which brighter hours had given. 

Thus, aged men, full loath and slow, 

The vanities of life forego, 

And count their youthful follies o^er 
Till memory lends her light no more. 

That is, as far as I remember, one of the most 
finished pieces of sunset he has given; and it has 
a woful moral; yet one which, with Scott, is in- 
separable from the scene. 

Hark, again : 

’Twere sweet to mark the setting day 
On Bourhope’s lonely top decay ; 

And, as it faint and feeble died 
On the broad lake and mountain’s side, 

To say, * Thus pleasures fade away ; 

Youth, talents, beauty, thus decay. 

And leave us dark, forlorn, and grey. ’ 

And again, hear Bertram ; 

Mine be the eve of tropic sun : 

With disk like battle-target red, 

He rushes to his burning bed, 

Dyes the wide wave with bloody light. 

Then sinks at once ; and all is night. 

In all places of this kind, where a passing thought 
is suggesteii by some external scene, that tnought is 
at once a slight and sad one. Scott’s deeper moral 
sense is marked in the conduct of his stories, and 
in casual reflections or exclamations arising out of 
their plot, and therefore sincerely uttered; as that 
of Marmion ; 

Oh, what a tangled web we weave, 

When first we practise to deceive 1 

But the reflections which are founded, not on 



805 . 


CHAP, XVI] OF MODERN LANDSCAPE 

eveaits, but on scenes, are, for the most part, shallow, 
partly insincere, and, as far as sincere, sorrowful. 
This habit of ineffective dreaming and moralizing over 
passing scenes, of which the earliest type I know is 
given in J.aques, is, as aforesaid, usually the satis- 
faction made to our modern consciences for the want 
of a sincere acknowledgment of God in nature : and 
Shakspeare has marked it as the characteristic of a 
mind ‘ compact of jars * (Act ii, Sc. vii, As You 
Like It). That description attaches but too accur- 
ately to all the moods which we have traced in the 
moderns generally, and in Scott as the first repre- 
sentative of them; and the question now is, what 
this love of landscape, so composed, is likely to 
lead us to, and what use can be made of it. 

We began our investigation, it will be remembered, 
in order to determine whether landscape-painting 
was worth studying or not. We have now reviewed 
the three principal phases of temper in the civilized 
human race, and we find that landscape has been 
mostly disregarded by great men, or cast into a 
second place, until now; and that now it seems 
dear to us, partly in consequence of our faults, and 
partly owing to accidental circumstances, soon, in 
all likelihood, to pass away : and there seems great 
room for question still, whether our love of it is a 
permanent and healthy feeling, or only a healthy 
crisis in a generally diseased state of mind. If the 
former, society will for ever hereafter be affected 
by its results ; and Turner, the first great landscape- 
painter, must take a place in the history of nations 
corresponding in art accurately to that* of Bacon 
in philosophy; Bacon having first opened the study 
of the laws of material nature, when, formerly, men 
had thought only of the laws of human mind; and 
Turner having first opened the study of the aspect 
of material nature, when, before, men had thought 
only of the aspect of the human form. Whether, 
therefore, the love of landscape be trivial and tran- 
sient, or important and permanent, it now becomes 
necessary to consider. We have, I think, data 
M. P.,111. X 



THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE [paetiv 

.enough before us for the solution of the question, 
and we will enter upon it, accordingly, in the follow- 
ing chapter. 


CHAPTER XVII 

THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE 

§ 1. Supposing then the preceding conclusions 
correct, respecting the grounds and component ele- 
ments of the pleasure which the moderns take in 
landscape, we have here to consider what are the 
probable or usual effects of this pleasure. Is it a 
safe or a seductive one? May we wisely boast of it, 
and unhesitatingly indulge it? or is it rather a senti- 
ment to be despised when it is slight, and condemned 
when it is intense; a feeling which disinclines us to 
labour, and confuses us in thought; a joy only to 
the inactive and the visionary, incompatible with 
the duties of life, and the accuracies of reflection? 

§ 2. It seems to me that, as matters stand at 
present, there is considerable ground for the latter 
opinion. We saw, in the preceding chapter, that our 
love of nature had been partly forced upon us by 
mistakes in our social economy, and led to no dis- 
tinct issues of action or thought. And when we look 
to Scott — ^the man who feels it most deeply — ^for 
some explanation of its effect upon him, we find 
a curious tone of apology (as if for an involuntary 
folly) running through his confessions of such senti- 
ment, and a still more curious inability to define, 
beyond a certain point, the character of tnis emotion. 
He has lost the company of his friends among the 
hills, and turns to these last for comfort. He says, 
‘ there is a pleasure in the pain ’ consisting in such 
thoughts 

As oft awake 

By lone St Mary’s silent lake ; 

but, when we look for some definition of these 
thoughts, all that we are told is, that they compose 



CHiLP. xvn] TRT, MORAL OF LANDSCAPE 807 

A mingled sentiment 
Of resignation and content i — 

a sentiment which, I suppose, many people can attain 
to on the loss of their friends, without the help of 
lakes or mountains ; while Wordsworth definitely and 
positively affirms that thought has nothing whatever 
to do with the matter, and that though, in his youth, 
the cataract and wood ‘ haunted him like a passion \ 
it was without the help of any ‘ remoter charm, by 
thought supplied.’ 

§ 8. There is not, however, any question, but that 
both Scott and' Wordsworth are here mistaken in their 
analysis of their feelings. Their delight, so far from 
being without thought, is more than half made up of 
thought, but of thought in so curiously languid and 
neutralized a condition that they cannot trace it. 
The thoughts are beaten to a powder so small that 
they know not what they are; they know only that 
in such a state they are not good for much, and 
disdain to call them thoughts. But the way in which 
thought, even thus broken, acts in producing the 
delight will be understood by glancing back to §§ 9 
and 10 of the tenth chapter, in which we observed 
the power of the imagination in exalting any visible 
object, by gathering round it, in farther vision, all 
the facts properly connected with it; this being, as 
it were, a spiritual or second sight, multiplying the 
power of enjoyment according to the fulness of the 
vision. For, indeed, although in all lovely nature 
there is, first, an excellent degree of simple beauty, 
addressed to the eye alone, yet often what tmpresses 
us most will form but a very small portion of that 
visible beauty. That beauty may, for instance, be 
composed of lovely flowers and glittering streams, 
and blue sky and white clouds; and yet the thing 
that impresses us most, and which we should be 
sorriest to lose, may be a thin grey film on the 
extreme horizon, not so large, in the space of the 
scene it occupies, as a piece of gossamer on a near 

^ Marmion, Introduction to canto ii. 



•THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE [partiv 

at hand bush, nor in any wise prettier to the eye 
than the gossamer; but, because the gossamer is 
known by us for a little bit of spider’s work, and 
the other grey film is known to mean a mountain 
ten thousand feet high, inhabited by a race of noble 
mountaineers, we are solemnly impressed by the 
aspect of it; and yet, all the while, the thoughts 
and knowledge which cause us to receive this im- 
pression are so obscure that we are not conscious of 
them; we think wc are only enjoying the visible 
scene; and the very men whose minds are fullest 
of such thoughts absolutely deny, as we have just 
heard, that they owe their pleasure to anything but 
the eye, or that the pleasure consists in anything else 
than ‘ Tranquillity 

§ 4. And observe, farther, that this comparative 
Dimness and Untraceableness of the thoughts which 
are the sources of our admiration, is not a fault in 
the thoughts, at such a time. It is, on the contrary, 
a necessary condition of their subordination to the 
pleasure of Sight. If the thoughts were more distinct 
we should not see so well; and beginning definitely 
to think, we must comparatively cease to see. In the 
instance just supposed, as long as we look at the 
film of mountain or Alp, with only an obscure con- 
sciousness of its being the source of mighty rivers, 
that consciousness adds to our sense of its sublimity ; 
and if we have ever seen the Rhine or the Rhone 
near their mouths, our knowledge, so long as it is 
only obscurely suggested, adds to our admiration of 
the Alp;^ but once let the idea define itself — once 
let us begin to consider seriously what rivers flow 
from that mountain, to trace their course, and to recall 
determinately our memories of their distant aspects, 
— and we cease to behold the Alp; or, if we still 
behold it, it is only as a point in a map which we 
are painfully designing, or as a subordinate object 
which we strive to thrust aside, in order to make 
room for our remembrances of Avignon or Rotterdam. 

Again : so long as our idea of the multitudes who 
inhabit the ravines at its foot remains indistinct, that 



CHAP. XVII] THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE 309 

idea comes to the aid of all the other associations 
which increase our delight. But let it once arrest 
us, and entice us to follow out some clear course 
of thought respecting the causes of the prosperity 
or misfortune of the Alpine villagers, and the snowy 
peak again ceases to be visible, or holds its place only 
as a white spot upon the retina, while we pursue 
our meditations upon the religion or the political 
economy of the mountaineers. 

§ 5. It is thus evident that a curiously balanced 
condition of the powers of mind is necessary to in- 
duce full admiration of any natural scene. Let those 
powers be themselves inert, and the mind vacant of 
knowledge, and destitute of sensibility; and the 
external object becomes little more to us than it is 
to birds or insects; we fall into the temper of the 
clown. On the other hand, let the reasoning powers 
be shrewd in excess, the knowledge vast, or sensi- 
bility intense, and it will go hard but that the visible 
object will suggest so much that it shall be soon itself 
forgotten, or become, at the utmost, merely a kind of 
key-note to the course of purposeful thought. New- 
ton, probably, did not perceive whether the apple 
which suggested his meditations on gravity w^as 
withered or rosy; nor could Howard be affected by 
the picturesqueness of the architecture which held 
the sufferers it was his occupation to relieve. 

§ 6. This wandering away in thought from the 
thing seen to the business of life, is not, however, 
peculiar to men of the highest reasoning powers, 
or most active benevolence. It takes place more or 
less in nearly all persons of average meiffcal endow- 
ment. They see and love what is beautiful, but 
forget their admiration of it in following some train 
of thought which it suggested, and which is of more 
personal interest to them. Suppose that three or 
four persons come in sight of a group of pine-trees, 
not having seen pines for some time. One, perhaps 
an engineer, is struck by the manner in which their 
roots hold the ground, and sets himself to examine 
their fibres, in a few minutes retaining little more 



310 THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE [partiv 

consciousness of the beauty of the trees than if he 
were a rope-maker uKtwisting the strands of a cable : 
to another, the ‘Sight of the trees calls up some 
happy association, and presently he forgets them, 
and pursues the memories they summoned : a third 
is struck by certain groupings of their colours, useful 
to him as an artist, which he proceeds/ immediately 
to note mechanically for future use, mth as little 
feeling as a cook setting down the constituents of a 
newly discovered dish; and a fourth, impressed by 
the wild coiling of boughs and roots, will begin to 
change them in his fancy into dragons and monsters, 
and lose his grasp of the scene in fantastic metamor- 
phosis : while, in the mind of the man who has most 
the power of contemplating the thing itself, all these 
perceptions and trains of idea are partially present, 
not distinctly, but in a mingled and perfect harmony. 
He will not see the colours of the tree so well as 
the artist, nor its fibres so well as the engineer; he 
will not altogether share the emotion of the senti- 
mentalist, nor the trance of the idealist; but fancy, 
and feeling, and perception, and imagination, will 
all obscurely meet and balance themselves in him, 
and he will see the pine-trees somewhat in this 
manner ; 

Worthier still of note 
Are those fraternal Four of Borrowdale, 

Joined in one solemn and capacious grove ; 

Huge trunks ! and each particular trunk a growth 
Of intertwisted fibres serpentine 
Up-coiling, and inveterately convolved ; 

Nor unintonned with Phantasy, and looks 
That «^breaten the profane ; a pillared shade, 

Upon whose grassless floor of red-brown hue, 

By sheddings from the pining umbrage tinged 
Perennially, — beneath whose sable roof 
Of boughs, as if for festal purpose, decked 
With unrejoicing berries, ghostly Shapes 
May meet at noontide ; Fear and trembling Hope, 
Silence and Foresight ; Death the Skeleton, 

And Time the Shadow ; there to celebrate, 

As in a natural temple scattered o’er 
With altars undisturbed with mossy stone, 

United worship. 



cHAf. ?LVII] THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE 811 


§ 7. The power, therefore, of thus fully mrceiving 
any natural object depends oil oi^^'beiiig able^to group 
and fasten all our fancies about ft as a centre J making 
a garland of thoughts for it, in which eadh^^^ separate 
thought is subdued and shortened of its own strength, 
in order to fit it for harmony with others; the in- 
tensity of ,pur enjoyment of the object depending, 
first, on it's own beauty, and then on the richness 
of the garland. And men who have this habit of 
clustering and harmonizing their thoughts are a 
little too apt to look scoinfully upon the harder 
workers who tear iiae bouquet to pieces to examine 
the stems. This was the chief narrowness of Words- 
worth’s mind : b© could not understand that to break 
a rock with a hammer in search of crystal may some- 
times be ^ act not ' disgraceful to ; human nature, 
and that th dissect a flower may sometimes be as 
proper as to dream over it; whereas all experience 
goes to teabh us, that among men of average intel- 
lect the most useful members of society are the dis- 
sectors, not the dreamers. It is not that they love 
nature or beauty less, but that they love result, 
effect, and progress more; and when we glance 
broadly along the starry crowd of benefactors to the 
human race, and guides of human thought, we shall 
find that this dreaming love of natural beauty — or 
at least its expression — ^has been more or less checked 
by them all, and subordinated either to hard work or 
watching of human nature. Thus in all the classical 
and medieeval periods, it was, as we have seen, sub- 
ordinate to agriculture, war, and religion; and in 
the modern |)eriod, in which it has becorfte far more 
powerful, obs^^te in what persons it is chiefly mani- 
fested. 


(1.) It is subordinate in 
Bacon. 

Milton. 

Johnson. 

Richardson. 

Goldsmith. 

Young. 


(2.) It is intense in 
Mrs Radclyffe. 
St Pierre. 
Shenstone. 
Byron. 

Shelley. 

Keats. 



M THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE [part iv 

(L) It is subordinate in (2.) It is intense in 

Newton. Burns. 

Howard. Eugene Sue. 

Fenelon. G-eorge Sand. 

Pascal. Dumas. 

§ 8. I have purposely omitted the names of Words- 
worth, Tennyson, and Scott, in the second list, be- 
cause, glancing at the two columns as they now 
stand, we may, I think, draw some useful conclu- 
sions -from the high honourableness and dignity of 
the names on one side, and the comparative slight- 
ness of those on the other — conclusions which may 
help us to a better understanding of Scott and Tenny- 
son themselves. Glancing, I say, down those columns 
in their present form, we shall at once perceive that 
the intense love of nature is, in modern times, 
characteristic of persons not of the first order of 
intellect, but of brilliant imagination, quick sym- 
pathy, and undefined religious principle, suffering 
also usually under strong and ill-governed passions : 
while in the same individual it will be found to vary 
at different periods, being, for the most part, strong- 
est in youth, and associated with force of emotion, 
and with indefinite and feeble powers of thought; 
also, throughout life, perhaps developing itself most 
at times when the mind is slightly unhinged by love, 
grief, or some other of the passions. 

§ 9. But, on the other hand, while these feelings 
of delight in natural objects cannot be construed into 
signs of the highest mental powers, or purest moral 
principles, *we see that they are assuredly indicative 
of minds above the usual standard of power, and 
endowed with sensibilities of great preciousness to 
humanity ; so that those who find themselves entirely 
destitute of them, must make tfiis want a subject 
of humiliation, not of pride. The apathy which can- 
not perceive beauty is very different from the stern 
energy which disdains it; and the coldness of heart 
which receives no emotion from external nature, is 
not to be confounded with the wisdom of purpose 



CHAP, xvn] THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE 318 

whick represses emotion in action. In the case of 
most men, it is neither acuteness of the reason, nor 
breadth of humanity, which shields them from the 
impressions of natural scenery, but rather low 
anxieties, vain discontents, and mean pleasures; and 
for one who is blinded to the works of God by pro- 
found abstraction or lofty purpose, tens of thousands 
have their eyes sealed by vulgar selfishness, and their 
intelligence crushed by impious care. 

Observe, then : we have, among mankind in 
general, the three orders of being; — the lowest, sordid 
and selfish, which neither sees nor feels; the second, 
noble and sympathetic, but which sees and feels 
without concluding or acting; the third and highest, 
which loses sight in resolution, and feeling in work 

1 The investigation of this subject becomes, therefore, diffi- 
cult beyond all other parts of our inquiry, since precisely the 
same sentiments may arise in different minds from totally 
opposite causes ; and the extreme of frivolity may sometimes 
for a moment desire the same things as the extreme of moral 
power and dignity. In the following extract from Marriage, 
the sentiment expressed by Lady Juliana (the ineffably foolish 
and frivolous heroine of the story) is as nearly as possible 
what Dante would have felt, under the same circumstances : 

‘ The air was soft and genial ; not a cloud stained the bright 
azure of the heavens ; and the sun shone out in all his splen- 
dour, shedding life and beauty even over the desolate heath- 
clad hills of Glenfern. But, after they had journeyed a few 
miles, suddenly emerging from the valley, a scene of match- 
less beauty burst at once upon the eye. Before them lay the 
dark blue waters of Ijochmarlie, reflecting, as in a mirror, 
every surrounding object, and bearing on its placid, trans- 
parent bosom a fleet of herring-boats, the drapery of whose 
black, suspended nets contrasted, with picture^jjjue effect, the 
white sails of the larger vessels, which were vainly spread to 
catch a breeze. All around, rocks, meadows, woods, and hills 
mingled in wild and lovely irregularity. 

‘ Not a breath was stirring, not a sound was heard, save the 
rushing of a waterfall, the tinkling of some silver rivulet, or 
the calm rippling of the tranquil lake ; now and then, at 
intervals, the fisherman’s Gaelic ditty, chanted as he lay 
stretched on the sand in some sunny nook; or the shrill, 
distant sound of childish glee. How delicious to the feeling 
heart to behold so fair a scene of unsophisticated nature, and 
to listen to her voice alone, breathing the accents of innocence 



814 THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE [partiv 

Thus, even in Scott and Wordsworth themselves, 
the lote of nature is more or less associated with 
their weaknesses. Scott shows it most in the cruder 
compositions of his youth, his perfect powers of mind 
being displayed only in dialogues with which descrip- 
tion has nothing whatever to do. Wordsworth’s dis- 
tinctive work was a war with pomp and pretence, 
and a display of the majesty of simple feelings and 
humble hearts, together with high reflective truth in 
his analysis of the courses of politics and ways of 
men; without these, his love of nature would have 
been comparatively worthless. 

§ 10. ‘ If this be so, it is not well to encourage the 
observance of landscape, any more than other ways 
of dreamily and ineffectually spending time?’ 

Stay a moment. We have hitherto observed this 
love of natural beauty only as it distinguishes one 
man from another, not as it acts for good or evil 
on those minds to which it necessarily belongs. It 
may, on the whole, distinguish weaker men from 
stronger men, and yet in those weaker men may be 
of some notable use. It may distinguish Byron from 
St Bernard, and Shelley from Sir Isaac Newton, and 
yet may, perhaps, be the best thing that Byron and 
Shelley possess — a saving element in them; just as 
a rush may be distinguished from an oak by its bend- 
ing, and yet the bending may bo the saving element 
in the rush, and an admirable gift in its place and 


and joy ! But none of the party who now gazed on it had 
minds capable of being touched with the emotions it was 
calculated to inspire. 

* Henry, inefeed, was rapturous in his expressions of admira- 
tion; but he concluded his panegyrics by wondering his 
brother did not keep a cutter, and resolving to pass a night on 
board one of the herring-boats, that he might eat the fish in 
perfection. 

‘ Lady Juliana thought it might be very pretty, if, instead of 
those frightful rocks and shabby cottages, there could be villas, 
and gardens, and lawns, and conservatories, and summer- 
houses, and statues. 

‘ Miss Bella observed, if it was hers, she would cut down the 
woods, and level the hills, and have races.’ 



CHAP, xvn] THE MORAL OF tAJ^DSOAFE 8lS 

way. So that, although St Bernard journeys all 
day by the Lake of Geneva, and asks at evening 
‘ where it is and Byron learns by it * to love earth 
only for its earthly sake ’ it does not fellow that 
Byron, hating men, was the worse for loving the 
earth, nor that St Bernard, loving men, was the 
better or wiser for being blind to it. And this will 
become still more manifest if we examine somewhat 
farther into the nature of this instinct, as character- 
istic especially of youth. 

§ 11. We saw above that Wordsworth described 
the feeling as independent of thought, and, in the 
particular place then quoted, he therefore speaks of 
it depreciatingly. But in other places he does not 
speak of it depreciatingly, but seems to think the ab- 
sence of thought involves a certain nobleness, as in 
the passage already quoted, Vol. II, Chap. XIV, § 1 ; 

lu such high hour 
Of visitation from the living God 
Thought was not. 

And he refers to the intense delight which he himself 
felt, and which he supposes other men feel, in nature, 
during their thoughtless youth, as an intimation of 
their immortality, and a joy which indicates their 
having come fresh from the hand of God. 

Now, if Wordsworth be right in supposing this 
feeling to be in some degree common to all men, 
and most vivid in youth, we may question if it can 
be entirely explained as I have now tried to explain 
it. For if it entirely depended on multitudes of 
ideas, clustering about a beautiful objqpt, it might 
seem that the youth could not feel it so strongly as 
the man, because the man knows more, and must 
have more ideas to make the garland of. Still less 
can we suppose the pleasure to be of that melancholy 
and languid kind, which Scott defines as ‘ Resig- 
nation ’ and ‘ Content boys being not distinguished 
for either of those characters, but for eager effort, 
and delightsome discontent. If Wordsworth is at all 
1 Childe Harold, canto iii, st. 71. 



816 ^ THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE [paetiv 

right in this matter, therefore, there must surely 
be some other element in the feeling not yet detected. 

§ 12. Now, in a question of this subtle kind, re- 
lating to a period of life when self-examination is 
rare, and expression imperfect, it becomes exceed- 
ingly difficult to trace, with any certainty, the move- 
ments of the minds of others, nor always easy to 
remember those of our own. I cannot, from observ- 
ation, form any decided opinion as to the extent in 
which this strange delight in nature influences the 
hearts of young persons in general; and, in stating 
what has passed in my own mind, I do not mean to 
draw any positive conclusion as to the nature of the 
feeling in other children; but the inquiry is clearly 
one in which personal experience is the only safe 
ground to go upon, though a narrow one; and I will 
make no excuse for talking about myself with refer- 
ence to this subject, because, though there is much 
egotism in the world, it is often the last thing a 
man thinks of doing — and, though there is much 
work to be done in the world, it is often the best 
thing a man can do — ^to tell the exact truth about 
the movements of his own mind; and there is this 
farther reason, that whatever other faculties I may or 
may not possess, this gift of taking pleasure in land- 
scape I assuredly possess in a greater degree than 
most men; it having been the ruling passion of my life, 
and the reason for the choice of its field of labour. 

§ 13. The first thing which I remember, as an 
event in life, was being taken by my nurse to the 
brow of Friar’s Crag on Derwentwater ; the iutense 
joy, mingle^? with aw^e, that I had in looking through 
the hollows in the mossy roots, over the crag, into 
the dark lake, has associated itself more or less with 
all twining roots of trees ever since. Two other 
things I remember, as, in a sort, beginnings of life; 
crossing Shapfells (being let out of the chaise to run 
up the hills), and going through Glenfarg, near Kin- 
ross, in a winter’s morning, when the rooks were 
hung with icicles; these being culminating points 
^in an early life of more travelling than is usually 



CHAP, xvn] THE MORAL OF CANDSCAPE- 81T 

indulged to a child. In such journeyings, whenever 
they brought me near hills, and in all mountain 
ground and scenery, I had a pleasure, as early as 
I can remember, and continuing till I was eighteen 
or twenty, infinitely greater than any which has been 
since possible to me in anything; comparable for 
intensity only to the joy of a lover in being near a 
noble and kind mistress, but no more explicable or 
definable than that feeling of love itself. Only thus 
much I can remember, respecting it, which is im- 
portant to our present subject. 

§ 14. First : it was never independent of associated 
thought. Almost as soon as I could see or hear, I 
had got reading enough to give me associations with 
all kinds of scenery; and mountains, in. particular, 
were always partly confused with those of my favour- 
ite book, Scott’s Monastery ; so that Glenfarg and 
all other glens were more or less enchanted to me, 
filled with forms of hesitating creed about Christie of 
the Clint Hill, and the monk Eustace; and with a 
general presence of White Lady everywhere. I also 
generally knew, or was told by my father and 
mother, such simple facts of history as were neces- 
sary to give more definite and justifiable association 
to other scenes which chiefly interested me, such as 
the ruins of Lochleven and Kenilworth; and thus 
my pleasure in mountains or ruins was never, even 
in earliest childhood, free from a certain awe and 
melancholy, and general sense of the meaning of 
death, though, in its principal influence, entirely 
exhilarating and gladdening. 

§ 15. Secondly ; it was partly dependent on con- 
trast with a very simple and unamused mode of 
general life : I was born in London, and accustomed, 
for two or three years, to no other prospect than 
that of the brick walls over the way; had no brothers 
nor sisters, nor companions; and though I could 
always make myself happy in a quiet way, the beauty 
of the mountains had an additional charm of change 
and adventure which a country-bred child would .not 
have felt. 



318 THE MOEAL OF LANDSCAPE [pabtiv 

§ 16, Thirdly : there was no definite religious 
feeling mingled with it. - I partly believed in ghosts 
smd fairies; but supposed tnat angels belonged en- 
tirely to the Mosaic dispensation, and cannot remem- 
ber any single thought or feeling connected with 
fchem. I believed that God was in heaven, arid could 
hear me and see me; but this gave me neither 
pleasure nor pain, and I seldom thought of it at all. 
I never thought of nature as God’s work, but as a 
separate fact or existence. 

§ 17. Fourthly : it was entirely unaccompanied by 

L owers of reflection or invention. Every fancy that 
had about nature was put into my head by some 
book; and I never reflected about anything till I 
grew older; and then, the more I reflected, the less 
nature was precious to me : I could then make my- 
self happy, by thinking, in the dark, or in the dullest 
scenery ; and the beautiful scenery became less 
essential to my pleasure. 

§ 18. Fifthly : it was, according to its strength, 
inconsistent with every evil feeling, with spite, anger, 
covetousness, discontent, and every other hateful 
passion; but would associate itself deeply with every 
just and noble sorrow, joy, or affection. It had not, 
however, always the power to repress what was in- 
consistent with it; and, though only after stout con- 
tention, might at last be crushed by what it had 
partly repressed. And as it only acted by setting one 
impulse against another, though it had much power 
in moulding the character, it had hardly any in 
strengthening it; it formed temperament, but never 
instilled prir.ciple ; it kept me generally good- 
humoured and kindly, but could not teach me per- 
severance or self-denial : what firmness or principle 
I had was quite independent of it; and it came 
itself nearly as often in the form of a temptation as 
of a safeguard, leading me to ramble over hills when 
I should have been learning lessons, and lose days 
in reveries which I might have spent in doing kind- 
nesses. 

§ 19. Lastly ; although there was no definite re- 



CHAP, xvii] THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE il9 

ligious sentiment mingled with it, there was a con- 
tinual perception of Sanctity in the whole of nature, 
from the slightest thing to the vastest; — ^an instinc- 
tive awe, mixed with delight; an indefinable thrill, 
such as v /0 sometimes imagine to indicate the pre- 
sence of a disembodied spirit. I could only feel this 
perfectly when I was alone ; and then it would often 
make me shiver from head to foot with the joy and 
fear of it, when after being some time away from 
hills, I first got to the shore of a mountain river, 
where the brown water circled among the pebbles, 
or when I saw the first swell of distant land against 
the sunset, or the first low broken wall, covered with 
mountain moss. I cannot in the least describe the 
feeling; but I do not think this is my fault, nor 
that of the English language, for, I am afraid, no 
feeling is describable. If we had to explain even the 
sense of bodily hunger to a person who had never 
felt it, we should be hard put to it for words; and 
this joy in nature seemed to me to come of a sort 
of heart-hunger, satisfied with the presence of a 
Great and Holy Spirit. These feelings remained in 
their full intensity till I was eighteen or twenty, and 
then, as the reflective and practical power increased, 
and the ‘ cares of this world ' gained upon me, faded 
gradually away, in the manner described by Words- 
worth in his Intimations of Immortality, 

§ 20. I cannot, of course, tell how far I am justified 
in supposing that these sensations may be reasoned 
upon as common to children in general. In the same 
degree they are not of course common, otherwise 
children would be, most of them, very digerent from 
what they are in their choice of pleasures. But, as 
far as such feelings exist, I apprehend they are more 
or less similar in their nature and influence; only 
producing different characters according to the ele- 
ments with which they are mingled. Thus, a very 
religious child may give up many pleasures to which 
its instincts lead it, for the sake of irksome duties; 
and an inventive child would mingle its love of nature 
with watchfulness of human sayings and doings : 




THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE [past it 


but I believe the feelings I have endeavoured to 
describe are the pure landscape-instinct; and the 
likelihoods of good or evil resulting from them may 
be reasoned upon as generally indicating the useful- 
ness or danger of the modern love and study of land- 
scape. 

§ 21. And, first, observe that the charm of romantic 
association (§ 14) can be felt only by the modem 
European child. It rises eminently out of the con- 
trast of the beautiful past with the frightful and 
monotonous present; and it depends for its force 
on the existence of ruins and traditions, on the 
remains of architecture, the traces of battle fields, 
and the precursorship of eventful history. The in- 
stinct to which it appeals can hardly be felt in 
America, and every day that either beautifies our 
present architecture and dress, or overthrows a stone 
of mediaeval monument, contributes to weaken it in 
Europe. Of its influence on the mind of Turner and 
Prout, and the permanent results which, through 
them, it is likely to effect, I shall have to speak 
presently. 

§ 22. Again : the influence of surprise in producing 
the delight, is to be noted as a suspicious or evanes- 
cent element in it. Observe, my pleasure was 
chiefly (§ 19) when I first got into beautiful scenery, 
out of London. The enormous influence of novelty — 
the way in which it quickens observation, sharpens 
sensation, and exalts sentiment — is not half enough 
taken note of by us, and is to me a very sorrowful 
matter. I think that what Wordsworth speaks of as 
a glory in |he child, because it has come fresh from 
God^s hands, is in reality nothing more than the 
freshness of all things to its newly opened sight. I 
find that by keeping long away from hills, I can 
in great part still restore the old childish feeling 
about them; and the more I live and work among 
them, the more it vanishes. 

§ 23. This evil is evidently common to all minds; 
Wordsworth himself mourning over it in the same 
poem : 



CHAP, xvn] THE MORAL OP LAI5D8CAPE 821 

Onstom hangs upon us, with a weight 

Heavy as frost, and deep almost as life. 

And if we grow impatient under it, and seek to 
recover the mental energy by more quickly repeated 
and bri^ter novelty, it is all over with our enjoy- 
ment. There is no cure for this evil, any more than 
for the weariness of the imagination already de- 
scribed, but in patience and rest : if we try to obtain 
perpetual change, change itself wdll become monoton- 
ous; and then we are reduced to that old despair, 
‘ If water chokes, what will you drink after it?’ 
And the two points of practical wisdom in this matter 
are, first, to be content with as little novelty as 
possible at a time; and, secondly, to preserve, as 
much as possible in the world, the sources of novelty. 

§ 24. I say, first, to be content with as little 
change as possible. If the attention is awake, and 
the feelings in proper train, a turn of a country road, 
with a cottage beside it, which we have not seen 
before, is as much as we need for refreshment; if 
we hurry past it, and take two cottages at a time, 
it is already too much : hence, to any person who 
has all his senses about him, a quiet walk along not 
more than ten or twelve miles of road a day, is the 
most amusing of all travelling; and all travelling 
becomes dull in exact proportion to its rapidity. 
Going by railroad I do not consider as travelling at 
all; it is merely ‘ being sent ’ to a place, and very 
little different from becoming a parcel; the next step 
to it would of course be telegraphic transport, of 
which, however, I suppose it has been truly said by 
Octave Feuillet, ** 

II y mrait des gens assez hetes pour trouver 9^ amusant.^ 

If we walk more than ten or twelve miles, it breaks 
up the day too much; leaving no time for stopping 
at the stream sides or shady banks, or for any work at 
the end of the day; besides that the last few miles 
are apt to be done in a hurry, and may then be con- 

1 Scknes et Proverbes. La Crise; (Sc^ne en caleche, hors 
Paris). 



m THE MOBAL OF LANDSCAPE [paetiv 

sidered as lost ground. But if, advancing thus 
slowly, after some days we approach any more inter- 
esting scenery, every yard of the changeful ground 
becomes precious and piquant; and the continual 
increase of hope, and of surrounding beauty, affords 
one of the most exquisite enjoyments possible to the 
healthy mind; besides that real knowledge is ac- 
quired of whatever it is the object of travelling to 
learn, and a certain sublimity given to all places, 
so attained, by the true sense of the spaces of earth 
that separate them. A man who really loves travel- 
ling would as soon consent to pack a day of such 
happiness into an hour of railroad, as one who loved 
eating would agree, if it w'ere possible, to concen- 
trate his dinner into a pill. 

§ 25. And, secondly, I say that it is wisdom to 
preserve as much as possible the innocent sources 
of novelty; — not definite inferiorities of one place 
to another, if such can be done away; but differ- 
ences of manners and customs, of language and 
architecture. The greatest effort ought especially to 
be made by all wise and far-sighted persons, in the 
present crisis of civilization, to enforce the distinc- 
tion betw^een wholesome reform, and heartless aban- 
donment of ancestral custom ; between kindly 
fellowship of nation with nation, and ape-hke adop- 
tion, by one, of the habits of another. It is ludi- 
crously woful to see the luxurious inhabitants of 
London and Paris rushing over the Continent (as they 
say, to see it), and transposing every place, as far 
as lies in their power, instantly into a likeness of 
Regent Street and the Rue de la Paix, which they 
ueed not certainly have come so far to see. Of this 
evil I shall have more to say hereafter; meantime 
I return to our main subject. 

§ 26. The next character we have to note in the 
landscape -instinct (and on this much stress is to 
be laid) , is its total inconsistency with all evil passion ; 
its absolute contrariety (whether in the contest it 
were crushed or not) to all care, hatred, envy, 
anxiety, and moroseness. A feeling of this kind is 



CHAP, xvii] THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE 325 

assuredly not one to be lightly repressed, or treated 
with contempt. 

But how, if it be so, the reader asks, can it be 
characteristic of passionate and unprincipled men,, 
like Byron, SheUey, and such others, and not 
characteristic of the noblest and most highly prin- 
cipled men? 

First, because it is itself a passion, and therefore 
likely to be characteristic of passionate men. Secondly,, 
because it is (§ 18) wholly a separate thing from 
moral principle, and may or may not be joined to^ 
strength of will, or rectitude of purpose only, this, 
much is always observable in the men whom it 
characterizes, that, whatever their faults or failings,, 
they fdways understand and love noble qualities of 
character; they can conceive (if not certain phases 
of piety), at all events, self-devotion of the highest 
kind; they delight in all that is good, gracious, and 
noble; and, though warped often to take delight also 
in what is dark or degraded, that delight is mixed 
with bitter self-reproach; or else is wanton, careless, 
or affected, while their delight in noble things is con- 
stant and sincere. 

§ 27. Look back to the two lists given above, § 7. 
I have not lately read anything by Mrs Iladclyffe 
or George Sand, and cannot, therefore, take instances- 
from tl^m. Keats hardly introduced human char- 
acter into his work; but glance over the others, and 

1 Compare the characters of Fleur de Marie and Rigolette, 
in the Mysteres da Paris. I know no other instance in which 
the two tempers are so exquisitely delineated and opposed. 
Read carefully the beautiful pastoral, in the eighth chapter of 
the first Part, where Fleur de Marie is first taken into the 
fields under Montmartre, and compare it with the sixth of the 
second Part, its accurately traced companion sketch, noting 
carefully Rigolette’s ‘ Non, je deteste la campagne.' She does 
not, however, dislike flowers, or birds : ‘ Cette caisse de bois, 
que Rigolette appellait le jardin de ses oiseaux, 4tait remplie 
de terre recouverte de mousse, pendant Thiver. Elle travail- 
lait aupres de la fenStre ouverte, A-demi-voil4e par un verdoy- 
ant rideau de pois de senteur roses, de capuciues oranges, de 
volubilis bleus et blancs.' 



^4 THE MOKAL OF LANDSCAPE [partiv 

note the general tone of their conceptions. Take 
St Pierre’s Virginia, Byron’s Myrrha, Angiolina, and 
Marina, and Eugene Sue’s Fleur de Marie; and out 
of the other list you will only be able to find Pamela, 
Clementina, and, 1 suppose, Clarissa to put beside 
them; and these will not more than match Myrrha 
and Marina; leaving Fleur de Marie and Virginia 
rivalless. Then meditate a little, with all justice 
and mercy, over the two groups of names; and I 
think you will, at last, feel that there is a pathos 
and tenderness of heart among the lovers of nature 
in the second list, of which it is nearly impossible to 
estimate either the value or the danger; that the 
sterner consistency of the men in the first may, in 
great part, have arisen only from the, to them, most 
merciful, appointment of having had religious teach- 
ing or disciplined education in their youth; while 
their want of love for nature, whether that love be 
originally absent, or artificially repressed, is to none 
of them an advantage. Johnson’s indolence. Gold- 
smith’s improvidence. Young’s worldliness, Milton’s 
severity, and Bacon’s servility, might all have been 
less, if they could in any wise have sympathized with 
Byron’s lonely joy in a Jura storm 2, or with Shelley’s 
interest in floating paper boats down the Serchio. 

§ 28. And then observe, farther, as I kept the 
names of Wordsworth and Scott out of the second 
list, I withdrew, also, certain names from the finest; 
and for this reason, that in all the men who are 
named in that list, there is evidently some degree 
of love for nature, which may have been originally 
of more power than we suppose, and may have had 
an infinitely hallowing and protective influence upon 
them. But there also lived certain men of high 

1 I have mot read Clarissa. 

3 It might be thought that Young could have sympathized 
with it. He would have made better use of it, but he would 
mot have had the same delight in it. He turns his solitude to 
good account ; but this is because, to him, solitude is sorrow, 
and his real enjoyment would have been of amiable society, 
and a place at court. 



CHAP, xvn] THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE 825 

intellect in that age who had no love of nature what- 
ever. They do not appear ever to have received the 
smallest sensation of ocular delight from any natural 
scene, but would have lived happily all their lives 
in drawingrooms or studies. And, therefore, in 
these men we shall be able to determine, with the 
greatest chance of accuracy, what the real influence 
of natural beauty is, and what the character of a 
mind destitute of its love. Take, as conspicuous 
instances, Le Sage and Smollett, and you will find, 
in meditating over their works, that they are utterly 
incapable of conceiving a human soul as endowed 
with any nobleness whatever ; their heroes are simply 
beasts endowed with some degree of human intellect ; 
— cunning, false, passionate, reckless, ungrateful, and 
abominable, incapable of noble joy, of noble sorrow, 
of any spiritual perception or hope. I said, * beasts 
with human intellect but neither Gil Bias nor 
Roderick Random reach, morally, anything near the 
level of dogs; while the delight which the writers 
themselves feel in mere filth and pain, with an 
unmitigated foulness and cruelty of heart, is just as 
manifest in every sentence as the distress and indig- 
nation with which pain and injustice are seen by 
Shelley and Byron. 

§ 29. Distinguished from these men by some evi- 
dence of love for nature, yet an evidence much less 
clear than that for any of those named even in the 
first list, stand Cervantes, Pope, and Molifere. It 
is not easy to say how much the character of these 
last depended on their epoch and education; but 
it is noticeable that the first two agree 4hus far in 
temper with Le Sage and Smollett, — that they de- 
light in dwelling upon vice, misfortune, or folly, as 
subjects of amusement; while yet they are distin- 
guished from Le Sage and Smollett by capacity of 
conceiving nobleness of character, only in a humiliat- 
ing and hopeless way ; the one representing all 
chivalry as insanity, the other placing the wisdom 
of man in a serene and sneering reconciliation of good 
with evil. Of Molifere I think very di^ffetently. 



. IHE MOBAL OF LANDSCAPE [paetiv 

Living in the blindest period of the world’s history, 
in the most luxurious city, and the most corrupted 
court, of the time, he yet manifests through all his 
writings an exquisite natural wisdom; a capacity for 
the most simple enjoyment; a high sense of all noble- 
ness, honour, and purity, variously marked through- 
-out his slighter work, but distinctly made the theme 
of his two perfect plays — the Tartuffe and Misan- 
thrope; and in all that he says of art or science he 
has an unerring instinct for what is useful and sin- 
cere, and uses his whole power to defend it, with 
as keen a hatred of everything affected and vain. 
And, singular as it may seem, the first definite 
lesson read to Europe, in that school of simpHcity 
of which Wordsworth was the supposed originator 
among the mountains of Cumberland, was, in fact, 
given in the midst of the court of Louis XIV, and by 
Moliere. The little canzonet, ‘ J’aime mieux ma 
mie ’, is, I believe, the first Wordsworthian poem 
brought forward on philosophical principles, to oppose 
the schools of art and affectation. 

§ 30. I do not know if, by a careful analysis, I 
could point out any evidences of a capacity for the 
love of natural scenery in Moliere stealing forth 
through the slightness of his pastorals; but, if not, 
we must simply sot him aside as exceptional, as a 
man uniting Wordsworth’s philosophy with Le Sage’s 
wit, turned by circumstances from the observance 
of natural beauty to that of human frailty. And 
thus putting him aside for the moment, I think 
cannot doubt of our main conclusion, that, though 
the absence of the love of nature is not an assured 
condemnation, its presence is an invariable sign of 
goodness of heart and justness of moral perception, 
though by no means of moral practice; that in pro- 
portion to the degree in which it is felt, will probably 
be the degree in which all nobleness and beauty of 
character will also be felt; that when it is originally 
absent from any mind, that mind is in many other 
respects hard, worldly, and degraded; that where, 
having been originally present, it is repressed by art 



CHAP. XVII] THE MOBAL OF LANDSCAPE mi 

or education, that repression appears .to have been 
detrimental to the person suffering it; and that 
wherever the feeling exists, it acts for good on the 
character to which it belongs, though, as it may often 
belong to characters weak in other respects, it may 
carelessly be mistaken for a source of evil in them. 

§ 31. And having arrived at this conclusion by 
a review of facts, which I hope it will be admitted, 
whether accurate or not, has at least been candid, 
these farther considerations may confirm our belief 
in its truth. Observe : the whole force of educa- 
tion, until very lately, has been directed in every 
possible way to the destruction of the love of nature. 
The only knowledge which has been considered essen- 
tial among us is that of words, and, next after it, 
of the abstract sciences; while every liking shown 
by children for simple natural history has been either 
violently checked, (if it took an inconvenient form 
for the housemaids), or else scrupulously limited to 
hours of play : so &at it has really been impossible 
for any child earnestly to study the works of God 
but against its conscience; and the love of nature 
has become inherently the characteristic of truants 
and idlers. While also the art of drawing, which 
is of more real importance to the human race than 
that of writing (because people can hardly draw 
anything without being of some use both to them- 
selves and others, and can hardly write anything 
without wasting their own time and that of others), 
— this art of drawing, I say, which on plain and stern 
system should be taught to every child, just as 
writing is — ^has been so neglected and tfbused, that 
there is not tme man in a thousand, even of its 
professed teachers, who knows its first principles : 
and thus it needs much ill-fortune or obstinacy — 
much neglect on the part of his teachers, or rebel- 
lion on his own — before a boy can get le^ve to use 
his eyes or his fingers; so that those who can use 
them are for the most part neglected or rebellious 
lads — ^runaways and bad scholars — passionate, 
erratic, self-willed, and restive against all forms of 



%28 THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE [partiv 

education; while your well-behaved and amiable 
scholars are disciplined into blindness and palsy of 
half their faculties. Wherein there is at once a 
notable ground for what difference we have observed 
between the lovers of nature and its despisers; be- 
tween the somewhat immoral and unrespectable 
Watchfulness of the one, and the moral and respect- 
able blindness of the other. 

§ 82 . One more argument remains, and that, I 
beheve, an imanswerable one. As, by the accident 
of education, the love of nature has been, among 
us, associated with wilfulness ^ so, by the accident 
of time, it has been associated with faithlessness. 
I traced, above, the peculiar mode in which this 
faithlessness was indicated; but I never intended to 
imply, therefore, that it was an invariable concomi- 
tant of the love. Because it happens that, by 
various concurrent operations of evil, we have been 
led, according to those words of the Greek poet 
already quoted, to ‘ dethrone the gods, and crown the 
whirlwind ’, it is no reason that wo should forget 
there was once a time when ‘ the Lord answered 
Job out of the whirlwind And if we now take 
final and full view of the matter, we shall find that 
the love of nature, wherever it has existed, has been 
a faithful and sacred element of human feeling ; that 
is to say, supposing all circumstances otherwise the 
same with respect to two individuals, the one who 
loves nature most will be always found to have more 
faith in Ood than the other. It is intensely diffi- 
cult, owing to the confusing and counter influences 
which always mingle in the data of the problem, to 
make this abstraction fairly; but so far as we can 
do it, so far, I boldly assert, the result is constantly 
the same : the nature- worship will be found to bring 
with it such a sense of the presence and power of a 
Great Spirit as no mere reasoning can either induce 
or controvert; and where that nature-worship is 
innocently pursued — ^i.e. with due respect to other 
claims on time, feeling, and exertion, and associated 
with the higher principles of religion — it becomes 



CHAP, xvn] THE MORAL OF LANDSCAFE m 

the channel of certain sacred truths, which by no 
other means can be conveyed, 

§ 83. This is not a statement which any investiga- 
tion is needed to prove. It comes to us at once 
from the highest of all authority. The greater 
number of the words which are recorded in Scrip- 
ture, as directly spoken to men by the lips dl the 
Deity, are either simple revelations of His ifW,, or 
special threatenings, commands, and promisee ipelit- 
ing to special events. But two passages of God’s 
speaking, one in the Old and one in the New Testa- 
ment, possess, it seems to me, a different character 
from any of the rest, having been uttered, the one 
to effect the last necessary change in the mind of a 
man whose piety was in other respects perfect; and 
the other, as the first statement to all men of the 
principles of Christianity by Christ Himself — mean 
the 38th to 41st chapters of the book of Job, and the 
Sermon on the Mount. Now the first of these pas- 
sages is, from beginning to end, nothing else than a 
direction of the mind which was to be perfected to 
humble observance of the works of God in nature. 
And the other consists only in the inculcation of 
three things: 1st, right conduct; 2nd, looking for 
eternal life; 3rd, trusting God, through watchfulness 
of His dealings with His creation : and the entire 
contents of the book of Job, and of the Sermon on 
the Mount, will be found resolvable simply into these 
three requirements from all men — ^that they should 
act rightly, hope for heaven, and watch God’s won- 
ders and work in the earth; the right conduct being 
always summed up under the three heads of justice ^ 
mercy, and truth, and no mention of any doctrinal 
point whatsoever occurring in either piece of divine 
teaching. 

§ 34. As far as I can judge of the ways of men, 
it seems to me that the simplest and most necessary 
truths are always the last believed; and 1 suppose 
that well-meaning people in general would rather 
regulate their conduct and creed by almost any 
other portion of Scripture whatsoever, than by that 



the moral OF LANDSCAPE [partiv 

Sermon on the Mount which contains the things that 
Christ thought it first necessary for all men to under- 
stand. Nevertheless, I believe the time will soon 
come for the full force of these two passages of 
Scripture to be accepted. Instead of supposing the 
love of nature necessarily connected with the faith- 
lessness of the age, I believe it is connected properly 
with the benevolence and liberty of the age; that it 
is precisely the most healthy element which dis- 
tinctively belongs to us; and that out of it, culti- 
vated no longer in levity or ignorance, but in earnest- 
ness, and as a duty, results will spring of an 
importance at present inconceivable ; and lights 
arise, which, for the first time in man’s history, will 
reveal to him the true nature of his life, the true 
field for his energies, and the true relations between 
him and his Maker. 

§ 35. I will not endeavour here to trace the various 
modes in which these results are likely to be effected, 
for this would involve an essay on education, on 
the uses of natural history, and the probable future 
destiny of nations. Somewhat on these subjects I 
have spoken in other places; and I hope to find time, 
and proper place, to say more. But one or two 
observations may be made merely to suggest the 
directions in which the reader may follow out the 
subject for himself. 

The great mechanical impulses of the age, of which 
most of us are so proud, are a mere passing fever, 
half-speculative, half -childish. People will discover 
at last that royal roads to anything can no more be 
laid in iroik than they can in dust; that there are, 
in fact, no royal roads to anywhere worth going to; 
that if there were, it would that instant cease to be 
worth going to — I mean, so far as the things to be 
obtained are in any way estimable in terms of price. 
For there are two classes of precious things in the 
world : those that God rfves us for nothing — sun, 
air, and life (both mortal life and immortal); and 
the secondarily precious things which He gives us 
for a price : these secondarily precious things. 



CHAP, xvii] THE MOKAL OF LANDSCAPE Ml 

worldly wine and milk, can only be bought for 
definite money; they never can be cheapened. No 
cheating nor bargaining will ever get a single thing 
out of nature’s ‘ establishment ’ at half-price. Do 
we want to be strong? — ^we must work. To be 
hungry? — we must starve. To be happy? — ^we must 
be kind. To be wise? — ^we must look and think. 
No changing of place at a hundred miles an hour, 
nor making of stuffs a thousand yards a minute, will 
make us one whit stronger, happier, or wiser. There 
was always more in the world than men could see, 
walked they ever so slowly ; they will see it no better 
for going fast. And they will at last, and soon too, 
find out that their grand inventions for conquering 
(as they think) space and time, do, in reality, con- 
quer nothing; for space and time are, in their own 
essence, unconquerable, and besides did not want 
any sort of conquering; they wanted using, A fool 
always wants to shorten space and time : a wise man 
wants to lengthen both. A fool wants to kill space 
and kill time : a wise man, first to gain them, then 
to animate them. Your railroad, when you come 
to understand it, is only a device for making the 
world smaller : and as for being able to talk from 
place to place, that is, indeed, well and convenient; 
but suppose you have, originally, nothing to say i. 
We shall be obliged at last to confess, what we 
should long ago have known, that the really precious 
things are thought and sight, not pace. It does a 
bullet no good to go fast; and a man, if he be truly 
a man, no harm to go slow; for his glory is not 
at all in going, but in being. • 

§ 36. ‘ Well; but railroads and telegraphs are so 
useful for communicating knowledge to savage 
nations.’ Yes, if you have any to give them. If 
you know nothing hut railroads, and can communi- 
cate nothing but aqueous vapour and gunpowder — 
what then? But if you have any other thing than 
1 The light-outspeeding telegraph 
Bears nothing on its beam. Emerson. 

See Appendix III. 



1832^ THE MOBAL OF LANDSCAPE [partiv 

those to give, then the railroad is of use only because 
it communicates that other thing ; and the question is 
— ^what that other thing may be. Is it religion? I 
believe if we had really wanted to communicate that^ 
we could have done it in less than 1800 years, with- 
out steam. Most of the good religious communica- 
^tion that I remember, has been done on foot; and 
it cannot be easily done faster than at foot pace. 
Is it science? But what science — of motion, meat, 
and medicine? Well; when you have moved your 
savage, and dressed your savage, fed him with white 
bread, and shown him how to set a limb — what 
next? Follow out that question. Suppose every 
obstacle overcome; give your savage every advan- 
tage of civilization to the full; suppose that you 
have put the Red Indian in tight shoes; taught the 
Chinese how to make Wedgwood’s ware, and to 
paint it with colours that will rub off; and per- 
suaded all Hindoo women that it is more pious to 
torment their husbands into graves than to burn 
themselves at the burial — what next? Gradually, 
thinking on from point to point, we shall come to 
perceive that all true happiness and nobleness are 
near us, and yet neglected by us; and that till we 
have learned how to be happy and noble we have 
not much to tell, even to Red Indians. The delights 
of horse-racing and hunting, of assemblies in the 
night instead of the day, of costly and wearisome 
music, of costly and burdensome dress, of chagrined 
contention for place or power, or wealth, or the eyes 
of the multitude; and all the endless occupation 
without purpose, and idleness without rest, of our 
vulgar world, are not, it seems to me, enjoyments 
we need be ambitious to commxmicate And all real 
and wholesome enjoyments possible to man have 
been just as possible to him, since first he was made 
of the earth, as they are now; and they are possible 
to him chiefly in peace. To watch the corn grow, 
and the blossoms set; to draw hard breath over 
ploughshare or spade; to read, to think, to love, to 
nope, to pray-rthese are the things that make men 



CHAP. XVII] THE MOBAIi OF LANDSCAPE 888 

happy; they have always had the power of doing 
these, they never will have power to do more. The 
world’s prosperity or adversity depends upon our 
knowing and teaching these few things : but upon 
iron, or glass, or electricity, or steam, in no wise. 

§ 87. And I am Utopian and enthusiastic enough 
to believe, that the time will come when the world 
will discover this. It has now made it-^i experiments 
in every possible direction but the right one; and 
it seems that it must, at last, try the, right one, in 
a mathematical necessity. It has tried fighting, and 
preaching, and fasting, buying and selling, pomp 
and parsimony, pride and humiliation — every pos- 
sible manner of existence in which it could con- 
jecture there was any happiness or dignity; and all 
the while, as it bought, sold, and fought, and fasted, 
and wearied itself with policies, and ambitions, and 
self-denials, God had placed its real happiness in the 
keeping of the little mosses of the wayside, and of 
the clouds of the firmament. Now and then a 
wearied king, or a tormented slave, found out where 
the true kingdoms of the world were, and possessed 
himself, in a furrow or two of garden ground, of a 
truly infinite dominion. But the world would not 
believe their report, and went on trampling down the 
mosses, and forgetting the clouds, and seeking hap- 
piness in its own way, until, at last, blundering and 
late, came natural science; and in natural science 
not only the observation of things, but the finding 
out of new uses for them. Of course the world, 
having a choice left to it, went wrong as usual, and 
thought that these mere material uses* were to be 
the sources of its happiness. It got the clouds 
packed into iron cylinders, and made them carry its 
wise self at their own cloud pace. It got weavable 
fibres out of the mosses, and made clothes for itself, 
cheap and fine — ^here was happiness at last. To go 
as fast as the clouds, and manufacture everything 
out of anything — ^here was paradise, indeed I 

§ 38. And now, when, in a little while, it is un- 
paradised again, if there were any other mistake 



fa4 THE MOEAL OF LANDSCAPE [partiv 

r t the world could make, it would of course make 
But I see not that there is any other; and, 
standing fairly at its wits’ end, having found that 
going fast, when it is used to it, is no more paradis- 
iacal than going slow; and that all the prints and 
cottons in Manchester cannot make it comfortable 
in its mind, I do verily believe it will come, finally, 
to understand that God paints the clouds and shapes 
the moss-fibres, that men may be happy in seeing 
Him at His work, and that in resting quietly beside 
Him, and watching His working, and — according to 
the power He has communicated to ourselves, and 
the guidance He grants — in carrying out His pur- 
poses of peace and charity among all His creatures, 
are the only real happinesses that ever were, or will 
be, possible to mankind. 

§ 39. How far art is capable of helping us in such 
happiness we hardly yet know; but I hope to be able, 
in the subsequent parts of this work, to give some 
data for arriving at a conclusion in the matter. 
Enough has been advanced to relieve the reader from 
any lurking suspicion of unworthiness in our sub- 
ject, and to induce him to take interest in the mind 
and work of the great painter who has headed the 
landscape school among us. What farther consider- 
ations may, within any reasonable limits, be put 
before him, respecting the effect of natural scenery 
on the human heart, I will introduce in their proper 
places either as we examine, under Turner’s guid- 
ance, the different classes of scenery, or at the close 
of the whole work; and therefore I have only one 
point more t<^ notice here, namely ^ the exact relation 
between landscape-painting and natural science, 
properly so called. 

§ 40. For it may be thought that I have rashly 
assumed that the Scriptural authorities above quoted 
apply to that partly superficial view of nature which 
is taken by the landscape-painter, instead of to the 
accurate view taken by the man of science. So far 
from there being rashness in such an assumption, 
the whole language, both of the book of Job and 



CHAP. XVII] THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE 88* 

the Sermon on the Mount, gives precisely the view 
of nature which is taken by the uninvestigating 
affection of a humble, but powerful mind. There is- 
no dissection of muscles or counting of elements,, 
but the boldest and broadest glance at the apparent 
facts, and the most magnificent metaphor in express- 
ing them. ‘ His eyes are like the eyelids of the 
morning. In his neck remaineth strength, and sor- 
row is turned into joy before him.’ And in the 
often repeated, never obeyed, command, ‘ Consider 
the lilies of the field observe there is precisely the 
delicate attribution of life which we have seen to be 
the characteristic of the modern view of landscape, 
— ‘ They toil not There is no science, or hint of 
science; no counting of petals, nor display of pro- 
visions for sustenance : nothing but the expression 
of sympathy, at once the most childish, and the most- 
profound, — ‘ They toil not.’ 

§ 41. And we see in this, therefore, that the in- 
stinct which leads us thus to attribute life to the* 
lowest forms of organic nature, does not necessarily 
spring from faithlessness, nor the deducing a moral 
Out of them from an irregular and languid con- 
scientiousness. In this, as in almost all things 
connected with moral discipline, the same results 
may follow from contrai^y causes; and as there are 
a good and evil contentment, a good and evil dis- 
content, a good and evil care, fear, ambition, and 
so on, there are also good and evil forms of this 
sympathy with nature, and disposition to moralize 
over itb In general, active men, of strong sense and 
stern principle, do not care to see anj^hing in a 
leaf, but vegetable tissue, and are so well convinced 
of useful moral truth, that it does not strike them 

1 Compare what is said before in various places of good and 
bad finish, good and bad mystery, &;c. If a man were disposed 
to system-making, he could easily throw together a counter- 
system to Aristotle’s, showing that in all things there were 
two extremes which exactly resembled each other, but of 
which one was bad, the other good ; and a mean, resembling 
neither, but better than the one, and worse than the other. 



THE MORAL OF LANDSCAPE [paetiv 

as a new or notable thing when they find it in any 
way symbolized by material nature; hence there is 
a strong presumption, when first we perceive a 
tendency in any one to regard trees as living, and 
enunciate moral aphorisms over every pebble they 
stumble against, that such tendency proceeds from 
a morbid temperament, likd Shelley’s, or an incon- 
sistent one, like Jaques’s. But when the active life 
is nobly fulfilled, and iiie mind is then raised be- 
yond it into clear and calm beholding of the world 
around us, the same tendency again manifests itself 
in the most sacred way : the simplest forms of 
nature are strangely animated by the sense of the 
Divine presence; the trees and flowers seem all, in 
a sort, children of God; and we ourselves, their 
fellows, made out of the same dust, and greater 
than they only in having a greater portion of the 
Divine power exerted on our frame, and all the 
common uses and palpably visible forms of things, 
beconie subordinate in our minds to their inner glory, 
— to the mysterious voices in which they talk to 
us about God, and the changeful and typical aspects 
by which they witness to us of holy truth, and fill 
us with obedient, joyful, and thankful emotion, 

§ 42. It is in raising us from the first state of 
inactive reverie to the second of useful thought, that 
scientific pursuits are to be chiefly praised. But in 
restraining us at this second stage, and checking tl^b 
impulses towards higher contemplation, they are io 
be feared or blamed. They may in certain minds be 
consistent with such contemplation; but only by 
an effort : ^'n their nature they are always adverse to 
it, having a tendency to chill and subdue the feel- 
ings, and to resolve all things into atoms and 
numbers. For most men, an ignorant enjoyment 
is better than an informed one; it is better to con- 
ceive the sky as a blue dome than a dark cavity, 
and the cloud as a golden throne than a sleety mist, 
I much question whether any one who knows optics, 
however religious he may be, can feel in equal degree 
the pleasure or reverence which an unlettered 



€HAP. xyiii] THE TEACHEES OF ^7 

peasant may leel at the sight of a rainbow. And it 
is mercifully thus ordained, since the law of life, 
for a finite being, with respect to the works of an 
infinite one, must be always an infinite ignorance. 
We cannot fathom the mystery of a single flower, 
nor is it intended that we should; but that the 
pursuit of science should constantly be stayed by 
the love of beauty, and accuracy of knowledge by 
tenderness of emotion. 

§ 43. Nor is it even just to speak of the love of 
beauty as in all respects unscientific; for there is a 
science of the aspects of things, as well as of their 
nature; and it is as much a fact to be noted in 
their constitution, that they produce such and such 
an effect upon the eye or heart (as, for instance, 
that minor scales of sound cause melancholy), as 
that they are made up of certain atoms or vibrations 
of matter. 

It is as the master of this science of Aspects^ that 
I said, some time ago, Turner must eventually be 
named always with Bacon, the master of the science 
of Essence, As the first poe^i who has, in all their 
range, understood the grounds of noble emotion 
which exist in landscape, his future influence will 
be of a still more subtle and important character. 
The rest of this work will therefore be dedicated 
to the explanation of the principles on which he 
composed, and of the aspects of nature which he 
was the first to discern. 


CHAPTER XVIII 

OF THE TEACHERS OF TURNER 

§ 1. The first step to the understanding either 
the mind or position of a great man ought, 1 think, 
to be an inquiry into the elements of his early in- 
struction, and the mode in which he was affected 
by the circumstances of surrounding life. In making 
this inquiry, with respect to Turner, we shall be 
M. P., 111 . z 



TWSi fBACHBES OF TUENER [part xv 

necessarily led to take note of the causes wliich had 
brought landscape-painting into the state in which 
he found it; and, thereford, of those transitions of 
style ifi^liioh, it will be remembered, we overleaped 
(hoping for ^ future opportunity of examining them) 
at the close of the fiEeenth chapter. 

§ 2. And first, I said, it will be remembered, some 
way back, that the relations between Scott, and 
Turner would probably be found to differ very curi- 
ously from those between Dante and Giotto. They 
diiler jprimarily in this — ^that Dante and Giotto, 
Mvixig in a consistent age, were subjected to one and 
the same influence, and may be reasoned about 
almost in similar terms. But Scott and Turner, 
living inconsister^t age, became subjected to 

inconsistoiit influences ; and are at once distinguished 
by notable contrarieties, requiring separate exam- 
ination in each. 

§ 3, Of these, the chief was, that Scott, having 
had the blessing of a totally neglected education, 
was able early to follow most of his noble instincts; 
but Turner, having suffered under the instruction of 
the Royal Academy, had to pass nearly thirty years 
of his life in recovering from its consequences i ; this 
permanent result following for both — ^that Scott 
never was led into any fault foreign to his nature, 
but spoke what was in him, in rugged or idle 
simplicity; erring only where it was natural to err, 
and failing only where it was impossible to succeed. 
But Turner, from the beginning, was led into con- 
strained and unnatural error; diligently -debarred 
from every ordinary help to success. The one thing 
which the '^Academy ought to have taught him 
(namely, the simple and safe use of oil colour), it 
never taught him ; but it carefully repressed his per- 
ceptions of truth, his capacities of invention, and 

1 The education here spoken of is, of course, that bearing 
on the main work of life. In other respects. Turner’s 
education was more neglected than Scott’s, and that not 
beneficently. See the close of the. third of my Edinburgh 
Lectures, 



CHAP, xvni] THE TEACHEBS OF TTJRHEB 3» 

his tendencies of choice. For him it was impossible 
to do right but in a spirit of defiance; and the first 
condition of his progress in learning, was the power 
to forget. 

§ 4. One most important distinction' in their feel- 
ings throughout life was necessitated by this difier- 
ence in early training. Scott gathered what little 
knowledge of architecture he possessed, in wander* 
ings among the rocky walls of QrichtoUn, Loch* 
leven, and Linlithgow, and among the delipate 
pillars of Holyrood, Bowlin, and Melrose. Tufner 
acquired his knowledge of architecture at the desk, 
from academical elevations of the Parthenon apd St 
Paul *8 ; and spent a large portion of his early years 
in taking views of gentlemen’s seats, temple^ of the 
Muses, and other productions of modern taste and 
imagination; being at the same time directed ex- 
clusively to classical sources for all information as 
to the proper subjects of art. Hence, while Scott 
was at once directed to the history of his native 
land, and to the Gothic fields of imagination; and 
his mind was fed in a consistent, natural, and felici- 
tous way from his youth up, poor Turner for a 
long time knew no inspiration but that of Twicken- 
ham; no sublimity but that of Virginia Water. All 
the history and poetry presented to him at the age 
when the mind receives its dearest associations, were 
those of the gods and nations of long ago; and his 
models of sentiment and style were the worst and 
last wrecks of the Renaissance affectations. 

§ 5. Therefore (though utterly free from affecta- 
tion), his early works are full of an enforced artificial- 
ness, and of things ill-done and ill-conceived, be- 
cause foreign to his own instincts; and, throughout 
life, whatever he did, because he thought he ought 
to do it, was wrong; all that he planned on any 
principle, or in supposed obedience to canons of 
taste, was false and abortive : he only did right when 
he ceased to reflect; was powerful only when he 
made no effort, and successful only when he had 
taken no aim. 



340 THE TEACHERS OF TURNER [part iv 

§ 6. And it is one of the most interesting things 
connected with the study of his art, to watch the 
way in which his own strength of English instinct 
breaks gradually through fetter and formalism; how 
from Egerian wells he steals away to Yorkshire 
streamlets; how from Homeric rocks, with laurels 
at the top and caves in the bottom, he climbs, at 
last, to Alpine precipices fringed with pine, and forti- 
fied with the slopes of their own ruins; and how 
from Temples of Jupiter and Gardens of the Hes- 
perides, a spirit in his feet guides him, at last, to the 
lonely arches of Whitby, and bleak sands of Holy Isle. 

§ 7. As, however, is the case with almost all 
inevitable evil, in its effect on great minds, a certain 
good rose even out of this warped education; namely, 
his power of more completely expressing all the 
tendencies of his epoch, and sympathizing with many 
feelings and many scenes which must otherwise have 
been entirely profitless to him. Scott’s mind was 
just as large and full of sympathy as Turner’s; but, 
having been permitted always to take his own choice 
among sources of enjoyment, Scott was entirely in- 
capable of entering into the spirit of any classical 
scene. He was strictly a Goth and a Scot, and his 
sphere of sensation may be almost exactly limited 
by the growth of heather. But Turner had been 
forced to pay early attention to whatever of good 
and right there was even in things naturally distaste- 
ful to him. The charm of early association had been 
cast around much that to other men would have 
been tame : while making drawings of flower-gardens 
and Palladia, n mansions, he had been taught sym- 
pathy with whatever grace or refinement the garden 
or mansion could display, and to the close of life 
could enjoy the delicacy of trellis and parterre, as 
well as the wildness of the wood and the moorland; 
and watch the staying of the silver fountain at its 
appointed height in the sky, with an interest as 
earnest, if not as intense, as that with which he 
followed the crash of the Alpine cataract into its 
clouds of wayward raga 



CBAP. xxrin] THE TEACHERS OE TURNER 341 

§ 8. The distinct losses to be weighed against this 
gain are, first, the waste of time during youth in 
painting subjects of no interest whatsoever, — sparks, 
villas, and ugly architectu’-e in general : secondly, 
the devotion of his utmost strength in later years 
to meaningless classical compositions, such as the 
Pali and Rise of Carthage, Bay of Baiae, Daphne and 
Leucippus, and such others, which, with infinite 
accumulation of material, are yet utterly heartless 
and emotionless, dead to the very root of thought, 
and incapable of producing wholesome or useful 
effect on any human mind, except only as exhibi- 
tions of technical skill and graceful arrangement : 
and, lastly, his incapacity, to the close of life, of 
entering heartily into the spirit of any elevated archi- 
tecture; for those Palladian and classical buildings 
which he had been taught that it was right to 
admire, being wholly devoid of interest, and in their 
own formality and barrenness quite unmanageable, 
he was obliged to make them manageable in his pic- 
tures by disguising them, and to use all kinds of 
playing shadows and glittering lights to obscure their 
ugly details; and as in their best state such build- 
ings are white and colourless, he associated the idea 
of whiteness with perfect architecture generally, and 
was confused and puzzled when he found it grey. 
Hence he never got thoroughly into the feeling of 
Gothic ; its darkness and complexity embarrassed 
him; he was very apt to whiten by way of idealiz- 
ing it, and to cast aside its details in order to get 
breadth of delicate light. In Venice, and the towns 
of Italy generally, he fastened on the wrong build- 
ings, and used those which he chose merely as kind 
of white clouds, to set off his brilliant groups of 
boats, or burning spaces of lagoon. In various other 
minor ways, which we shall trace in their proper 
place, his classical education hindered or hurt him; 
but I feel it very difficult to say how far the loss was 
balanced by the general grasp it gave his mind; nor 
am I able to conceive what would have been the 
result, if his aims had been made at once narrower 



342 THE TEACHERS OF TURNER [part iv 

and more natural, and he had been led in his youth 
to delight in Gothic legends instead of classical 
mythology; and, instead of the porticoes of the Par- 
thenon, had studied in the aisles of Notre Dame. 

§ 9. It is still more difficult to conjecture whether 
he gathered most good or evil from the pictorial art 
which surrounded him in his youth. What that art 
was, and how the European schools had arrived at 
it, it now becomes necessary briefly to inquire. 

It will be remembered that, in the 14th chapter, 
we left our mediaeval landscape (§ 18) in a state of 
severe formality, and perfect subordination to the 
interest of figure-subject. I will now rapidly trace the 
mode and progress of its emancipation. 

§ 10. The formalized conception of scenery re- 
mained little altered until the time of Raphael, being 
only better executed as the knowledge of art 
advanced; that is to say, though the trees were still 
stiff, and often set one on each side of the principal 
figures, their colour and relief on the sky were 
exquisitely imitated, and all groups of near leaves 
and flowers drawn with the most tender care, and 
studious botanical accuracy. The better the sub- 
jects were painted, however, the more logically 
absurd they became : a background wrou^t in 
Chinese confusion of towers and rivers, was in early 
times passed over carelessly, and forgiven for the 
sake of its pleasant colour; but it appealed some- 
what too far to imaginative indulgence when Ghir- 
landajo drew an exquisite perspective view of Venice 
and her lagoons behind an Adoration of the Magi i ; 
and the impossibly small boats which might be par- 
doned in a mere illuniination, representing the 
miraculous draught of fishes, became, whatever may 
be said to the contrary, inexcusably absurd in 
Raphael’s fully realized landscape; so as at once to 
destroy the credibility of every circumstance of the 
event. 

§ 11. A certain charm, however, attached itself to 
many forms of this landscape, owing to their very 
1 The picture is iu the TJffizi of Florence. 



CHAP, ifviii] THE TEACHERS OF TURNER 343 

unnaturalness, as I have endeavoured to explain 
already in the last chapter of the second volume, 
§§ 9 to 12; noting, however, there, that it was in 
no wise to be made a subject of imitation; a con- 
clusion which I have since seen more and more 
ground for holding finally. The longer I think over 
the subject, the more I perceive that the pleasure 
we take in such unnatural landscapes is intimately 
connected with our habit of regarding the New Testa- 
ment as a beautiful poem, instead of a statement 
of plain facts. He who believes thoroughly that the 
events are true will expect, and ought to expect, real 
olive copse behind real Madonna, and no sentimental 
absurdities in either. 

§ 12. Nor am I at all sure how far the delight 
which we take (when I say we^ I mean, in general, 
lovers of old sacred art) in such quaint landscape, 
arises from its peculiar falsehood, and how far from 
its peculiar truth. For as it falls into certain errors 
more boldly, so, also, what truth it states, it states 
more firmly, than subsequent work. No engravings, 
that I know, render the backgrounds of sacred pic- 
tures with sufficient care to enable the reader to 
judge of this matter unless before the works them- 
selves. I have, therefore, engraved, on the opposite 
page, a bit of the background of Raphael’s Holy 
Family, in the Tribune of the Uffizi, at Florence. I 
copied the trees leaf for leaf, and the rest of the work 
with the best care I could; the engraver, Mr. Army- 
tage, has admirably rendered the delicate atmosphere 
which partly veils the distance. Now I do not know 
how far it is necessary to such pleasure ^s we receive 
from this landscape, that the trees should be both 
so straight and formal in stem, and should have 
branches no thicker than threads; or that the out- 
lines of the distant hills should approximate so closely 
to those on any ordinary Wedgwood’s china pattern. 
I know that, on the contrary, a great part of the 
pleasure arises from the sweet expression of air and 
sunshine; from the traceable resemblance of the 
city and tower to Florence and F4sole ; from the fact 



^ TB:E teachers of turner [tAMav 

ihat, though the boughs are too thin, the lines of 
rami&oation are true and beautiful; and from the 
expression of continually varied form in the clusters 
of leafage. And although all lovers of sacred art 
would shrink in horror from the idea of substituting 
for such a landscape a bit of Cuyp or Rubens, I do 
^not think that the horror they feel is because Cuyp 
and Rubens’s landscape is tTuer^ but because it ia 
coarseT and more vulgar in associated idea than 
Raphael’s; and 1 think it possible that the true forms 
of hills, and true thicknesses of boughs, might be 
tenderly stolen into this background of Raphael’s 
without giving oSence to any one. 

§ 13. Take a Acme what more definite instance. 
The rook in Rg. 5 [Plate B], at the side, is one put 
by Ghirlandajo into the background of his Baptism of 
Christ. I have no doubt Ghirlandajo ’s own rocks 
and trees are better, in several respects, than those 
here represented, since I have copied them from one 
of Lasmio’s execrable engravings; still, the harsh 
outline and generally stiff and uninventful blankness 
of the design are true enough, and characteristic of 
all rock-painting of the period. In the plate opposite 
I have etched i the outline of a fragment of one of 
Turner’s cliffs, out of his drawing of Bolton Abbey; 
and it does not seem to me that, supposing them 
properly introduced in the composition, the sub- 
stitution of the soft natural lines for the hard un- 
natural ones would make Ghirlandajo ’s background 
one whit less sacred. 

§ 14. But, be this as it may, the fact is, as ill 
luck would have it, that profanity of feeling, and 
skill in art, increased together; so that we do not 
find the backgrounds rightly painted till the figures 
become irreligious and feelingless; and hence we 
associate necessarily the perfect landscape with want 
of feeling. The first great innovator was either 

1 This etching is prepared for receiving mezzotint in the 
next volume ; it is therefore much heavier in line, especially in 
the water, than I should have made it, if intended to be coin- 
plete as it is, in the 1st edition.] 









OF TUap 84^ 

Masaccio or Filippino Lippi : iheir works con 
fused togethei^'jKi €tie CJiapel of the Carnune, that^-" 
know not to whom I may attribute — or whether, 
without being immediately quarrelled with, and con- 
ij^dieted, I may attribute to anybodj^ — the 4and- 
soape background of the fresco of the Tribute Money. 
But that background, with on# or two other frag- 
ments in the same chapel, is far in advance ot euI 
other work I have seen of the period, in expression 
of the rounded contours and large slopes of hills, 
and the association of their summits with the clouds. 
The opposite engraving will give some better idea of 
its character than can be gained from the outlines 
commonly published; though the dark spaces, which 
in the original are deep blue, come necessarily some- 
what too harshly on the eye when translated into 
light and shade. I shall have occasion to speak with 
greater speciality of this background in examining 
the forms of hills ; meantime, it is only as an isolated 
work that it can be named in the history of pictorial 
progress, for Masaccio died too young to carry out 
his purposes ; and the men around him were too 
ignorant of landscape to understand or take advan- 
tage of the little he had done. Raphael, though he 
borrowed from him in the human figure, never seems 
to have been influenced by his landscape, and retains 
either, as in Plate XI, the upright formalities of 
Perugino; or, by way of being natural, expands his 
distances into flattish flakes of hill, nearly formless, 
as in the backgrounds of the Charge to Peter and 
Draught of Fishes; and thenceforward the Tuscan 
and Roman schools grew more and mo»e artificial, 
and lost themselves finally under round-headed 
niches and Corinthian porticoes. 

§ 1$. It needed, therefore, the air of the northern 
mountains and of the sea to brace the hearts of men 
to iho developement of the true landscape schools. I 
sketched by chance one evening the line of the 
Apennines from the ramparts of Parma, and I have 
put the rough note of it, and the sky that was over 
it, in Plate XIV, and next to this (Plate XV) a 



346 THE TEACHERS OF TURNER [part iv 

moment of sunset, behind the Euganean hills at 
Venice. I shall have occasion to refer to both here- 
after; but they have some interest here as types of 
the kind of scenes which were daily set before the 
eyes of Correggio and Titian, and of the sweet free 
spaces of sky through which rose and fell, to them, 
the coloured rays of the morning and evening. 

§ 16. And they are connected, also, with the forms 
of landscape adopted by the Lombardic masters, in 
a very curious way. We noticed that the Flemings, 
educated entirely in flat land, seemed to be always 
contented with the scenery it supplied ; and we 
.should naturally have expected that Titian and Correg- 
gio living in the midst of the levels of the lagoons, 
and of the plain of Lombardy, would also have ex- 
pressed, in their backgrounds, some pleasure in such 
level sp^ery, associated, of course, with the sub- 
limity 'd£ the far-away Apennine, Euganean, or Alp. 
But not a whit. The plains of mulberry and maize, 
of sea and shoal, by which they were surrounded, 
never occur in their backgrounds but in cases of 
necessity; and both of them, in all their important 
landscapes, bury themselves in wild wood; Correggio 
delighting to relieve with green darkness of oak and 
ivy the golden hair and snowy flesh of his figures; 
and Titian, whenever the choice of a scene was in 
his power, retiring to the narrow glens and forests 
of Cadore. 

§ 17. Of the vegetation introduced by both, I shall 
have to speak at length in the course of the chapters 
on Foliage; meantime, I give in Plat#, XVI one of 
Titian’s slightest bits of background, from one of the 
frescoes in the little chapel behind St Antonio, at 
Padua, which may be compared more conveniently 
than any of his more elaborate landscapes with the 
purist work from Raphael. For m both these ex- 
amples the trees are equally slender and delicate, 
only the formality of mediaeval art is, by Titian, 
entirely abandoned, and the old conception of the 
aspen grove and meadow done away with for ever. 
We are now far from cities : the painter takes true 







\lll ■ 


CHAP, xviii] THE TEACHERS OF TURNER 347 

delight in the desert; the trees grow wild and free; 
the sky also has lost its peace, and is writhed into 
folds of motion, closely impendent upon earth, and 
somewhat threatening, through its solemn light. 

§ 18. Although, however, this example is character- 
istic of Titian in its wildness, it is not so in its loose- 
nr 88. It is only in the distant backgrounds of his 
slightest work, or when he is in a hurry, that Titian 
is vague : in all his near and studied work he com- 
pletes every detail with scrupulous care. The nexi^j 
Plate, XVII, a background of Tintoret’s, from h^^ 
picture of the Entombment at Parma, is more enj 
tirely characteristic of the Venetians. Some mis^ 
takes made in the reduction of my drawing during 
the course of engraving have cramped the curves 
of the boughs and leaves, of which I will give the 
t^yue outline farther on; meantime the subject, which 
is that described in § 16. of the chapter on Penetra- 
tive Imagination, Vol. II, will just as well answer the 
purpose of exemplifying the Venetian love of gloom 
and wildness, united with perfect definition of detail. 
Every leaf and separate blade of grass is drawn; 
but observe how tlie blades of grass are broken, hd\v 
completely the aim at expression of faultlessness and 
felicity has been withdrawn, as contrary to the laws 
of the existent world. 

§ 19. From this great Venetian school of landscape 
Turner received much important teaching — almost 
the only healthy teaching which he owed to pre- 
ceding art. The designs of the Liber Studiorum are 
founded first on nature, but in many cases modified 
by forced imitation of Claude, and /ontf imitation oi 
Titian. AH the worst and feeblest studies in the 
book — as the pastoral with the nymph playing the 
tambourine, that with the long bridge seen through 
trees, and with the flock of goats on the walled road 
— owe the principal part of their imbecilities tc 
Claude; another group (Solway Moss, Peat Bog, 
Lauffenbourg, &c.) is taken witR hardly any modifi- 
cation by pictorial influence, straight from nature; 
and the finest works in the book — the Grande Char- 



348 THB*TEACHERS OF TURNER [paet iv 

treuse, Rizpah, Jason, Cephalus, and one or two 
more — are strongly under the influence of Titian. 

§ 20. The Venetian school of landscape expired 
with Tintoret, in the year 1594; and the sixteenth 
century closed, like a grave, over the great art of 
the world. There is no entirely sincere or great art 
in the seventeenth century. Rubens and Rembrandt 
are its two greatest men, both deeply stained by the 
errors and affectations of their age. The influence 
of the Venetians hardly extended to them; the 
tower of the Titianesque art fell southwards; and 
pn the dust of its ruins grew various art- weeds, such 
Its Domenichino and the Carraccis. Their landscape, 
which may in few words be accurately defined as 
‘ Soum of Titian *, possesses no single merit, nor any 
ground for the forgiveness of demerit; they are to 
be named only as a link through which the Venetian 
influence came dimly down to Claude and Salvator; 

§ 21, Salvator possessed real genius, but was 
crushed by misery in his youth, and by fashionable 
society in his age. He had vigorous animal life, and 
considerable invention, but no depth either of thought 
or‘ perception. He took some hints directly from 
nature, and expressed some conditions of the gro- 
tesque of terror with original power ; but his baseness 
of thought, and bluntness of sight, were unconquer- 
able; and his works possess no value whatsoever 
for any person versed in the walks of noble art. 
They had little, if any, influence on Turner; if any, 
it was in blinding him for some time to the grace 
of tree trunks, and making him tear them too much 
into splinters. 

§ 22. Not so Claude, who may be considered as 
Turner’s principal master. Claude’s capacities were 
of the most limited kind; but he had tenderness of 
perception, and sincerity of purpose, and he effected 
a revolution in art. This revolution consisted mainly 
in setting the sun in heaven i. Till Claude’s time 

1 Compare Vol. I, Part II, Sec. I, Chap. VII. I repeat 
here some things that were then said ; but it is necessary now 
to review them in connection with Turner’s education, as well 
as for the sake of enforcing them by illustration. 




Ifac, 



CHAP, xvm] THE TEACHERS OF TURNER 349 

no one had seriously thought of painting the sun but 
conventionally; that is to say, as a red or yellow 
star, (often) with a face in it, under which type it 
was constantly represented in illumination; else it 
was kept out of the picture, or introduced in frag- 
mentary distances, breaking through clouds with 
almost definite rays. Perhaps the honour of having 
first tried to represent the real effect of the sun in 
landscape belongs to Bonifazio, in his pictures of 
the camps of Israel i. Rubens followed in a kind of 
bravado, sometimes making the rays issue from any- 
thing but the orb of the sun; — here, for instance, 
fig. 6 [Plate B] , is an outline of the position of the sun 
(at s) with respect to his own rays, in a sunset behind 
a tournament in the Louvre : and various interesting 
effects of sunlight issuing from the conventional face- 
filled orb occur in contemporary missal-painting; 
fo? instance, very richly in the Harleian MS Brit. 
Mus. 3469. But all this was merely indicative of 
the tendency to transition which may always be 
traced in any age before the man comes who is to 
accomplish the transition. Claude took up the new 
idea seriously, made the sun his subject, and painted 
the effects of misty shadows cast by his rays over 
the landscape, and other delicate aerial transitions, 
as no one had ever done before, and, in some re- 
spects, as no one has done in oil colour since. 

§ 28. ‘ But,, how, if this were so, could his capa- 
cities be of the meanest order?’ Because doing one 
thing well, or better than others have done it, does 
not necessarily imply large capacity. Capacity means 
breadth of glance, understanding of the •relations of 
things, and invention, and these are rare and pre- 
cious; but there are very few men tvho have not 
done something, in the course of their lives, better 
than other people. I could point out many en- 
gravers, draughtsmen, and artists, who have each a 
particular merit in their manner, or particular field 
of perception, that nobody else has, or ever had. But 
this does not make them great men, it only indicates 
a small special capacity of some kind : and all the 
1 Now in the old library of Venice. 



380 .''i'THE TEACHERS OF TURNER [part iv 

smatkr if tbe gift be very peculiar and single ; for 
a great man never so limits himself to one thing, as 
that we shall be able to say, ‘ That is all he can do 
If Claude had been a great man he would not have 
been so steadfastly set on painting effects of sun; 
he would have looked at all nature, and at all art, 
and would have painted sun effects somewhat worse, 
and nature universally much better. 

§ 24. Such as he was, however, his discovery of 
the way to make pictures look warm was very de- 
lightful to the shallow connoisseurs of the age. Not 
that they cared for sunshine; but they liked seeing 
jugglery. They could not feel Titian’s noble colour, 
nor Veronese’s noble composition; but they thought 
it highly amusing to see the sun brought into a 
picture : and Claude’s works were bought and de- 
lighted in by vulgar people then, for their real-looking 
suns, as pictures are now by vulgar people for having 
real timepieces in their church towers. 

§ 25. But when Turner arose, with an earnest de- 
sire to paint the whole of nature, he found that the 
existence of the sun was an important fact, and by 
no means an easily manageable one. He loved sun- 
shine for its own sake; but he could not at first 
paint it. Most things else, he would more or less 
manage without much technical difficulty; but the 
burning orb and the golden haze could not, somehow, 
be got out of the oil paint. Naturally he went , to 
Claude, who really had got them out of oil paint; 
approached him with great reverence, as having done 
that which seemed to Turner most difficult of all 
technical matters, and he became his faithful dis- 
ciple. How much ho learned from him of manipula- 
tion, I cannot tell; but one thing is certain, that 
he never quite equalled him in that particular forte 
of his. I imagine that Claude’s way of laying on oil 
colour was so methodical that it could not possibly 
be imitated by a man whose mechanism was inter- 
fered with by hundreds of thoughts and aims totally 
different from Claude’s; and, besides, I suppose that 
certain useful principles in the management of paint. 




XV 





CHA.P. xvm] TBB teachers OF JUBNEB 351 

of which our schools are now whoHy ignorant, had 
come down as far as Claude, from the Venetians. 
Turner at last gave up the attempt, and adopted a 
manipulation of his own, which indeed effected 
certain objects attainable in no other way, but which 
still was in many respects unsatisfactory, dangerous, 
and deeply to be regretted. 

§ 26. But meantime his mind had been strongly 
warped by Claude’s futilities of conception. It was 
impossible to dwell on such works for any length of 
time without being grievously harmed by them; and 
the style of Turner’s compositions was for ever after- 
wards weakened or corrupted. For, truly, it is 
almost beyond belief into what depth of absurdity 
Claude plunges continually in his most admired de- 
signs. For instance; undertaking to paint Moses at 
the Burning Bush, he represents a graceful landscape 
with a city, a river, and a bridge, and plenty of tall 
trees, and the sea, and numbers of people going 
about their business and pleasure in every direction; 
and the bush burning quietly upon a bank in the 
corner; rather in the dark, and not to be seen with- 
out close inspection. It would take some pages of 
close writing to point out, one by one, the inanities 
of heart, soul, and brain which such a conception 
involves; the ineffable ignorance of the nature of 
the event, and of the scene of it; the incapacity of 
conceiving anything, even in ignorance, which should 
be impressive; the dim, stupid, serene, leguminous 
enjoyment of his sunny afternoon — burn the bushes 
as much as they liked — these I leave the reader to 
think over at his leisure, either before ^le picture 
in Lord Ellesmere’s gallery, or the sketch of it in 
the Liber Veritatis, But all these kinds of fallacy 
sprung more or less out of the vices of the time in 
which Claude lived; his own peculiar character 
reaches beyond these, to an incapacity of understand- 
ing the main point in anything he had to represent, 
down to the minutest detail, which is quite un- 
equalled, as far as I know, in human nugatoriness. 
For instance; here, in Fig. 7, is the head, with half 



362 THE TEACHERS OF TURNER [part iv 

the body, of Eneas drawing his Bow, from No. 180 
of the Liber Veritatis. Observe, the string is too 
long by half; for if the bow were unbent, it would 
be two feet longer than the whole bow. Then the 
ft|*row is too long by half, has too heavy a head by 
half; and finally, it actually is under the bow -hand, 
instead of above it. Of the ideal and heroic refine- 
ment of the head and drapery I will say nothing; 
but look only at the wretched archery, and consider 
if it would be possible for any child to draw the thing 
with less understanding, or to make more mistakes 
in the given compass 

§ 27. And yet, exquisite as is Claude’s instinct for 
blunder, he has not strength of mind enough to 
blunder in a wholly original manner, but must needs 
falter out of his way to pick up other people’s 
puerilities and be absurd at second-hand. I have 
been obliged to laugh a little — though I hope re.er- 
ently — at Ghirlandajo’s landscapes, which yet we 
saw had a certain charm of quaintness in them when 
contrasted with his grand figures; but could any one 
have believed that Claude, with all the noble land- 
scapes of Titian set before him, and all nature round 
about him, should yet go back to Ghirlandajo for 
types of form. Yet such is the case. I said that 
the Venetian influence came dimly down to Claude : 
but the old Florentine influence came clearly. The 
Claudesque landscape is not, as so commonly sup- 

3 My old friend Blackwood complains bitterly, in his last 
number, of my having given this illustration at one of ray late 
lectures, saying, that I ‘ have a disagreeable knack of finding 
out the joints in my opponent’s armour and that ‘ I never 
fight for love I never do. I fight for truth, earnestly, and 
in no wise for jest ; and against all lies, earnestly, and in no 
wise for love. They complain that ‘ a noble adversary is not 
in Mr Ruskin’s way ’. No ; a noble adversary never was, 
never will be. With all that is noble I have been, and shall 
be, in perpetual peace ; with all that is ignoble and false ever- 
lastingly at war. And as for these Scotch houryeoU yevtils- 
hommes, with their ‘Tu n’as pas la patience que je pare’, let 
them look to their fence. But truly, if they will tell me 
where Claude’s strong points are, I will strike there, and be 
thankful. 




yi/./*.. ///.| 


Pla'ii- X\'1 ■ Pari \ Nailkvm'^m 


I /’. 





CHAP, xvm] THE TEACHERS OF TURNER 353 

posed, an idealized abstract of the nature about 
Rome. It is an ultimate condition of the Florentine 
conventional landscape, more or less softened by re- 
ference to nature. Fig. 8 [Plate B] , from No. 145 
of the Liber Veritatis, is sufficiently characteristic of 
Claude’s rock-drawing; and compared with fig. 5 
[Plate B] , will show exactly the kind of modification 
he made on old and received types. We shall see 
other instances of it hereafter. 

Imagine this kind of reproduction of whatever 
other people had done worst, and this kind of mis- 
understanding of all that he saw himself in nature, 
carried out in Claude’s trees, rocks, ships — in every- 
thing that he touched — and then consider what kind 
of school this work was for a young and reverent dis- 
ciple. As I said, Turner never recovered the effects 
of it; his compositions were always mannered, life- 
l(^s, and even foolish; and he only did noble things 
TOon the immediate presence of nature had over- 
powered the reminiscences of his master. 

§ 28. Of the influence of Gaspar and Nicolo Poussin 
on Turner, there is hardly anything to be said, nor 
much respecting that which they had on landscape 
generally. Nicolo Poussin had noble powers of de- 
sign, and might have been a thoroughly great painter 
had he been trained in Venice; but his Roman educa- 
tion kept him tame ; his trenchant severity was 
contrary to the tendencies of the ago, and had few 
imitators compared to the dashing of Salvator, and 
the mist of Claude. Those few imitators adopted 
his manner without possessing either his science or 
invention; and the Italian school of landscape soon 
expired. Reminiscences of him occur ^ometimes in 
Turner’s c(jrapositions of sculptured stones for fore- 
ground; and the beautiful Triumph of Flora, in the 
Louvre, probably first showed Turner the use of 
definite flower, or blossom-painting, in landscape. 
I doubt if he took anything from Gaspar; whatever 
he might have learned from him respecting masses of 
foliage and gplden distances, could have been learned 
better, and, I believe, was learned, from Titian. 

M. P., III. 


A A 



THE TEACHERS OP TURNER [part iv 

§ 29. Meantime, a lower, but more living school 
had developed itself in the north; Ouyp had painted 
sunshine as truly as Claude, gilding with it a more 
homely, but far more honestly conceived landscape; 
and the effects of light of De Hooghe and Rembrandt 
presented examples of treatment to which southern 
art could show no parallel. Turner evidently studied 
these with the greatest care, and with great benefit in 
every way; especially this, that they neutralized 
the idealisms of Claude, and showed the young 
painter what power might be in plain truth, even of 
the most familiar kind. He painted several pictures 
in imitation of these masters; and those in which, 
he tried to rival Cuyp are healthy and noble works, 
being, in fact, just what most of Cuyp’s own pictures 
are-T— faithful studies of Dutch boats in calm weather, 
on smooth water. De Hooghe was too precise, and 
Rembrandt too dark, to be successfully or affectiqn- 
ately followed by him ; but he evidently learned much 
from both. 

§ 30. Finally, he painted many pictures in the 
manner of Vandevelde (who was the accepted 
authority of his time in sea painting), and received 
much injury from him. To the close of his life, 
Turner always painted the sea too grey, and too 
opaque, in consequence of his early study of Vande- 
velde. He never seemed to perceive colour so truly 
in the sea as he saw it elsewhere. But he soon dis- 
covered, the poorness of Vandevelde ’s forms of waves, 
and raised their meanly divided surfaces into massive 
surge, effecting rapidly other changes, of which more 
in another place. 

Such was the art to which Turner, in early years, 
devoted his most earnest thoughts. More or less 
respectful contemplation of Reynolds, Loutherbourg, 
Wilson, Gainsborough, Morland, and Wilkie, was 
incidentally mingled with his graver study; and he 
maintained a questioning watchfulness of even the 
smallest successes of his brother artists of the modern 
landscape school. It remains for us only to note the 
position of that living school when Turner, helped or 




XVII . 




cHAP.xvm] THE TEACHERS QF TURNER 355 

misled, as the case may be, by the study of the older 
artists, be^an to consider ifvhat remained f^r him to 
do, or design. 

§ 31. The dead schools of landscape, composed of 
the works we have just been examining, were broadly 
divisible into northern and southern : the Dutch 
schools, more or less natural, but vulgar; the Italian, 
more or Igss elevated, but absurd. There was a 
certain foolish elegance in Claude, and a dull dignity 
in Caspar; but then their work resembled nothing 
that ever existed in the world. On the contrary, a 
canal or cattle piece of Cuyp’s had many veracities 
about it; but they \rere, at best, truths of the ditch 
and dairy. The grace of Nature, or her gloom, her 
tender and sacred seclusions, or her reach of power 
and wrath, had never been painted; nor had any- 
t^ng been painted yet in true love of it; for both 
Dutch and Italians agreed in this, that they always 
painted for the picture's sake, to show how well they 
could imitate sunshine, arrange masses, or articulate 
straws — never because they loved the scene, or 
wanted to carry away some memory of it. 

And thus, all that landscape of the old masters 
is to be considered merely as a struggle of expiring 
skill to discover some new direction in which to dis- 
play itself. There was no love of nature in the age; 
only a desire for something new. Therefore those 
schools expired at last, leaving a chasm of nearly utter 
emptiness between them and the true moderns, out 
of which chasm the new school rises, not engrafted 
on that old one, but, from the very base of all 
things, beginning with mere washes o^ Indian ink, , 
touched upon with yellow and brown; and gradually 
feeling its way to colour. 

But this infant school differed inherently from that 
ancienter one, in that its motive was love. However 
feeble its efforts might be, they were for the sake 
of the nature, not of the picture, and therefore, 
having this germ of true life, it grew and throve. 
Robson did not paint purple hills because he wanted 
to show how he could lay on purple ; but because ho 
M. P., III. AA2 



356 THE TEACHERS OF TURNER [part iv 

truly loved their dark peaks. Fielding did not paint 
downs to show how dexterously he could sponge out 
mists; but because he loved downs. 

This modern school, therefore, became the only 
true school of landscape which has yet existed; the 
artificial Claude and Caspar work may be cast aside 
out of our way — as I have said in my Edinburgh 
lectures, under the general title of ‘ pastjralism ’, — 
and from the last landscape of Tintoret, if we look 
for Zi/e, we must pass at once to the first of Turner, 

§ 32. What help Turner received from this or 
that companion of his youth is of no importance to 
any one now. Of course every great man is always 
being helped by everybody for his gift is to get 
good out of all things and all persons; and also 
there were two men associated with him in early 
study, who showed high promise in the same field, 
Cousen and Girtin (especially the former), a^d 
there is no saying what these men might have done 
had they lived; there might, perhaps, have been 
a struggle between one or other of them and Turner, 
as between Giorgione and Titian. But they lived 
not; and Turner is the only great man whom the 
school has yet produced — quite great enough, as we 
shall see, for all that needed to be done. To him, 
therefore, we now finally turn, as the sole object of 
our inquiry. I shall first reinforce, with such addi- 
tions as they need, those statements of his general 
principles which I made in the first volume, but 
could not then demonstrate fully, for want of time 
to prepare pictorial illustration; and then proceed 
to examine,^ piece by piece, his representations of 
the facts of nature, comparing them, as it may seem 
expedient, with what had been accomplished by 
others. 

I cannot close this volume without alluding briefly 

1 His first drawing-master was, I believe, that Mr Lowe, 
whose daughters, now aged and poor, have, it seems to me, 
some claim on public regard, being connected distantly with 
the memory of Johnson, and closely with that of Turner. 



CHAP. XVIII] THE TEACHERS OF TURNER 357 

to a subject of different interest from any that have 
occupied us in its pages. For it may, perhaps, seem 
to a general reader heartless and vain to enter zeal- 
ously into questions about our arts and pleasures in 
a time of so great public anxiety as this. 

But he will find, if he looks back to the sixth 
paragraph of the opening chapter of the last volume, 
some stal^ment of feelings, which, as they made 
me despondent in a time of apparent national pros- 
perity, now cheer me in one which, though of stern 
trial, I will not be so much a coward as to call one 
of adversity. And I derive this encouragement first 
from the belief that the War itself, with all its 
bitterness, is, in the present state of the European 
nations, p^’oductive of more good thah evil; and, 
secondly, because I have more confidence than others 
generally entertain, in the justice of its cause. 

I say, first, because I believe the war is at pre- 
sent productive of good more than of evil. I will 
not argue this hardly and coldly, as I might, by 
tracing in past history some of the abundant evidence 
that nations have always reached their highest virtue , 
and wrought their most accomplished works, in times 
of straitening and battle; as, on the other hand, no 
nation ever yet enjoyed a protracted and triumphant 
peace without receiving in its own bosom ineradicable 
seeds of future decline. I will not so argue this 
matter; but I will appeal at once to the testimony 
of those whom the war has cost the dearest. I know 
what would be told me, by those who have suffered 
nothing; whose domestic happiness has been un- 
broken; whose daily comfort undistryrbed ; whose 
experience of calamity consists, at its utmost, in 
the incertitude of a speculation, the dearness of a 
luxury, or the increase of demands upon their fortune 
which they could meet fourfold without inconveni- 
ence. From these, I can well believe, be they pru- 
dent economists, or careless pleasure-seekers, the 
cry for peace will rise alike vociferously, whether in 
street or senate. But I ask their witness, to whom 
the war has changed the aspect of the earth, and 



358 THE TEACHERS OF TURNER [part iv 

imagery of heaven, whose hopes it has cut off like 
a spider’s web, whose treasure it has placed, in a 
moment, under the seals pf clav. Those who can 
never more see sunrise, nor watcti the climbing light 
gild the Eastern clouds, without thinking what graves 
it has gilded, first, far down behind the dark earth - 
line — who never more shall see the crocus bloom in 
spring, without thinking what dust it is ,that feeds 
the wild flowers of Balaclava. Ask their witness, 
and see if they will not reply that it is well with 
them, and wdth theirs; that they would have it no 
otherwise; would not, if they might, receive back 
their gifts of love and life, nor take again the purple 
of their blood out of the cross on the breastplate of 
England. Ask them : and though they should answer 
only with a sob, listen if it does not gather upon their 
lips into the sound of the old Seyton war-cry — ‘ S^t 
on. ’ 

And this not for pride — not because the names 
of their lost ones will be recorded to all time, as 
of those who held the breach and kept the gate of 
Europe against the North, as the Spartans did against 
the East; and lay down in the place they had to 
guard, with the like homo message, ‘ Oh, stranger, 
go and tell the English that wo are lying here, 
having obeyed their words ’; — ^not for this, but be- 
cause, also, they have felt that the spirit which has 
discerned them for eminence in sorrow — the helmed 
and sworded skeleton that rakes with its white 
fingers the sands of the Black Sea beach into grave- 
heap after grave-heap, washed by everlasting surf 
of tears — has, been to them an angel of other things 
than agony; that they have learned, with those 
hollow, undeceivable eyes of his, to see all the earth 
by the sunlight of deathbeds; — ^no inch-high stage 
for foolish griefs and feigned pleasures; no dream, 
neither, as its dull moralists told them ; — Anything 
but that ; a place of true, marvellous, inextricable 
sorrow and power; a question-chamber of trial by 
rack and fire, irrevocable decision recording con- 
tinually; and no sleep, nor folding of hands, among 



CHAP, xviii] THE TEACHEKS OF TURNER 359 

the demon-questioners; none among the angel- 
watchers, none among the men who stand or tail 
beside those hosts of God. They know now the 
strength of sacrifice, and that its flames can illumine 
as well as consume ; they are bound by new fidelities 
to all that they have saved — ^by new love to all for 
whom they have suffered; every affection which 
seemed to sink with those dim life-stains into the 
dust, has* been delegated, by those who need it no 
more, to the cause for which they have expired; 
and every mouldering arm, which will never more 
embrace the beloved ones, has bequeathed to them 
its strength and its faithfulness. 

For the cause of this quarrel is no dim, half- 
avoidable involution of mean interests and errors, as 
some would have us believe. There never was a 
great war caused by such things. There never can 
ne. The historian may trace it, with ingenious 
trifling, to a courtier’s jest or a woman’s glance; but 
ho does not ask — (and it is the sum of questions) — 
how the warring nations had come to found their 
destinies on the course of the sneer, or the smile. 
If they have so based them, it is time for them to 
learn, through suffering, how to build on other founda- 
tions; — for groat, accumulated, and most righteous 
cause, their foot slides in due time; and against the 
torpor, or the turpitude, of their myriads, there is 
loosed the haste of the devouring sword and the 
thirsty arrow. But if they have set their fortunes 
on other than such ground, then the war must be 
owing to some deep conviction or passion in their 
own lioarts — a conviction which, in resistless flow, 
or reckless ebb, or consistent stay, iS the ultimate 
arbiter of battle, disgrace, or conquest. 

Wherever there is war, there mufit be injustice on 
one side or the other, or on both. There have been 
wars which were little more than trials of strength 
between friendly nations, and in which the injustice 
was not to each other, but to the God who gave them 
life. But in a malignant war of these present ages 
there is injustice of ignobler kind, at once to God 



360 THE TEACHERS OF TURNER [part iv 

and man, which must be stemmed for both their 
sakes. It may, indeed, be so involved with national 
prejudices, or ignorances, that neither of the con- 
tending nations can conceive it as attaching to their 
cause; nay, the constitution of their governments, 
and the clumsy crookedness of their political dealings 
with each other, may be such as to prevent either 
of them from knowing the actual cause for which 
they have gone to war. Assuredly this is,^in a great 
degree, the state of things with us; for I noticed 
that there never came news by telegraph of the ex- 
plosion of a powder-barrel, or of the loss of thirty 
men by a sortie, but the Parliament lost confidence 
immediately in the justice of the war; reopened the 
question whether we ever should have engaged in it, 
and remained in a doubtful and repentant state of 
mind until one of the enemy’s powder-barrels blew 
up also; upon which they were immediately satisficed 
again that the war was a wise and necessary one. 
How far, therefore, the calamity may have been 
brought upon us by men whose political principles 
shoot annually like the leaves, and change colour at 
every autumn frost : — how loudly the blood that has 
been poured out round the walls of that city, up to 
the horse-bridles, may now be crying from the ground 
against men who did not know, when they first bade 
shed it, exactly what war was, or what blood was, 
or what life was, or truth, or what anything else was 
upon the earth; and whose tone of opinions touching 
the destinies of mankind depended entirely upon 
whether they were sitting on the right or left side of 
the House of Commons; — this, I repeat, I know not, 
nor (in all solemnity I say it) do I care to know. 
For if it be so, and the English nation could at the 
present period of its history be betrayed into a war 
such as this by the slipping of a wrong w^ord into 
a protocol, or bewitching into unexpected battle under 
the budding hallucinations of its sapling senators, 
truly it is time for us to bear the penalty of our base- 
ness, and learn, as the sleepless steel glares close 
upon us, how to choose our governors more wisely. 



CHAP, xviii] THE TEACHERS OF TURNER 361 

and our ways more warily. For that which brings 
swift punishment in war, must have brought slow 
ruin in peace; and those who have now laid down 
their lives for England, have doubly saved her; they 
have humbled at once her enemies and herself; and 
have done less for her, in the conquest they achieve; 
than in the sorrow that they claim. 

But it is not altogether thus : wo have not been cast 
into this fp^ar by mere political misapprehensions, or 
popular ignorances. It is quite possible that neither 
we nor our rulers may clearly understand the nature 
of the conflict ; and that we may be dealing blows in 
the dark, confusedly, and as a soldier suddenly 
awakened from slumber by an unknown adversary. 
But I believe the struggle was inevitable, and that 
the sooner it came, the more easily it was to be met, 
and the more nobly concluded. France and Eng- 
land are both of them, from shore to shore, in a 
state of intense progression, change, and experi- 
mental life. They are each of them beginning to 
examine, more distinctly than ever nations did yet. 
in the history of the world, the dangerous question 
respecting the rights of governed, and the responsi- 
bilities of governing, bodies; not, as heretofore, 
foaming over them in red frenzy, with intervals of 
fetter and straw crown, but in health, quietness, and 
daylight, with the help of a good Queen and a great 
Emperor: and to determine them in a way which, 
by just so much as it is more effective and rational, 
is likely to produce more permanent results than ever 
before on the policy of neighbouring States, and to 
force, gradually, the discussion of similar questions 
into their places of silence. To foroe it, — for true 
liberty, like true religion, is always aggressive or 
persecuted; but the attack is generally made upon 
it by the nation which is to be crushed, — by Persian 
on Athenian, Tuscan on Roman, Austrian on Swiss; 
or, as now, by Russia upon us and our allies : her 
attack appointed, it seems to me, for confirmation of 
all our greatness, trial of our strength, purging and 
punishment of our futilities, and establishment for 



362 THE TEACHERS OF TURNER [partiv 

ever, in our hands, of the leadership in the political 
progress of the world. 

Whether this its providential purpose be accom- 
plished, must depend on its enabling France and 
England to love one another, and teaching these, 
the two noblest foes that ever stood breast to breast 
among the nations, first to decipher the law of inter- 
national charities; first to discern that races, like 
individuals, can only reach their true* strength, 
dignity, or joy, in seeking each the welfare, and 
exulting each in the glory, of the other. It is strange 
how far we still seem from fully perceiving this. We 
know that two men, cast on a desert island, could 
not thrive in dispeace; we can understand that four, 
or twelve, might still find their account in unity; 
but that a multitude should thrive otherwise than by 
the contentions of its classes, or two multitudes hold 
themselves in anywise bound by brotherly law Ifb 
serve, support, rebuke, rejoice in one another, this 
seems still as far beyond our conception, as that 
clearest of commandments, ‘ Let no man seek his 
own, but every man another’s wealth is beyond our 
habitual practice. Yet, if once we comprehend that 
precept in its breadth, and feel that what we now 
call jealousy for our country’s honour, is, so far 
as it tends to other countries’ dishonour, merely 
one of the worst, because most complacent and self- 
gratulatory, forms of irreligion — a newly breathed 
strength will, with the newly interpreted patriotism, 
animate and sanctify the efforts of men. Learning, 
unchecked by envy, will be accepted more frankly, 
throned more firmly, guided more swiftly; charity, 
unchillod by* fear, will dispose the laws of each 
State, without reluctance to advantage its neighbour 
by justice to itself; and admiration, un warped by 
prejudice, possess itself continually of new treasure 
in the arts and the thoughts of the stranger. 

If France and England fail of this, if again petty 
jealousies or selfish interests prevail to unknit their 
hands from the armoured grasp, then, indeed, their 
faithful children will have fallen in vain; there will 



CHAP, xviii] THE TEACHEB8 OP TURNEB 363 

be a sound as of renewed lamentation along those 
Euxine waves, and a shaking among the bones that 
bleach by the mounds of Sebastopol. But if they fail 
not of this — ^if we, in our love of our queens and 
kings, remember how France gave to the cause of 
early civilization, first the greatest, then the holiest, of 
monarchsi; and France, in her love of liberty, re- 
members how we first raised the standard of Com- 
monweallfh, trusted to the grasp of one good and 
strong hand, witnessed for by victory; and so join 
in perpetual compact of our different strengths, to 
contend for justice, mercy, and truth throughout the 
world — who dares say that one soldier has died in 
vain? The scarlet of the blood that has sealed this 
convenant will be poured along the clouds of a new 
aurora, glorious in that Eastern heaven; for every 
sob of wreck-fed breaker round those Pontic preci- 
f)ices, the floods shall clap their hands betw^een the 
guarded mounts of the Prince-Angel; and the spirits 
of those lost multitudes, crowned with the olive and 
rose among the laurel, shall haunt, satisfied, the 
willowy brooks and peaceful vales of England, and 
glide, triumphant, by the poplar groves and sunned 
coteaux of Seine. 


^ Charlemajijno and St Lonis. 




APPENDIX 


I. Claude’s Tree-drawing 

The reader may not improbably hear it said, by persons who 
are incapable of maintaining an honest argument, and, there- 
fore, incapable of understanding or believing the honesty of 
an adversary, that I have caricatured, or unfairly chosen, the 
examples I give of the masters I depreciate. It is evident, in 
the first place, that I could not, if I were even cunningly dis- 
posed, adopt a worse policy than in so doing ; for the discovery 
of caricature or falsity in my representations, would not only 
mvalidate the immediate statement, but the whole book ; and 
Invalidate it in the most fatal way, by showing that all I had 
ever said about “truth was hypocrisy, and that in my own 
affairs 1 expected to prevail by help of lies. Nevertheless it 
necessarily happens, that in endeavours to facsimile any work 
whatsoever, bad or good, some changes are induced from the 
exact aspect of the original. These changes are, of course, 
sometimes harmful, sometimes advantageous; the bad thing 
generally gains ; the good thing always loses : so that I am 
continually tormented by finding, in my plates of contrasts, 
the virtue and vice I exactly wanted to talk about, eliminated 
from both examples. In some cases, however, the bad thing 
will lose also, and then I must eith(*r cancel the plate, or in- 
crease the cost of the work by preparing another (at a similar 
risk), or run the chance of incurring the charge of dishonest 
representation. I desire, therefore, very earnestly, and once 
for all, to have it understood that whatever I say in the text, 
bearing on questions of comparison, refers always to the 
original works; and that, if the reader has in his power, I 
would far rather he diould look at those works than at my plates 
of them; 1 only give the plates for his immediate help and 
convenience : and I mention this, with respect to my plate of 
Claude's ramification, because, if I have such a thing as a 
prejudice at all, (and, although 1 do not myself think I have, 
people certainly say so,) it is against Claude ; and T might, 
therefore, be sooner suspected of some malice in this plate 
than in others. But I simply gave the original engravings 
from the Liber Veritatis to Mr Le Keux, earnestly requesting 
that the portions selected might be faithfully copied ; and I 
365 



366 APPENDIX 

think he is much to be thanked for so carefully and success- 
fully accomplishing the task. The figures are from the 
following plates; 

No. 1. Part Of the central tree in No. 134 of the Liber Veritatds. 


2. From the largest tree 

„ 158 

S. Bushes at root of tree 

184 

4. Tree on the left 

183 

5. Tree on the left 

05 

G. li-ee on the left 

172 

7. Principal tree 


8. Tree on the right 

32 


If, in fact, any change be effected in the examples in this 
plate, it is for the better ; for, thus detached, they all look 
like small boughs, in which the faults are of little conse- 
■quence ; in the original works they are seen i.o he intended for 
largetrunks of trees, and the errors are therefore pronounced 
on a much larger scale. 

The plate of mediieval rocks (X) has bt)cm executed with 
much less attention in transcript, because the iJoinls there to 
be illustrated were quite indisputable, and the instances were 
needed merely to show the kind of thitu/ spoken of, not tlft 
skill of particular masters. The example from Leonardo was, 
liowever, somewhat carefully treated. Mr Cuff copied it 
accurately from the only engraving of the picture which, I 
believe, exists, and with which, therefore, 1 suppose the world 
is generally content. That engraving, however, in no respect 
seems to mo to give the look of the light behind Leonardo’s 
rocks ; so I afterwards darkened the rocks, and put some light 
into the sky and lily ; and tlie effect is certainly more like that 
of the picture than it is in the same portion of the old 
engraving. 

Of the. other masters represented in the plates of thi.s 
volume, the noblest, Tintoret, has assuredly suffered the most 
(Plate XVII) ; first, in my too hasty drawing from the original 
picture; and, secondly, through some accidintal errors of out-, 
line which occurred in the reduction to the size of the page ; 
lastly, and chiefly, in the withdrawal of the heads of the four 
figures underue;^h, in the shadow, on which the composition 
entirely depends. This last evil is unavoidable. It is quite 
impossible to make extracts from the great masters without 
partly spoiling every separated feature ; the very essence of a 
noble composition being, that none should bear separation from 
the rest. 

The plate from Raphael (XI) is I think, on the whole, satis- 
factory. It cost me much pains, as I had to facsimile the 
irregular form of every leaf; each being, in the original 
picterc, executed with a somewhat wayward pencil-stroke of 
vivid brown on the clear sky. 



APPENDIX 


367 


Of the other plates it would be tedious to speak in detail. 
Generally, it will be found that I have taken most pains to do 
justice to the masters of whom I have to speak depreciatingly ; 
and that, if there be calumny at all, it is always of Turner, 
rather than of Claude. 

The reader might, however, perhaps suspect me of ill-will 
towards Constable, owing to my continually introducing him 
for depreciatory comparison. So far from this being thecase, 
I had, as will be seen in various passages of the first volume, 
considerable# respect for the feeling with which he worked; 
but I was compelled to do harsh justice ii})ou him now, 
because Mr Leslie, in his unadvised and unfortunate rechauffe 
of the fallacious art-maxims of the last century, has sulfered 
his personal regard for Constable so far to prevail over his 
judgment as to bring him forward as a great artist, comparable 
in some kind with Turner. As Constable’s reputation was, 
even before this, most mischievous, in giving coimtenauce to 
the blotting and blundering of Modernism, I saw myself 
obliged, though unwillingly, to carry the suggested comparison 
^^oroughly out. 


II. German Phii.osophy 

The reader must have noticed that I never speak of German 
art, or German philosophy, but in depreciation. This, how- 
ever, is not because I cannot feel, or would not acknowledge, 
the value and power, within certain limits, of both ; but be- 
cause I also feel that the immediate tendency of the English 
mind is to rate them too highly ; and, therefore, it becomes a 
necessary task, at present, to mark what evil and weakness 
there are in them, rather than what good. I also am brought 
continually into collision with certain extravagances of the 
•German mind, by ray own steady pursuit of Naturalism as 
opposed to Itlealism ; and, therefore, I become unfortunately 
cognizant of the evil, rather than of the good ; which evil, so 
far as I feel it, I am bound to declare. AncLit is not to the 
point to protest, as the Chevalier Biinsrn and other German 
writers have done, against the expression of opinions respect- 
ing their philosophy by persons who have not profoundly or 
carefully studied it; for the very resolution to study any 
system of metaphysics profoundly, must be based, in any 
prudent man’s miiid. on some preconceived opinion of its 
worthiness to be studied; which opinion of German meta- 
physics the naturalistic English cannot be led to form. This 
IS not to be murmured .against— it is in the simple necessity 
of things. Men who have other business on their hands must 



368 


APPENDIX 


be content to choose what philosophy they have occasion for, 
by the sample j and when, glancing into the second volume of 
Hippolytus, we find the Chevalier Bunsen himself talking of a 
* finite realization of the infinite’ (a phrase considerably less 
rational than ‘ a black realization of white ’), and of a triad 
composed of God, Man, and Humanity i (which is a parallel 
thing to talking of a triad composed of man, dog, and caniue- 
ne-ss), knowing those expressions to be pure, definite, and 
highly finished nonsense, we do not in general trouble our- 
selves to look any farther. Some one will perHaps answer 
that if one always judged thus by the sample — as, for 
instance, if one judged of Turner’s pictures by the head of a 
figure cut out of one of them — very precious things might 
often be despised. Not, I think, often. If any one went to 
Turntir, expecting to learn figure-drawing from him, the 
sample of his figure-drawing would accurately and justly 
inform him that he had come to the wrong master. But if he 
came to be taught landscape, the smallest fragment of Turner’s 
work would justly exemplify his power. It may sometimes 
unluckily happen that, in such short trial, we strike upon ag,^ 
accidentally failing part of the thing to be tried, and then we* 
maybe unjust; but there is, nevertheless, in multitudes of 
cases, no other way of judging or acting; and the necessity of 
occasionally being unjust is a law of life, — like that of some- 
times stumbling, or being sick. It will not do to walk at 
snail’s pace all our lives for fear of .stumbling, nor to spend 
years in the investigation of eveiy thing which, by specimen, 
we must condemn. He who seizes all that he plainly dis- 
cerns to be valuable, and never is unjust but when he honestly 
cannot help it, will soon be enviable in his possessions, and 
venerable in his equity. 

Nor can I think that the risk of loss is great in the matter 
under discussion. I have often been told that any one who 
will read Kant, Strauss, and the rest of the German meta- 
physicians and divines, resolutely througli, and give his * 
whole strength to the study of them, will, after ten or twelve 
years’ labour, discover that there is very little harm in them ; 
and this I can w«ll believe; but I believe also that the ten or 
twelve years may be better spout; and that any man who 
honestly wants philosophy not for show, but for vse, and 
knowing the Proverbs of Solomon, can, by way of com- 
mentary, afford to buy, in convenient editions, Plato, Bacon, 

1 I am truly sorry to have to introduce such words in an apparently 
irreverent way. But it would be a guilty reverence which prevented 
us from exposing fallacy, precisely where fallacy was most dangerous, 
and shrank from unveiling an error, ju.st because tliat error existed in 
parlance respecting the moat solemn subjects to which it could 
I)Ossibly be attached. 



APPENDIX 


Wordsworth, CJarlyle, and Helps, will find that he has got as 
much as will be suffii^ient for him and his household during 
life, and of as good quality as need be. 

It is also often declared necessary to study the German 
controversialists, because the grounds of religion ‘ must be 
inquired into *. I am sorry to hear they have not been 
inquired into yet; but if it be so, there are two ways of 
pursuing that inquiry : one for scholarly men, who have 
leisure on their hands, b}*^ reading all that they have time to 
read, for and against, and arming themselves at all points for 
controversy with all persons ; the other — a shorter and 
simpler w'ay — for busy and practical men, who want merely 
to find out how to live and die. Now for the learned and 
leisurely men I am not writing ; they know what and how to 
read better than I can t dl them. For simple and busy men, 
concerned much with art, which is eminently a practical 
matter, and fatigues the eyes, so as to render much reading 
inexpedient, I am writing ; and such men 1 do, to the utmost 
of my power, dissuade from meddling with German books; 
^^ot because I fear inquiry into the grounds of religion, but be- 
cause the only inquiry which is jmsihle to them must be 
conducted in a totally different way. They have been brought 
up as Christians, and doubt if they should remain Christians. 
They cannot ascertain, by investigation, if tlie Bible be true ; 
but if it he, and Christ ever existed, and was God, then, 
certainly, the Sermon which He has permitt:^! for 1800 years 
to stand recorded as first of all His own teaching in the New 
Testament, must be true. Let them take that Sermon and 
give it fair practic^al trial: act out every verse of it, with no 
quibbling, nor explaining away, except the reduction of such 
evidently metaphorical expressions as ‘cut off thy foot’ 

‘ pluck the beam out of thine eye’, to their effectively practi- 
cal sense. Let them act out, or obey, every verse literally for 
a whole year, so far as they can — a year being little enough 
•time to give to an inquiry into religion ; and if, at the end of 
the year, they are not satisfied, and still need to prosecute the 
inquiry, let them try the German system if they choose. 


III. Plagiarism 

Some time after I had written the concluding chapter of 
this work, the interesting and powerful poems of Emerson were 
brought under my notice by one of the members of my class at 
the Working Men’s College. There is much in some of these 
poems so like parts of the chapter in question, even in turn of 
expression, that though I do not usually care to justify myself 



370 


APPENDIX 


from the charge of plagiarism, I felt that a few words were 
necessary in this instance. 

I do not, as aforesaid, justify myself, in general, because I 
know there is internal evidence in my work of its originality, 
if people care to examine it ; and if they do not, or have not 
skill enough to know genuine from borrowed work, my simple 
assertion would not convince them, especially as the charge of 
plagiarism is hardly ever made but by plagiarists, and persons 
of the unhappy class who do Aot believe in honesty hut on 
evidence. Nevertheless, as my work is so much oat of doors, 
and among pictures, tliat I have time to read few modem 
books, and am therefore in more danger than most people of 
repeating, as if it were new, what others have said, it may be 
well to note, once for all, that any such apparent plagiarism 
results in fact from my writings being more original than I 
wish them to be, from my having worked out my wholb 
subject in unavoidable, but to myself hurtful, ignoraifce of the 
labours of others. On the other hand, I should be very sorry 
if I had not been continually taught and influenced by the 
writers whom I love; and am quite unable to say to whaj^ 
extent my thoughts have been guided by Wordsworth, Carlyle, 
and Helps; to whom (with Dante and George Herbert, in 
olden time) I owe more than to any other writers ; — most of 
all, perhaps, to Carlyle, whom I read so constantly, that, with- 
out wilfully setting myself to imitate him, I find myself per- 
petually falling into his modes of exi^ression, and saying many 
things in a ‘ quite other and, I hope, stronger, way, than I 
should have adopted some years ago ; as also there are things 
which I hope are said more clearly and simply than before, 
owing to the influence upon me of the beautiful quiet English 
of^ Helps. It would be both foolish and wrong to struggle to 
cast off influence.s of this kind ; for they consist mainlj in a 
real and healthy help ; — the master, in writing as in painting, 
showing certain methods of language which it would be, ridi- 
culous, and even affected, not to employ, when once shown ; 
just as it would have been ridiculous in Bonifazio to refuse to 
employ Titian’s way of laying on colour, if he felt it the best, 
because he hadfUot himself discovered it. There is all the 
difference in the world between this receiving of guidance, or 
allowing of influence, and wilful imitation, much more, plagi- 
arism ; nay, the guidalice may even innocently reach into local 
tones of thought, and must do so to some extent ; so that I 
find Carlyle’s stronger thinking colouring mine rontinually ; 
and should be very sorry if I did not; otherwise I should 
have read him to little purpose. But what I have of my own 
is still all there, and, I believe, better brought out, by far, 
than it would have been otherwise. Thus, if we glance over 
the wit and satire of the popular writers of the day, we shall 



371 


APPENDIX 

find that the niattner of it, so far as it is distinctive, is always 
owing to Dickens ; and that out of his first exquisite ironies 
branched innumerable other forms of wit, viirjung with the 
disposition of the writers; original in the matter and substance 
of them, yet never to have been expressed as they now are, but 
for Dickens. 

Many people will suppose that for several ideas in the 
chapters on Landscape I was indebted to Humboldt’s Kosmoa^ 
and Hewitt’s Rural Scenery, I am indebted to Mr Howitt’s 
book for much pleasure, b^ for no suggestion, as it was not 
put into my hands till the chapters in question were in type. 
I wish it ht^ been ; as I should have been glad to have taken 
farther note of the landscape of Theocritus, on which Mr 
Howitt dwells with just delight. Other parts of the book 
will be found very suggestive and helpful to the reader who 
cares to pursue the subject. Of Humboldt’s Kosmos I 
heard much talk when it first came out, and looked through it 
cursorily; but thinking it contained no material (connected 
with my subject) i which I had not already possessed myself 
of, I have never since referred to the work. I may be 
mistaken in my estimate of it, but certainly owe it absolutely 
^nothing. 

It is also often said that I borrow from Pugin. I glanced at 
Pugin’s Contrasts once, in the Oxford architectural reading- 
room, during ansidle forenoon. His ‘ Remarks on Articles in 
the Rambler ’ were brought under my notice by some of the 
reviews. I never read a word of any other of his works, not 
feeling, from the style of his architecture, the smallest 
interest in his opinions. 

I have so often spoken, in the preceding pages, of Holman 
Hunt’s picture of the Light of the World, that I may as well, 
in this place, glance at the envious charge against it of being 
plagiarized from a German print. * 

It is indeed true that there was a painting of the subject 
before ; and there were, of course, no paintings of the 
Nativity before Raphael’s time, nor of the Last Supper before 
^ieonJirdo’s, else those masters could have laid no claim to 
originality. But what was still more singular (the verse to be 
illustrated being, ‘ Behold, I stand at thg door^ and knock 
the principal figure in the antecedent picture was knocking at 
a door, knocked with its right hand, and had its face turned to 
the spectator ! Nay, it was even robed in a long robe, down to' 
its feet. All these circumstances were the same in Mr Hunt’s 
picture ; and as the chances evidently were a hundred to one 
that if he had not been helped to the ideas by the German 
artist, be would have represented the figure as 7iot knocking at 


1 iSco the Fourth Volume. 



372 


APPENDIX* 

any door, as tuhxing its back €o ’the spectator', an<l &s dressed 
in a short robe, the plagiarism was considered as demonstrated. 
Of course no defence is possible in such a case. All I can say 
is, that I shall be sincerely grateful to any unconscientious 
persons who will adapt a few more German prints in the same 
manner. 

Finally, touching plagiarism in general, it is to be remem- 
bered that all men who have sense and feeling are being 
continually helped: they are taught by every person whom 
they meet, and enriched by everything that falls in their way. 
The greatest is he who has been oftenest aided ; and, if the 
attainments of all human minds could be traced'»to their real 
sources, it would be found that the world had been laid most 
under contribution by the men of most original power, and 
that every day of their existence deepened their debt to their 
race, while it enlarged their gifts to it. The labour devoted 
to trace the origin of any thought, or any invention, will 
usually issue in the blank conclusion tliat there is nothing new 
under the sun : yet nothing that is truly great can ever be 
altogether borrowed ; and h^e is commonly the wisest, and is 
always the happiest, who receives simply, and without envioirs 
question, whatever good is offered him, with thanks to ivs' 
immediate giver. 


KND OF von. 111. 


Richard Clay de Sons, Limited, London and Bungay.